ebook img

Knowledge: The Philosophical Quest in History PDF

313 Pages·2014·1.692 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Knowledge: The Philosophical Quest in History

SK Knowledge tN e vO eW The Philosophical Quest in FL uE l History lD e rG E Steve Fuller ISBN 978-1-8446-5817-6 ,!7IB8E4-gfibhg! www.routledge.com(cid:15)aninformabusiness Knowledge Thetheoryofknowledge,orepistemology,isoftenregardedasadrytopicthatbears little relation to actual knowledge practices. This book aims to correct this by showing the roots, developments and prospects of modern epistemology from its beginnings in the nineteenth century to the present day. Contemporary epistemology is shown to draw on the insights of a wide range of disciplines. Philosophy has always been concerned with how we balance aspiration, belief, experience and knowledge. Science has come to represent a very highly pri- vileged knowledge, whilst recent insights from psychology and sociology have questioned how knowledge is acquired and structured. Meanwhile, theology has shaped the quest for knowledge in ways which have only relatively recently become separate from more secular knowledge systems. The book offers readers a very broad, cross-disciplinary, and historically-informed assessment of the ways in which humanity has, and continues to, pursue, question, contest, expand and shape knowledge. Steve Fuller is Auguste Comte Professor of Social Epistemology at the University of Warwick. He is the author of twenty books, including The Knowledge Book and Science. Page Intentionally Left Blank Knowledge The philosophical quest in history Steve Fuller Firstpublished 2015 byRoutledge 2ParkSquare, MiltonPark,Abingdon, OxonOX144RN andbyRoutledge 711ThirdAvenue,NewYork,NY10017 Routledge isanimprint oftheTaylor &FrancisGroup,aninformabusiness ©2015SteveFuller TherightofSteveFullerto beidentifiedastheauthor ofthiswork hasbeenassertedin accordancewithsections77and78oftheCopyright, DesignsandPatentsAct1988. Allrightsreserved.Nopartofthisbookmaybereprintedorreproducedorutilized in anyformorbyanyelectronic,mechanical, orothermeans, nowknownorhereafter invented,includingphotocopyingandrecording,orinanyinformationstorageorretrieval system,withoutpermission inwritingfromthepublishers. Trademarknotice: Productorcorporatenames maybetrademarks orregistered trademarks,andareusedonlyforidentificationandexplanationwithoutintenttoinfringe. British LibraryCataloguing inPublication Data Acataloguerecordfor thisbookisavailablefromtheBritishLibrary. LibraryofCongress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Acatalogrecordhasbeenapplied for. ISBN:978-1-84465-817-6 (hbk) ISBN:978-1-84465-818-3 (pbk) Typeset inGillSans byCenveoPublisherServices Contents List of tables vii Acknowledgements viii Introduction: is there a problem of or with knowledge? 1 1 Epistemology as cognitive economics 19 Social epistemology as the art of cognitive management, 19 . Two kinds of cognitive economy for social epistemology, 22 . The history of epistemology as a struggle over cognitive economy, 25 . The problem of the economic use of knowledge already produced, 29 . Why did our ancestors seem to know so much more than we know now?, 34 . Projecting the future of social epistemology: the proactionary imperative, 38 2 Epistemology as divine psychology 41 The divine origins of intellectual life, 41 . Secularizing the sacred mind: the centrality of theodicy, 46 . Theism by other means: sociology’s secular problematic, 54 . Why naturalism is too conservative to explain science, 59 . David Hume: naturalist philosopher of diminished expectations, 63 . The need for theism to explain science, 69 . The awkwardness of natural theology in the secular world, 74 . Intelligent design: a “Left Creationist” affirmation of science, 86 . Darwinism’s own anti-humanist theodicy, 90 . Recap: the Creationist Left’s challenge to the science–religion nexus, 96 3 Epistemology as psychology of science 102 In the beginning the psychologist was the self-conscious scientist, 102 . The genealogy of validity: from the bank to vi Contents the lab bench, 106 . The need for psychology of science to improve the conduct of science, 117 . Conclusion: how scientific creativity went from being abundant to scarce, 121 4 Epistemology as philosophy of science 130 By misunderstanding Kuhn, we misunderstand our own times, 130 . Kuhn’s legacy of prescriptive/descriptive confusion, 134 . Popper’s (pre-)challenge to Kuhn and Kuhn’s anti-rationalist response, 141 . Kuhn’s contemporary legacy: the naturalization of consensus in science, 149 . The problem of positioning Popper on his own terms, 154 . The key to Popper: the psychologist who never really left the lab, 161 . The problem of assessing Popper’s philosophical fortunes, 166 5 Epistemology as sociology of science 169 In search of the “will to science”: from religious inspiration to remunerated research, 169 . Science and expertise: natural bedfellows or mortal enemies?, 177 . Expertise as site for normative recession in analytic social epistemology, 181 . Expertise as site for normative recession in science and technology studies, 187 . Learning from the past to redeem a normatively “fuller” social epistemology, 192 . The challenge ahead: the legacies of Kuhn and Latour as obstacles, 202 6 Epistemology as counterfactual historiography 210 The complementarity of freedom and determinism in the modern world-view, 210 . Freedom and determinism as a problem of historical perspective, 220 . Possible worlds as the micro-structure of freedom and determinism, 232 . The normative stakes of a flexibly revisable history, 242 . Giving the past back its future: the ultimate test of “giving voice”, 250 Conclusion: redeeming epistemology from the postmodern condition 262 Bibliography 280 Index 301 Tables 1 Social epistemology as (1) epistemology and (2) sociology. 6 2 The existential horizons of social epistemology. 15 3 The two philosophical traditions before cognitive economics. 26 4 The two philosophical traditions after cognitive economics. 29 5 The realm of the knowable. 35 6 Philosophy of science or for science? 145 7 The two modern world-views. 211 8 The two modal logics of history. 225 9 The epistemic rudiments of time travel. 228 Acknowledgements I must acknowledge the support of those who over the past fifteen years have provided the conditions and criticism necessary to develop the arguments in these pages: Elisabeth Arweck, Babette Babich, Jesus Zamora Bonilla, James Robert Brown, Jim Collier, Manuel Crespo, Jean- Pierre Dupuy, Mark Erickson, Greg Feist, Bob Frodeman, Tom Glick, Jim Good, Michael Gorman, Mathew Guest, Morteza Hashemi Madani, Ian Jarvie, Byron Kaldis, Ilya Kasavin, Noretta Koertge, Veronika Lipinska, Juan Vicente Mayoral, Martin Medhurst, Jaume Navarro, Greg Radick, Paul Roth, Raphael Sassower, Sergio Sismondo, Nick Turnbull, Stephen Turner, Immanuel Wallerstein. I must also thank my long- suffering editor Tristan Palmer at Acumen. This book is dedicated to Emilie Whitaker, someone whose generosity of mind and spirit can merely be gestured at in a work such as this. I would like to acknowledge the Institute of Philosophy (Department of Social Epistemology) of the Russian Academy of Sciences and the Russian Science Foundation for funding the project on “Social Philosophy of Science” (grant #14-18-02227) which was made in support of some of this work. Introduction of with Is there a problem or knowledge? Humans are gods in the making. An actual deity may be guiding or otherwise enabling the process, but even if that turns out to be false, Homo sapiens has distinguished itself from other animals most remarkably by acting as if having been touched by the divine. As a result, we live in the future perfect – that is, the time when our ideas will have come to be realized. In this respect, it is telling that induction becomes a significant “problem of knowledge” only in the final quarter of the nineteenth cen- tury, once Thomas Henry Huxley popularizes David Hume as a precursor of Charles Darwin’s view that we are animals conditioned by experience to believe that the future will be like the past. Before that time, only self- avowed “traditionalists”, such as Bishop Richard Whately, would have accorded the past such strictly epistemic weight. And notwithstanding the continued popularity of the “problem of induction” in analytic phi- losophical circles, we have come to value the future over the past in quite radical ways – albeit resulting in enormous distress, including incredible violence to various groups of people at various times, as well as the rest of the natural world. And even if postmodernism has made it no longer fashionable to believe in the idea of progress, we still hold personal sacrifice in high esteem while pathologizing those who “discount the future too heavily”, as the economists gingerly say. Compared with other animals, we seem to take our imaginative projections much more ser- iously than the evidence of experience would require – or even advise. Only an Abrahamic God could be sanguine about humanity’s track record based on its having adopted such a mind-centred, future-oriented view of the world. Of course, theologians may be correct that this is simply because we are so much like the deity that “People of the Book” have envisaged – one in whose “image and likeness” we were created. After all, the Abrahamic deity creates through dictation, something to which humans aspire, be it understood as the imposition of will, delivery on a promise or, more recently, the execution of a programme. Against this backdrop, “knowledge” is a troublesome concept: It draws attention to just how far short we still fall from divine perfection, even assuming that it is a reasonable aspiration. Thus, philosophers – in the

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.