ebook img

Kant, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche on Motivation, Agency and the Formation of a Higher Self PDF

302 Pages·2011·1.29 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Kant, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche on Motivation, Agency and the Formation of a Higher Self

Anti-Utilitarians: Kant, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche on Motivation, Agency and the Formation of a Higher Self by Ryan Stuart Beaton A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctorate of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto © Copyright by Ryan Stuart Beaton 2011 Anti-Utilitarians: Kant, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche on Motivation, Agency and the Formation of a Higher Self Ryan Stuart Beaton Doctorate of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2011 Abstract This thesis examines the moral philosophical commitments that Kant, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche advance in their respective oppositions to utilitarianism. Though not always under that title, all three reject the claim that promoting happiness is the ultimate end that we pursue, or ought to pursue, through moral principles and values. Kant, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche see this rejection reflected in human nature itself. Each develops a distinctive conception of 'higher self,' or of higher purposes already belonging, in some sense, to each of us, in accordance with which we ought to shape our character. Self-formation, not the mere pursuit of happiness (whether our own or that of others), is thus our true moral project. I focus on each philosopher's account of agency and motivation as the locus in which this view of morality is developed, highlighting the differences that emerge from the details of their respective accounts. This thesis shows that a tight relation between cognition and motive feeling is central, though in different ways, for Kant, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche, to the motivational structure of those actions through which we develop moral character. According to Kant, recognition of being bound by the ii moral law (our 'practical cognition' of freedom) is indissolubly linked to the feeling of respect for it, which in turn is explicable only through such recognition. For Schopenhauer, the 'intuitive cognition' that our existence as distinct individuals is illusory is the feeling of compassion. Nietzsche radically expands this point, arguing that, in every act of will, the motive feeling and guiding cognition are uniquely linked. Only a superficial grasp of human motivation supports the idea that pleasure and pain are the common motive forces underlying all our actions. The inner conflict in human nature, the creative tension in self-formation, is not, for Nietzsche, that between a uniquely moral form of motivation and a 'lower' instrumental pursuit of pleasure. Rather, this inner tension, expressed most strikingly and distressingly in extreme ascetic and guilt-ridden strands of Christian morality, is the product of a complex historical conflict between two different modes of behavioural selection – our evolutionary development and the processes of socialization. iii Acknowledgments I would like to thank my supervising committee for their invaluable help and support. It has been a great pleasure to work with my supervisor, Amy Mullin. I’m deeply grateful for her ever prompt and insightful comments and suggestions, for many illuminating discussions, and most of all for her investment in and attention to this project. I could not have asked for more in a supervisor. To Paul Franks, on my supervising committee, I feel privileged to have had the opportunity to take a number of his graduate seminars, both officially and unofficially, during my years in the PhD program. To Rebecca Comay, also on my supervising committee, I’m forever grateful for an engaging Nietzsche reading course in the summer of 2006, which launched this project. I would also like to thank the entire faculty and staff from the Department of Philosophy, and fellow graduate students during my time here, for a wonderfully stimulating research environment. A special thanks to Margaret Opoku-Pare for her friendly and gracious help, with all problems big and small. Finally, I would like to thank SSHRC and the University of Toronto for the financial support that allowed me to pursue this research. iv Table of Contents Abstract..................................................................................................ii Acknowledgments.................................................................................iv Abbreviations........................................................................................vi Introduction............................................................................................1 Chapter 1: The Kantian Highest Good and Competing Conceptions of Freedom.........................16 Chapter 2: Schopenhauer on Kant, and the Pure Knowing Subject...68 Chapter 3: Evolution and Socialization: Nietzsche on Conflicting Modes of Behavioural Selection...................150 Chapter 4: Nietzsche on the Will to Truth.........................................236 Conclusion.........................................................................................282 Bibliography.......................................................................................292 v Abbreviations Kant, Immanuel Unless otherwise indicated, citations to Kant are from the standard Akademie collection: Königlichen Preußischen (later Deutschen) Akademie der Wissenschaften (ed.), 1900-, Kants gesammelte Schriften, Berlin: Georg Reimer (later Walter De Gruyter). I use the following abbreviations for Kant's individual works. G – Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten (Groundwork to the Metaphysics of Morals) KpV – Kritik der praktischen Vernunft (Critique of Practical Reason) KrV – Kritik der reinen Vernunft (Critique of Pure Reason) KU – Kritik der Urteilskraft (Critique of the Power of Judgment) Religion – Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft (Religion within the Bounds of Bare Reason) Schopenhauer, Arthur Unless otherwise indicated, citations to Schopenhauer are from: Arthur Schopenhauer, Sämtliche Werke, ed. by Arthur Hübscher, Eberhard Brockhaus Verlag, Wiesbaden, 1972. I use the following abbreviations for Schopenhauer's individual works. BM – Über die Grundlage der Moral (On the Basis of Morality) VW – Über die vierfache Wurzel des Satzes vom zureichenden Grunde (On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason) WWV – Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung 1. Band (The World as Will and Representation volume 1) WWV v2 – Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung 2. Band (The World as Will and Representation volume 2) Nietzsche, Friedrich Unless otherwise indicated, citations to Nietzsche are from: Nietzsche Werke: Kritische Gesamtausgabe, eds. G. Colli and M. Montinari, de Gruyter, Berlin 1967- 2006. I use the following abbreviations for Nietzsche's individual works: AC – Der Antichrist (The Antichrist) vi FW – Die fröhliche Wissenschaft (Gay Science) GD – Götzen-Dämmerung (Twilight of the Idols) GM – Zur Genealogie der Moral (On the Genealogy of Morals) JGB – Jenseits von Gut und Böse (Beyond Good and Evil) M – Morgenröte (Daybreak) Z – Also sprach Zarathustra (Thus Spoke Zarathustra) vii 1 Introduction This thesis looks at Kant, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche making their stand against utilitarianism. In broadest possible terms, utilitarianism, as a moral philosophy, holds that promoting general happiness is the ultimate goal and guiding principle of morally good action. Utilitarianism takes as its foundation the rock solid empirical fact that, barring tragic or bizarre circumstances, every human being has a strong and abiding interest in her own personal happiness. This interest is not held constantly in mind. Clearly we don't keep personal happiness uninterruptedly before our eyes, in making everyday decisions and in generally going about our lives. But if we imagine someone taking a broad look at his life – in particular, at his long-term goals, at the important relationships in his life, at his major personal commitments and potential life-changing decisions – and telling us that personal happiness doesn't play a central role in shaping his deliberations about what to do with his life, we're likely to think he's lying to us or to himself, or seriously ill. This obviously is not a matter of being selfish – that will depend on the particular ends that an individual thinks make up personal happiness – but simply a central element of our existence as agents who have to make countless decisions about how to live our lives, from the most trivial daily choices to life-long commitments. In fact, the interest in personal happiness is so central an element of our agency that we would be hard-pressed to make any sense of human agency without it. It seems a reasonable view, then, that any minimally cooperating and mutually respecting group of people will share a common interest in their general happiness, i.e., in the sum of the personal happiness of individuals in the group. For the philosopher, there are, of course, many questions that spring to mind here. What exactly 2 do we mean by personal happiness? Is there some objective list of necessary or sufficient elements of personal happiness? Or is it essentially a subjective matter of individuals' inclinations and sources of pleasure? Is it simply the aggregate of an individual's wants or desires? Is that tautologous? How does personal happiness relate to general happiness? Can the personal happiness of individuals – 'happinesses'? – be summed? Does the interest of a group, or of society – or perhaps of humanity at large – in promoting general happiness really follow from the interest of each individual in her own personal happiness? Do we not need moral principles precisely to constrain the individual's interest in personal happiness, moral principles that therefore seem external to, at least potentially opposed to, the interest in personal happiness? These are interesting and important questions. But they are not my questions in this thesis. The resistance utilitarianism encounters in Kant, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche doesn't turn on the details with which we flesh out the basic utilitarian intuition1 – and I'm interested here precisely in the resistance of Kant, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche to the basic utilitarian intuition. Their resistance is interesting, in the first instance, for the form it does not take. Historically, the main opposition to the basic utilitarian intuition, at least insofar as that opposition was articulated on moral grounds, came from religious commitments, or from (more or less closely related) traditional considerations of social and political authority. So long as faith in God grounds the moral world view, so long as the social order determines right and wrong, deliberations about moral duty are not likely to start with the interest of the individual in personal happiness. However, absent strong religious authority and entrenched traditional social and political norms, 1 Mainly for this reason, I'm putting off, very briefly, addressing the fact that Kant and Schopenhauer do not directly oppose anything called 'utilitarianism.' Nonetheless, both explicitly oppose promotion of general happiness as an ultimate moral ideal, i.e., they oppose the basic utilitarian intuition discussed here. Moreover, their rejection of what they call 'eudaemonism,' is closely related to their rejection of utilitarian thinking, and in the context of more general discussion, as in this introduction, I will use 'utilitarianism' and 'eudaemonism' roughly interchangeably, though this may seem especially strange to any reader who thinks of eudaemonism primarily in terms of ancient ethical theories. I take up these points in chapters 1 and 2. 3 reasons for opposing utilitarianism are far from obvious. If there is no divine or transcendent moral authority, no social order clearly sanctioned by nature, then we seemingly have nowhere else to turn for guiding principles of choice and action than to the kinds of desires and aspirations that we have both as individuals and as a society. Again, there are many difficult questions lurking here for the utilitarian, which she can only answer by articulating detailed conceptions of individual and general happiness, and of the relation between them. But it seems eminently plausible that we would want to adopt principles that offer something like maximum satisfaction of the desires and aspirations in our deliberations about morality. At the most general level, then, we will want principles that promote harmony between the individual's interest in her personal happiness and her interest in general happiness, and that define as right, or morally good, those actions that tend to increase general happiness, and thereby the happiness of individuals. In other words, we will adopt core utilitarian principles. Yet Kant, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche all reject this general approach to questions of moral value and duty, and none of them looks to religion or to the weight of tradition to justify his rejection. They do not object to this or that element or nuance of the utilitarian view I've just presented it. Each of them insists that this way of approaching morality, or more generally, of approaching the question as to how we should live our lives (and the endless choices, big and small, that this involves), is fundamentally wrong. The burden, it seems to me, is on them to justify their rejection of utilitarianism, on whose side lie the basic moral intuition and considerations outlined above. There is something provocative, if not offensive, about the denial of the basic utilitarian moral intuition. Undoubtedly, a sense of having been provoked or offended runs through much of the criticism directed at the moral philosophies of Kant, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche. I confess that I find much of what Kant, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche have to say in opposition to utilitarianism appealing. My primary aim in writing this thesis has been to articulate just what they

Description:
different ways, for Kant, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche, to the motivational .. complete happiness once we have fully adapted to life in society.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.