ebook img

Isonomia: Studien zur Gleichheitsvorstellung im griechischen Denken PDF

153 Pages·1971·15.519 MB·German
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Isonomia: Studien zur Gleichheitsvorstellung im griechischen Denken

DEUTSCHE AKADEMIE DER WISSENSCHAFTEN ZU BERLIN Institut für griechisch-römische Altertumskunde Arbeitsgruppe für hellenistisch-römische Philosophie Veröffentlichung Nr. 9 ISONOMIA Studien zur Gleichheitsvorstellung im griechischen Denken herausgegeben von JÜRGEN MAU UND ERNST GÜNTHER SCHMIDT . Unveränderter Nachdruck der 1. Auflage AKADEMIE-VERLAG • BERLIN in Arbeitsgemeinschaft mit ADOLF M. HAKKERT • AMSTERDAM 1971 Erschienen im Akademie-Verlag GmbH, 108 Berlin, Leipziger Stratte 3—4 Copyright 1964 by Akademie-Verlag GmbH Offsetdruck und buchbinderische Weiterverarbeitung: VEB Druckerei „Thomas Müntzer", 582 Bad Langensalza/DDR Bestellnummer: 2053/9 • ES 7 M EDV 751 824 5 INHALT Vorbemerkungen V GREGORY VLASTOS 'foovo/iia nohuxr] 1 SALOMO LURIA Zwei Demokrit-Studien 37 1. Ov fiäXXov und laovoftla 37 2. 'Avayxaiov und avftßeßrptöc 46 CARLO DIANO Mallon Hetton e Isonomia 55 PHILLIP DE LACT Colotes' First Criticism of Democritus 67 LOREN MACKINNEY The Coneept of Isonomia in Greek Medicine 79 WILLY THEILER Einheit und unbegrenzte Zweiheit von Plato bis Plotin 89 ERNST GÜNTHER SCHMIDT Das Gedicht des Ausonius de ratione librae und der Isorrhopie- Gedanke ill Autoren- und Stellenregister 129 VORBEMERKUNG Im letzten Jahrzehnt erschienen mehrere Studien zum Isonomie-Begriff, z. B. G. Vlastos, Isonomia, AJP 64, 1953, 337-366; G. Freymuth, Eine Anwendung von Epikurs Isonomie-Gesetz, Philol. 98,1954, 101—115; Ch. Mugler, L'isonomie des Atomistes, Revue de Philol. 30, 1956, 231-250. Die Fortsetzung der Dis- kussion in Form einer Aufsatzsammlung erhebt nicht den Anspruch, jeder Einzelheit des Isonomie-Themas gerecht zu werden, berücksichtigt aber alle drei Gebiete, in denen der Begriff eine Rolle spielte: Politik, Philosophie und Medizin. Weitere Spielarten des Gleichheitsgedankens sind in die Erörterung einbezogen. Während die Diskussion von laovofiia stets verhältnismäßig wenigen Stellen der antiken Literatur galt — mehreren Bezeugungen des Wortes im politischen Bereich stehen im philosophischen im wesentlichen nur die Belege bei Cicero (de nai. deor. I 19, 50; 39, 109) und Philon, im medizinischen gar nur das Alkmaion-Fragment B 4 Diels gegenüber —, öffnet sich hier ein weites Feld, und man mag nach der gedanklichen Verknüpfung der Beiträge unter- einander fragen: Gregory Vlastos, der seine frühere Veröffentlichung ergänzt, sucht den Iso- nomie-Begriff zunächst in seinem Ursprungsgebiet auf, im politischen Denken der klassischen Zeit Griechenlands. Salomo Luria zeigt in der ersten seiner beiden Demokrit-Studien die Verbindung, die der Isonomie-Gedanke bei seiner Über- nahme durch die Philosophie mit dem ov fiätäov-Prinzip einging. Die zweite Abhandlung erläutert im Rahmen eines Themas aus der Frühgeschichte der Logik ebenfalls Anwendungen des ov ^¿¡AAor-Begriffs, und dem gleichen Prinzip ist auch ein wesentlicher Teil des Beitrages von Phillip De Lacy gewidmet. Eine philosophiegeschichtliche Skizze der Entwicklung von den Eleaten bis zur Aufstellung der epikureischen Isonomie-Lehre gibt Carlo Diano. Loren MacKinney untersucht den Gebrauch von laovofiia und Ausdrücken verwandten Inhalts in der medizinischen Literatur. Weitere Aspekte des Gleichheitsgedan- kens werden in den restlichen Beiträgen erörtert. Das Begriffspaar taov — avutov hatte eine wichtige Funktion in Piatons Vorlesung „Über das Gute" und be- gegnet in den Texten, in denen die Gedanken dieser Vorlesung bewahrt bzw. abgewandelt wurden; es entspricht der Aktualität des Themas in der gegen- wärtigen Forschung, wenn Willy Theiler in seinem Beitrag weit über eine spezielle Behandlung des Gleichheitsgedankens hinausgreift. Der letzte Aufsatz VI Vorbemerkungen schließlich sucht ein spätes Zeugnis, ein Ausonius-Gedicht, zu jenen älteren Gleichheitsvorstellungen in Verbindung zu setzen, denen z. T. schon die vorauf- gehenden Beiträge galten. Allen, die sich durch Gastbeiträge am vorliegenden Band beteiligten, sei für ihre Mitarbeit gedankt. April 1963 Jürgen Mau Ernst Günther Schmidt z. Z. Berkeley, Calif. Berlin VORBEMERKUNG ZUM NACHDRUCK Die Beiträge werden in unveränderter Form hiermit erneut vorgelegt, nur eine Anzahl von Druckfehlern sind beseitigt. Die Vorbemerkung zur 1. Auflage schloß mit dem Dank an die Mitarbeiter. Um zwei von ihnen trauern wir: Loren MacKinney und Salomo Luria verstarben bald nach dem ersten Er- scheinen des Bandes. August 1970 Jürgen Mau Ernst Günther Schmidt Göttingen Jena IZONOMIA nOAITIKH GREGORY VLASTOS (Princeton University) That isonomia was so closely associated with democracy that it even served as a name for that constitution before demokratia came into use is scarcely a recent thesis'. But it was brought to the attention of scholars with renewed force shortly after the War by three able essays, published within four years of one another: "Demokratia", by A. Debrunner (1947)2; "Cleisthenes and the Development of the Theory of Democracy at Athens", by J. A. 0. Larsen (1948)1; "Origins of Democracy", by V. Ehrenberg (1950)But even before the third of them appeared, emphatic dissent from this thesis was voiced by a distinguished historian, the late A. W. Gomme. In a brief review of the Fest- schrift in which Larsen's paper had been published, he wrote in his charac- teristically lucid and forthright manner: "Isonomia, I still think, means a con- stitutional regime, whether oligarchic or democratic, the rule of order, the contrary of the irresponsible tyranny; a term that might have been used by both parties that were opposed to Hippias.5" Gomme gave no evidence at the time to support this pronouncement; he was reserving it doubtless for the second volume of his Historical Commentary on Thucydides6. So I took no account of his opinion in a paper on "Isonomia" I published in 19537. I did allude in it to the logically related view that isonomia meant no more than 'equality before the law.' This had enjoyed considerable currency at one time. But I had thought that strong, indeed conclusive, reasons against it had been 1 To go back no further than Wilamowitz (Aristoteles und Athen II, Berlin, 1893, p. 319): he thinks isonomous in the Harmodius skolion, „wofür schon Aristophanes demokratia gesagt haben würde", shows that the skolion can be „schwerlich viel jünger" than the tyrannicide. 2 In Festschrift für E. Ti&che (Berne, 1947), pp. llff. 3 In Essays in Political Theory presented to O. H. Sabine (Ithaca, 1948). (I shall refer to this essay by Larsen hereafter by the abbreviation "CD"). 4 In Historia 1 (1950), pp. 515ff. (I shall refer to this hereafter by "OD"). 5 CR 03 (1949), p. 125. 6 Oxford 1956, pp. 109-110, 347, 379-380, 542.1 shall refer to it hereafter by "Comm. II." Lest my controversial differences with it give anyone a false idea of my esteem for this work and for its author, let me say onoe for all that I consider this one of the finest achievements of English-speaking classical scholarship in our century. 7 AJP 64 (1953), pp. 337-66. 1 shall refer to this paper hereafter by title only. 2 GREGORY VLASTOS already given, notably by Ehrenberg in his RE article on "IsonomiaReferr- ing to Ehrenberg then for this point, I felt free to devote my paper to other matters. Rereading it now, nearly ten years later, I feel that one of the major items of unfinished business left over from it is the issue raised by Gomme's dissent. For this concerns not a detail but the fundamentals of our conception of the role of isonomia in the political thought of the classical period. If it means what Gomme thought it did, much of what has been written on the subject by others as well as myself is false or at least misleading. How widely his view is now shared I have no way of knowing. Nor would this be of any great consequence. In such a case numbers count for nothing. What does matter is that such a view could have been held, with such depth of conviction, by a scholar who, in addition to his great learning, had a critical intelligence of the first order. From this I can only infer that full justice has yet to be done to the other side of the controversy — that either the thesis has not been stated with the greatest attainable precision or that the full weight of the evidence it commands has not yet been added to the balance. I have no confidence that I can make up for all this here. But I can at least try to bring out some things which do not seem to have been said, or said as fully as they should be. Moreover I am only too glad to have this opportunity to remedy one of the main deficiencies of "Isonomia": its treatment of the apparent counter-examples, oligarchia isono- mos in Thucydides (3. 62. 3), Isocrates' application of it to Sparta (Panath. 178) and Plato's to the aristocratic Athens of the Menexenus (239a). The second and, still more, the third of these I handled in a brusque, short-winded, almost short-tempered, way, for which I now beg leave to make amends. This I shall do in Part Two, whose longest section (III) I shall devote to the passage in the Menexenus, which presents fascinating problems all of its own. In Part One I shall deal with Herodotus and, much more briefly, with the earlier texts. Part One In the Debate in Herodotus (3. 80. 2—82. 5) the constitution "which has2 the fairest of all names, isonomia", is identified with democracy in the most positive and unmistakeable way. It is that which exists where "the management of public affairs is made common"3 and the power is given to the masses;4" 1 RE Suppl. VII, cols. 293ff., at cols. 295ff. 2 Note that the speaker is not suggesting that he is undertaking to give it this name, but that this is the name it already has. 3 iç fitaov . . . xaTa&eïvai rà 7iQr¡yfiaxa, 3. 80. 2. (Here, and occasionally hereafter, I allow myself a rather free translation of the Greek, in order to make my text read more smoothly.) 4 ¿ç TÓ nXrfôoç . . . tpégeiv TO xgdroç, 3. 81. 1. 'Iaovofiia nohxtxij 3 where "the masses rule"1, and do so through the characteristic devices of the democratic polis: magistrates are appointed by lot2 and their official acts are subject to the euthyna3; proposals on matters of public policy are referred for decision to the assembly4. From the omission of demokratia throughout the whole of the Debate we may infer that the word had not yet come into use5, when this text was written by Herodotus or his source6. For the Debate goes on for several paragraphs, offering repeated opportunities for the use of abstract names for each of the three constitutions under discussion. The writer makes ample use of such names for the other two: he uses mounarchie four times, tyrannis once, oligarchie five times. If he had demokratia he would surely have 1 itkfj&OQ ÀGXOV, 3. 80. 6 ; drjfiov . . . SQXOVTOS, 82. 4. 2 naXco /lèv ÒQXIIs &QXei' 3. 80. 6. One of the hallmarks of democracy: Plato, Rep. 557a, Polit. 289d; and cf. the reference to Laws 759b, at p. 18, n. 1, below. 3 vnev&vvav óè ÒQxty &QXel> 3- 80. 6. Cf. ¿vev&vvqi, of the tyrant, 80. 3. 4 fiovAeu/iara óè ndvra ig TÓ xotvòv àvag>égei, 3. 80. 6. The one major democratic institution to which Otanes makes no explicit reference is the participation of the demos in the administration of justice. This is doubtless implied. Cf. e. g. Arist., Pol. 1298 a 4ff. : the sovereign power deliberates ((¡ovXevófievov) about judicial matters (negi &avarov xai <pvyfjg xai ÓTjftevaeiog) no less than about war, alliances, etc., and the audit of magistrates. 5 Cf. CD, p. 6. The same conclusion is reached on independent (purely linguistic) grounds by A. Debrunner, op. cit. The earliest epigraphical occurrence of the word would be in the Athenian decree concerning Colophon (ca. 460 B. C.) 1612 15, line 37 : xai Sefio[xgaTÌav ov xaraXvaai], if the restoration is sound; it is retained in B. D. Meritt, H. T. Wade-Gery, and F. McGregor, The Athenian Tribute Lists (Princeton, 1939—53), Vol. 2, p. 69, and is apparently endorsed by M. Ostwald, "Athenian Legislation Against Tyranny", TAPhA 86 (1955), pp. 103 ff., at p. 113, n. 51. 6 I mention the possibility that Herodotus was drawing on an earlier source, (which, if true, would strengthen my argument for the early currency of isonomia as a name for democracy) but put no weight on it, for lack of evidence. For a survey of the literature and a judicious conclusion see K. Wiist, Politisches Denken bei Herodot (Diss., Munich, 1935), pp. 47 ff. Sophistic influence on Herodotus is generally admitted (especially during his residence in Athens before he joined her Panhellenic colony at Thurioi: in this connection it is extremely likely that he knew Protagoras, who took a part in draf- ting the legislation for the colony [Heracleides Pont. ap. Diogenes Laertius 9.50]). There is good reason to think that at 3.108 Herodotus is echoing a Protagorean source (cf. my "On the Pre-History in Diodorus", AJP 67 [1946], pp. 51ff., at pp. 56-57). Wo may suspect that he is doing the same thing in this Debate, but lack the materials to prove this. Hence we had best speak of it as a conjecture (so Larsen, CD, p. 4.). T. B. L. Webster, Political Interpretations in Greek Literature, Manchester, 1948, p. 49, cites the Debate as a "genuine memory of Protagoras" on the ground that it represents monarchy as another form of government "beside tyranny, democracy, and oligarchy." If monarchy were so represented, the indebtedness to Protagoras would still be conjectural: we have no evidence that he invented or even expounded this idea. In any case, as Wiist points out (op. cit., pp. 57 and 59), it is the same form of government, one-man rule, which is attacked by Otanes and Megabyzus, and defended by Darius. This is clear from the nomenclature : Otanes uses IIOVVAQXAW (80. 2) and TVQOVVOV (80. 4) interchangeably, and uses the horrors of tyranny to discredit jiowagxtT) at 80. 3.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.