ebook img

Introduction to Mathematics (Barnes & Noble Library of Essential Reading) PDF

158 Pages·2004·1.76 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Introduction to Mathematics (Barnes & Noble Library of Essential Reading)

Table of Contents Title Page Copyright Page Introduction CHAPTER I - THE ABSTRACT NATURE OF MATHEMATICS CHAPTER II - VARIABLES CHAPTER III - METHODS OF APPLICATION CHAPTER IV - DYNAMICS CHAPTER V - THE SYMBOLISM OF MATHEMATICS CHAPTER VI - GENERALIZATIONS OF NUMBERS CHAPTER VII - IMAGINARY NUMBERS CHAPTER VIII - IMAGINARY NUMBERS(Continued) CHAPTER IX - COORDINATE GEOMETRY CHAPTER X - CONIC SECTIONS CHAPTER XI - FUNCTIONS CHAPTER XII - PERIODICITY IN NATURE CHAPTER XIII - TRIGONOMETRY CHAPTER XIV - SERIES CHAPTER XV - THE DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS CHAPTER XVI - GEOMETRY CHAPTER XVII - QUANTITY BIBLIOGRAPHY ENDNOTES INDEX SUGGESTED READING Introduction and Suggested Reading Copyright © 2005 by Barnes & Noble Books Originally published in 1911 This edition published by Barnes & Noble Publishing, Inc. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission of the Publisher. Cover Design by Stacey May 2005 Barnes & Noble Publishing, Inc. ISBN 0-7607-6588-X eISBN : 978-1-41143142-3 Printed and bound in the United States of America 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 2 INTRODUCTION ALFRED North Whitehead’s Introduction to Mathematics is one of the most charming books ever written about the queen of the sciences. In it the great British mathematician and philosopher gives a delightful and intellectually stimulating exposition of mathematical concepts, the history of their development, and the application thereof. Expertly written with razor-sharp clarity by a brilliant man, Introduction to Mathematics is filled with precious insights and lively prose. A required reading for all those who never understood how anyone could find the subject even remotely interesting, this little gem of a book demonstrates the immense pedagogical talent of its author. While it can be easily adopted as a basis for a short class or tutorial for high-school students or science and humanities undergraduates, laymen wishing to re-familiarize themselves with the fundamental ideas of mathematics will find it more enjoyable than any other contemporary introductory book in the field. The youngest of four children of an Anglican vicar, Whitehead (1861-1947)— one of the most interesting and imaginative scholars of our era—showed no sign of the genius that he was later in life. As a scholar, his academic interests spanned mathematics, science, and metaphysics, all of which were thoroughly and carefully treated by him with a unique and original style. Guided by the intellectual honesty and the personal touch that is so characteristic of his writings, only few follow Whitehead in the rarely taken path that combines mathematics, physics, and philosophy. His ingenuity and creativity shall remain an inspiration to generations of scholars. After winning two scholarships for studying mathematics in Trinity College, Cambridge, Whitehead was offered a fellowship as an assistant lecturer there. Despite a poor publication record, Whitehead displayed remarkable teaching skills, as readers of Introduction to Mathematics will surely appreciate, and was soon promoted to lecturer. The shift of emphasis in his career, from teaching to publishing, came with his marriage in late 1890. It was also marked by his decision to renounce Christianity. He himself stated that the biggest factor in his becoming an agnostic was the rapid developments in science; particularly his view that Newton’s physics was false. It may seem surprising to many that the correctness of Newton’s physics could be a major factor in deciding anyone’s religious views. However, one has to understand the complex person that Whitehead was and, in particular, the interest which he was developing in philosophy and metaphysics. Whitehead left Cambridge in 1910 and went to London, and then to Harvard, where he was the chair of the philosophy department until his retirement. Apart from his metaphysics, he is perhaps best known for his collaboration with Bertrand Russell, who came to Cambridge in 1890 as an undergraduate and was immediately spotted by the talented lecturer. A decade later, the student and the master began collaborating on one of the most ambitious projects in the philosophy of mathematics, Principia Mathematica (1910), which was an attempt to supply mathematics with rigorous logical foundations. When the first volume of this monumental work was finished, Whitehead and Russell began to go their separate ways. Perhaps inevitably, Russell’s anti-war activities during World War I, in which Whitehead lost his youngest son, also led to something of a split between the two men. Nevertheless, they remained on relatively good terms for the rest of their lives. It was then that Whitehead turned his attention to the philosophy of science. This interest arose out of the attempt to explain the relation of formal mathematical theories in physics to their basis in experience, and was sparked by the revolution brought on by Einstein’s GTR, to which he had developed an alternative in another famous book, The Principle of Relativity (1922). Most of Whitehead’s work prior to 1911 was intended exclusively for a professional audience, namely mathematicians. This was especially evident in his Treatise on Universal Algebra (1898) and in Principia Mathematica, but also in minor publications where Whitehead had mathematical physicists in mind. Introduction to Mathematics, however, was written for a broader readership. Although he no longer could assume such intense mathematical familiarity as with his previous readers, and although the subjects of higher mathematics (such as mathematical logic, group theory, analytic, non-Euclidian, and projective geometries, and integral calculus) could not be dealt with here, mathematics cognoscenti will surely agree that Whitehead’s exposition of mathematics is anything but superficial. Rather, we find him profoundly dealing afresh with philosophical, historical, and applied mathematics, insofar as these topics had already appeared in his earlier works on pure mathematics. Whitehead declares in the beginning of Introduction to Mathematics that “[t]he object of the following chapters is not so much to teach mathematics, but to enable the students from the very beginning of their course to know what the science is about, and why it is necessarily the foundation of exact thought as applied to natural phenomena.” The book fulfills this promise by intertwining three basic problems that had occupied Whitehead in his work up to that point: the question about the applicability of mathematics to the physical world; its essence, or nature ; and its unity, generality, and internal structure. The unique position of mathematics is that it is apparently unconstrained by physical reality: Unlike physical laws, mathematical theorems need no empirical ratification. Their discovery, however, is equally “emotionally stirring,” as, says Whitehead, the discovery of the Western shore by Columbus, or the Pacific Ocean by Pizzaro. By and large, the development of mathematical concepts is driven by the innate human curiosity and by the pleasure derived from the exercise of the human faculties. But these concepts are widely applied in modern physics, and it is this successful applicability that was always at the center of attention of theoretical physicists and philosophers. The Physics Nobel Laureate Eugene Wigner, for one, called this applicability “a miracle” in his celebrated paper “The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences” (1960), and Whitehead, a trained mathematician, has chosen this “miracle” to be one of the threads that unite the chapters of Introduction to Mathematics. The question about the relation of mathematics to physics is an old one. One may even say that the mere possibility of mathematical physics is a major continental divide between rationalism and empiricism—the two famous philosophical schools that constitute early modern philosophy from Descartes to Kant. Interestingly, none of the “traditional” philosophies of mathematics (e.g., formalism, intuitionism, logicism) ever made an especially serious attempt to explain why mathematics works when applied to the world or even gave much of a sign that they could offer such an explanation. In contrast, this question must have occupied Whitehead since the beginning of his scientific career. His dissertation on Maxwell’s electromagnetic field theory as well as his first two scientific publications on special problems of the hydrodynamics of incompressible fluids testify to his strong awareness to the longstanding debate on the possibility of mathematical physics. As Christoph Wassermann—a contemporary German Whitehead scholar—remarks, it may also explain why Whitehead devotes so much attention to questions concerning the methods and principles of applying mathematical ideas to the phenomena of nature, and why he sees himself obliged to write that “all science as it grows to perfection becomes mathematical in its ideas.” Whitehead’s analysis of the applicability of mathematics to the physical world involves a threefold distinction between symbolism and interpretation, between variables and form, and between mathematical ideas and mathematical correlations. Formal as this analysis is, Whitehead, in his unique style, portrays matters in their most humane: “It was an act eminently characteristic of the age that Galileo, a philosopher, should have dropped the weights from the leaning tower of Pisa. There are always men of thought and men of action; Mathematical physics is the product of an age which combined in the same men impulses to thought with impulses to action.” The “miraculous” applicability of mathematics to the physical world is conceived as such because of the unique nature of mathematics itself. This nature, according to Whitehead, is abstract in character: It is the fact that mathematics “.... deals with properties and ideas which are applicable to things just because they are things, and apart from any feelings, or emotions, or sensations in any way connected with them.” Not surprisingly, says Wassermann, whose research aims to establish a continuity in Whitehead’s work, Whitehead had been engaged with this abstract character more than two decades prior to Introduction to Mathematics. This preoccupation had found an exact establishment in Whitehead’s monumental Principia Mathematica, where he and Russell aimed to show that the concepts thus far regarded as basic to mathematics, e.g., numbers or geometrical points, were not that basic at all, nor constituted by our intuition of nature, but could be deduced from the axioms of mathematical logic. It is noteworthy that even in this new foundational level, the axioms and definitions of formal logic could be formulated without any direct reference to the content of assertions, thereby assuring complete independence from any particular context in which they were applied. In connection with the abstract nature of mathematics Whitehead specifies three concepts that unite all mathematical disciplines, while using a somewhat personal, religious analogy: “These three notions of the variable, of form, and of generality, compose a sort of mathematical trinity which preside over the whole subject. They all really spring from the same root, namely from the abstract nature of the science.” Of these three, the notion of the variable is the most fundamental. In Whitehead’s earlier works it is defined in the context of the calculus of

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.