ebook img

Interpretations and Causes: New Perspectives on Donald Davidson’s Philosophy PDF

269 Pages·1999·7.826 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Interpretations and Causes: New Perspectives on Donald Davidson’s Philosophy

INTERPRETATIONS AND CAUSES SYNTHESE LIBRARY STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Managing Editor: JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Boston University Editors: DIRK VAN DALEN, University of Utrecht, The Netherlands DONALD DAVIDSON, University of California, Berkeley THEO A.F. KUIPERS, University of Groningen, The Netherlands PATRICK SUPPES, Stanford University, California JAN WOLENSKI, Jagiellonian University, Krakow, Poland VOLUME 285 INTERPRETATIONS AND CAUSES New Perspectives on Donald Davidson's Philosophy Edited by MARIO DE CARO Universita Roma Tre. Italy SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. A C.I.P. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-90-481-5283-4 ISBN 978-94-015-9227-7 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-015-9227-7 Printed Oil acid-free paper All Rights Reserved © 1999 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1999 Softcover reprint ofthe hardcover 1st edition 1999 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner. TABLE OF CONTENTS Preface vii MARIO DE CARO I Davidson in Focus DONALD DAVIDSON I Interpretation: Hard in Theory, Easy in Practice 31 PART I. LANGUAGE, METAPHYSICS, AND MIND ERNEST LEPORE I Davidson and Understanding Language 47 NEIL TENNANT I Radical Interpretation, Logic, and Conceptual Schemes 71 TED A. WARFIELD I Donald Davidson's Freedom 95 SANDRO NANNINI I Physicalism and the Anomalism of the Mental 101 PAOLO LEONARDI I Anomalous Monism 117 ANTONIO RAINONE I Thirty-five Years after" Actions, Reasons, and Causes": What Has Become of Davidson's Causal Theory of Action? 125 SIMONE GOZZANO I Davidson on Rationality and Irrationality 137 PART II. EXTERNALISM ROSARIA EGIDI I "Cred'io ch'ei credette ch'io credesse ... ". What basis for belief? 153 PETER LUDLOW I First Person Authority and Memory 159 EV A PICARDI I Sensory Evidence and Shared Interests 171 MARCIA CAVELL I Owning One's Mind 187 v VI TABLE OF CONTENTS RAFFAELLA DE ROSA / Is There a Problem about Davidson's Externalism vis a-vis His Holism? 201 AKEEL BILGRAMI / Internalism and Scepticism 217 NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS 251 INDEX OF NAMES 253 INDEX OF SUBJECTS 257 PREFACE This volume traces its origins to spring, 1992, when Donald Davidson delivered a series of lectures in Rome, and a conference dedicated to his philosophy was organized by Rosaria Egidi at the Department of Philosophy of the Universita Roma Tre. Originally, this book was to consist of the proceedings of that conference; for several reasons, however, some years passed before the project was actually started. As a consequence, the list of the contributors of the present volume only partially resembles the list of speakers attending the Rome conference - and, of course, the essays published here are different from the ones that were read on that occasion. I wish to thank Rosaria Egidi for her helpful suggestions and constant support on this project. I am particularly grateful to Cesare Cozzo, for his valuable comments on the introductory essay I wrote for this volume, and I would also like to thank Ned Block, Francesco Ferretti, Ernie Lepore, Giacomo Marramao, Eva Picardi, Roberto Pujia, Hilary Putnam, Patricia Sayre, and Ted (Fritz) Warfield, for the profitable talks concerning one or other of the issues I have discussed in that essay. To Portia Prebys and Gus Rancatore I am grateful for having patiently edited the texts. Finally, I am happy to specially thank Donald Davidson, both for his generous support during the whole period in which this volume was prepared, and for the enlightening conversations I had with him when I was working on his philosophy for my doctoral dissertation. My introductory essay was written during summer, 1998, while I was spending an academic year at Harvard University, as a Fulbright Visiting Scholar. My stay there was made possible by two fellowships, granted by the Fulbright Commission for Cultural Exchange and by the Universita Roma Tre. For this, I am most grateful to both these institutions. MARIO DE CARO vii MARIO DE CARO DAVIDSON IN FOCUS Insofar as the notion of systematic philosophy can make sense in the analytic world, Donald Davidson is a systematic philosopher. While he has never directly written about some of the most fundamental branches of philosophy, as the classic systematic philosophers used to do (he has never discussed ethical or political issues, for example), Davidson's fundamental contributions to many fields, such as the philosophy of language and metaphysics, epistemology and the theory of action, the philosophy of mind and the theory of explanation form a complex, integrated whole in which any single part is interdependent on the others. This holistic feature of Davidson's philosophy gives us clear evidence of its systematic character - besides being a major source of its notorious difficulty. However, in his quite formidable, but remarkably original philosophical system, two notions play a fundamental role: interpretation and causation. Over the years, Davidson's philosophy has more and more assumed the form of an investigation of the possibility, the modalities, the requisites and the import of interpretation. At the beginning, Davidson only considered the adoption of the interpretative stance as a promising methodological prospect for the philosophy of language: Like many others. I wanted answers to such questions as "What is meaning?" and became frustrated by the fatuity of the attempts at answers I found in Ogden and Richard. Charles Morris. Skinner and others. So I substituted another question which I thought might be less intractable: What would it suffice an interpreter to know in order to understand the speaker of an alien language. and how could he come to know it? (Davidson I 994a. p. 126). Over the last three decades, however, the relevance of interpretation for Davidson's philosophy became much greater. In this light, it can now be said. without exaggerating, that Davidson's philosophy as such has assumed a third person point of view, that it has become nothing less than a philosophy ex parte interpretis (so that today Davidson is the philosopher of interpretation in the analytic world, in the same sense in which Hans-Georg Gadamer and Paul Ricoeur are the philosophers of interpretation in the contemporary Continental philosophy). In particular, Davidson has unceasingly reflected on the so-called radical interpretation (the situation in which the interpreter does not have any previous knowledge of the speaker's language and mental states). How important radical interpretation has become in Davidson's view is shown by the following quotation. 2 MARIO DE CARO This is the process of radical interpretation. There is no further court of appeal, no impersonal objective standard against which to measure our own best judgement of the rational and the true. (Davidson 1994b, p. 232). In a nutshell, Davidson has come to the conclusion that mutual interpretation is an indispensable requisite for language and thought, and a necessary condition for acquiring the concepts of truth, objectivity, reality. Davidsonian analyses have also shown that in the accounts of (radical) interpretation another theoretical notion plays an essential role: the notion of causality. As interpreters, in fact, we cannot in general fix what someone means independently of what he bel ieves and independently of what caused the belief... [W]e can't in general first identify beliefs and meanings and then ask what caused them. The causality plays an indispensable role in determining the content of what we say and believe. (Davidson 1993, p. 317). This shows that causality plays a fundamental role in Davidson's conception of language and thought. But causality is not a neutral notion. Philosophers have held many different opinions about it, and Davidson himself, for many years, has reflected deeply on causality and connected issues. However, to be exact, he has never cared much about the most typical philosophical questions regarding this topic (can one give an analysis of this notion in terms of necessary and/or sufficient conditions? Could the reference to counterfactual conditionals help in finding such an analysis? Is there such a thing as "backward causation"?). Even so, Davidson has done much to clarify this concept. He has presented a classic analysis of the logical form of singular causal statements (Davidson 1967); advocated a sharp distinction between causal relations, concerning events, and causal explanations, concerning sentences (Davidson 1963); expounded on a very influential causal conception of action (Davidson 1963, 1987); defended the so-called "nomological conception of causality", according to which every singular true causal statement relating two events is backed by a strict (i. e., physical) law that covers those events, when they are adequately described (Davidson 1967, 1995); supported the thesis that while psychology and the other "special sciences" cannot help referring to causal concepts,1 mature physics eliminates the causal notions from its vocabulary (Davidson 1987). In short, the notions of interpretation and causality have played a pivotal role in the development and the achievements of Davidsonian reflection. Most of the essays in this volume will discuss these two notions at length, with the aim of contributing to their clarification - both from a general point of view and as regards the philosophy of Donald Davidson. DA VIDSON IN Focus 3 I. LANGUAGE AND INTERPRETABILITY Many of Davidson's greatest contributions to the philosophical debate of the last decades are connected with the philosophy of language. He introduced the seminal notion of "theory of meaning" for a language;2 proposed an influential model for such a theory in the shape of a Tarskian theory of truth for L that an interpreter could use to understand the utterances of a speaker of that language;] argued that the notion of language (as it has been traditionally meant) is conceptually subordinated to the notion of idiolect;4 offered enlightening analyses of fundamental linguistic notions, such as those of truth, reference, meaning, metaphor.5 In his paper in this volume ("Davidson and Understanding Language"), Ernest Lepore discusses two very basic questions that concern a fundamental assumption of Davidson's philosophy of language, i.e., the idea that by developing an adequate semantic theory we could obtain a satisfying (philosophical) account of linguistic comprehension. More specifically, these two questions come to mind: (I) Are semantic theories for natural languages (or for the idiolects spoken by particular speakers) adequate models of linguistic comprehension? (2) If the semantic theories merely model linguistic comprehension (assuming they do), what can we learn from them? Even if some philosophers are skeptical, if not utterly pessimistic about the possibility of answering "yes" to the first query, many authors - most of whom have been directly inspired by Davidson -, think that semantic theories (that specify truth conditions or satisfaction conditions for a language L) can correctly describe (or model) the linguistic competence of an interpreter, i.e., the interpreter's ability to understand the utterances of another speaker. However, arguably the second query is philosophically more basic. In fact, most of the authors believe that in understanding language, ordinary speakers do not use any metalinguistic (semantic) theory; in this view, linguistic comprehension does not amount to any propositional knowledge at all (Fodor 1987; Schiffer 1987). Davidson himself is very careful in saying that his theory of meaning only aims at modeling the competence of the real interpreter, without claiming anything about the empirical modalities of interpretation. Thus, to Dummett, who accused him of having inappropriately attributed the (propositional) knowledge of a theory of meaning to empirical interpreters, Davidson replies: I do not think I have ever conflated the (empirical) question how we actually go about understanding a speaker with the (philosophical) question what is necessary and sufficient for such understanding. I have focused on the latter question not because I think it brings us close to the psychology of language learning and use, but because I think it brings out the philosophically important aspects of communication while the former tempts us to speculate about arcane empirical matters that neither philosophers nor psychologist know much about... I don't think we normally understand what others say by consciously reflecting on the question what they mean, by appealing to some theory of interpretation, or by summoning up what we take to be the relevant evidence. (Davidson I 994c, p. 3 [my italics])."

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.