Interactive Wittgenstein SYNTHESE LIBRARY STUDIESINEPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC,METHODOLOGY,ANDPHILOSOPHYOF SCIENCE Editors-in-Chief: VINCENT F. HENDRICKS, University of Copenhagen, Denmark JOHN SYMONS, University of Texas at El Paso, U.S.A. Honorary Editor: JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Boston University, U.S.A. Editors: DIRK VAN DALEN, University of Utrecht, The Netherlands THEO A.F. KUIPERS, University of Groningen, The Netherlands TEDDY SEIDENFELD, Carnegie Mellon University, U.S.A. PATRICK SUPPES, Stanford University, California, U.S.A. JAN WOLEN´ SKI, Jagiellonian University, Krako´w, Poland VOLUME 349 For further volumes: http://www.springer.com/series/6607 Interactive Wittgenstein Essays in Memory of Georg Henrik von Wright Editedby Enzo De Pellegrin 123 Dr.EnzoDePellegrin [email protected] ISBN978-1-4020-9908-3 e-ISBN978-1-4020-9909-0 DOI10.1007/978-1-4020-9909-0 SpringerDordrechtHeidelbergLondonNewYork (cid:2)c SpringerScience+BusinessMediaB.V.2011 Nopartofthisworkmaybereproduced,storedinaretrievalsystem,ortransmittedinanyformorby anymeans,electronic,mechanical,photocopying,microfilming,recordingorotherwise,withoutwritten permissionfromthePublisher,withtheexceptionofanymaterialsuppliedspecificallyforthepurpose ofbeingenteredandexecutedonacomputersystem,forexclusiveusebythepurchaserofthework. Printedonacid-freepaper SpringerispartofSpringerScience+BusinessMedia(www.springer.com) Preface WhenGeorgHenrikvonWrightdiedinhisnativetownofHelsinkion16June 2003,aged87,heleftbehindarichandvariedlegacyofscholarlyachievements. Apartfromtherenownhehadattainedforhisworkinphilosophicallogicand asaquintessentialContinentalthinkeronculturaltopics,thepolyglotFinnof Scottish descent had earned the esteem of philosophers and scholars around the globe for his wide-ranging efforts to make the philosophical thought of LudwigWittgensteinavailabletoaninterestedpublic.AsafriendofWittgen- stein’s, his successor as Professor of Philosophy at Cambridge University and one of the original legatees of his literary estate, von Wright played a crucial partincompilingandorganizingthevastbodyofWittgenstein’smanuscripts andtypescripts.This,initself,wasnominorfeat,forwhatisknownsimplyas “theNachlass”amongexpertsturnedouttobeageographicallyscatteredset of interrelated texts. In an effort to tame this abundance, von Wright devised a simple classificatory framework and created an annotated catalogue, both ofwhichremaininusebyspecialiststoday,servingasindispensableguidesto the corpus of Wittgenstein’s philosophical writings. VonWrightwasalsodeeplyinvolvedinextractingfromtheNachlass many of the books through which Wittgenstein’s philosophy has reached a broader philosophical audience. Among the volumes he edited and co-edited are Re- marks on the Foundations of Mathematics,Notebooks 1914–1916,Culture and Value, Zettel, On Certainty, Notes on Logic, and four volumes of remarks on the philosophy of psychology. But von Wright not only helped open up a wide new field of inquiry, now known as Wittgenstein Studies, and define its borders through his edito- rial work. He also helped us place Wittgenstein’s work in the context of the philosopher’s life by producing an early memoir and by publishing, in collab- oration with Brian McGuinness, Wittgenstein’s correspondence with, among others, Bertrand Russell, G. E. Moore and Frank Plumpton Ramsey. More- over,thecarefullyresearchedaccountsheprovidedofthetangledtextualhis- tory of Wittgenstein’s early masterpiece, the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, V VI Preface and the posthumously published Philosophical Investigations are considered classics in the field to this day. Early on, von Wright took strides to make the material basis of his schol- arlyandeditorialworkaccessibletootherspecialists.Heopenedhiscollection ofcopiesfromtheNachlass toacountlessnumberofvisitorsatthephilosophy department at the University of Helsinki. Working alongside Norman Mal- colm, von Wright supervised the production of a set of microfilms, which, in duplicated form, would remain the primary resource for scholarly research on Wittgenstein’sphilosophyforseveraldecadesuntiltheWittgensteinArchives at the University of Bergen and Oxford University Press released the results of many years of steadfast efforts to present text and images of the Nachlass in machine-readable form on CD-ROM. This venture, too, received crucial support from von Wright. TohonorthememoryofGeorgHenrikvonWrightandhismanifoldcontri- bution to the study of Wittgenstein’s lifework, the present volume assembles essays by experts in the field. Its main title derives from the unique focus many of these essays provide on the philosophical significance of Wittgen- stein’s real and presumed interactions with—and of his reactions to—other thinkers, including his former self, for the development of his thought. The first three contributions concern nature and scope of Wittgenstein’s philosophicalandpersonalinteractionswiththeGermanphilosopherandlogi- cianGottlobFrege,asrelatedchieflythroughlettersandcardsthatFregehad addressedtotheyoungphilosopherbetweentheyearsof1914and1920.Itwas duringthisperiodthatWittgensteinservedonthesideoftheCentralPowers during World War I and composed his seminal Tractatus. Frege’s dispatches tothefrontlineandhisletterstotheunpublishedauthorafterhisreturnfrom war and captivity are rendered here in the original German with a modern English translation en face, which was jointly undertaken by the late Burton Dreben and by Juliet Floyd. The one-sided correspondence reflects Frege’s admiration for the unflinching soldier’s ability to keep up scientific work un- der conditions of hardship. But it also contains stridently worded criticism of a typescript version of the Tractatus, which Frege had received in 1919. In addition, as Floyd, who also provides a prefatory note and an indispensable scholarly apparatus, points out in a companion essay entitled “Interpretive Themes”, Frege’s letters record his response to criticism Wittgenstein had lodged about Frege’s paper “Thoughts” in the half of their correspondence that is now missing. Drawing on her own research on the correspondence between Frege and Wittgenstein, Floyd puts the mutual criticisms into per- spectives and speculates on the extent to which these criticisms may have played a part in the abrupt termination of their interaction. The theme of influence, or lack thereof, is the starting point for Eran Guter’sexplorationofWittgenstein’sthoughtonmusicandmusicallanguage. In his essay “A Surrogate for the Soul: Wittgenstein and Schoenberg”, Guter challenges a widespread assumption, arguing that Wittgenstein and the Aus- trian composer Arnold Schoenberg had little in common beyond their shared Preface VII culturalheritage,overlappingsocialcirclesinfin-de-si`ecleViennaandtheno- toriety each of them had attained in his respective domain in the first half of the twentieth century. Guter combines a vivid account of Wittgenstein’s aesthetic inclinations and the intellectual influences that may have reinforced them with a survey of various philosophical statements by Wittgenstein on music,musicalmeaningandlanguage.GuteralsoattemptstoformaWittgen- steinian response to Schoenberg’s dodecaphonic language and to answer the question as to why Wittgenstein and Schoenberg arrived at very different ideas about contemporary music and the music of the future. Inhisessay“TheCrashofthePhilosophyoftheTractatus:TheTestimony ofWittgenstein’sNotebooksinOctober1929”,JaakkoHintikkadescribesthe central features of what he takes to be Wittgenstein’s own reassessment of Tractarian doctrines in the years of 1929 and 1930. Building on conclusions in his earlier interpretive work on Wittgenstein, Hintikka focuses on a small number of entries to Wittgenstein’s philosophical diaries and other sources that he takes to reflect a momentous shift in Wittgenstein’s conception of language. It is this shift, Hintikka argues, that brings about an abrupt and lasting change in Wittgenstein’s thinking and radically transforms his stance on a wide range of philosophical questions. Besides providing a translation of the relevant passages from the Nachlass, Hintikka examines some of the methodological issues arising from the shift of 1929. The shift in thought that David Pears has in mind in his contribution to this volume, which is entitled “Linguistic Regularity” and a different ver- sion of which appears in his book “Paradox and Platitude in Wittgenstein’s Philosophy” (Oxford University Press, 2006), is of another sort altogether. It pertains to basic differences Pears perceives in the ways Wittgenstein treats philosophical questions about linguistic meaning, and in particular linguistic regularity, in the Tractatus and in his later writings, such as the Philosophi- cal Investigations. Pears assumes that, in his later work, Wittgenstein comes to reject his Tractarian account of the phenomenon of linguistic regularity. Starting with this assumption, Pears sets out to examine the question as to what replaces Wittgenstein’s earlier account of the phenomenon in his later considerations on philosophical uses of the notion of meaning. Finally,withhisessay“OnaRemarkbyJukundus”,JoachimSchulteturns our attention to Wittgenstein’s views on religious belief and practice. While doubtful that Wittgenstein produced a self-standing philosophy of religion, Schulte takes the scattered remarks on religion in the Nachlass, and in par- ticular those on Christianity, to reflect Wittgenstein’s distinctive conception of ethics. The centerpiece in Schulte’s survey is his analysis of Wittgenstein’s qualifiedrejectionofthePaulinedoctrineofelectionbygraceasmeaningless. SchulteproposesanewreadingofWittgenstein’sclaimthatthisdoctrinecan be accepted as meaningful on one level of religiosity while being rejected as meaningless on another level. Along the way, Schulte develops an account of Wittgenstein’s personal level of religiosity that connects his laconic remarks on this matter with other strands in his thinking. Georg Henrik von Wright (1916–2003). Reproduced by Courtesy of Anna- Maija Hintikka. Acknowledgments Fortheirsageadviceandgenerousassistance,particularlyduringearlystages intheevolutionofthisvolume,IthankJaakkoHintikkaandRobertS.Cohen. Moreover,IoweadebtofgratitudetoHermiKastnerandReginaldE.Harris fortheunflaggingsupportandencouragementtheybothprovidedthroughout thepastfewyears.Ananonymousrefereewhosescrupulouseyedetectedmany aninfelicityinanearlierversionofthemanuscriptsubmittedtothepublisher deserves special thanks. I also gratefully acknowledge the unstinting support of Ingrid van Laarhoven of Springer Publishing Company. Sadly, David Pears passed away before this volume reached the printer. His original contribution is included here by kind permission of his widow, Anne Pears. IX