ebook img

Inner and Outer: Essays On a Philosophical Myth PDF

262 Pages·1991·24.375 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Inner and Outer: Essays On a Philosophical Myth

INNER AND OUTER Essays on a Philosophical Myth Also by Godfrey Vesey THE EMBODIED MIND PERCEPTION PERSONAL IDENTITY AGENCY AND NECESSITY (with Antony Flew) DICTIONARY OF PHILOSOPHY (with Paul Foulkes) Inner and Outer Essays on a Philosophical Myth Godfrey Vesey Emeritus Professor of Philosophy The Open University Palgrave Macmillan ISBN 978-1-349-21641-3 ISBN 978-1-349-21639-0 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-1-349-21639-0 ©Godfrey Norman Agmondisham Vesey, 1991 Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 1991 All rights reserved. For information, write: Scholarly and Reference Division, St. Martin's Press, Inc., 175 Fifth Avenue, New York, NY 10010 First published in the United States of America in 1991 ISBN 978-0-312-06174-6 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Vesey, Godfrey Norman Agmondisham. Inner and outer: essays on a philosophical myth/Godfrey Vesey. p. em. Essays originally published 1954-1990. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-0-312-06174-6 1. Dualism. I. Title. B812.V37 1991 128' .2-dc20 90-28462 CIP Contents Acknowledgements Vll 1 Introduction PART I VOLUNTARY ACTION 2 The Princess and the Philosopher 17 3 Volition 29 4 Agent and Spectator-The Double Aspect Theory 45 5 Hume on Liberty and Necessity 65 6 Free Will 84 PART II PERCEPTION 7 Unthinking Assumptions and Their Justification 105 8 Seeing and Seeing As 114 9 Sensations of Colour 127 10 Of the Visible Appearances of Objects 144 11 The Location of Bodily Sensations 161 12 The World Without 173 PART III COMMUNICATION 13 Is Talk a Mode of Transport? 189 14 Self-acquaintance and the Meaning ofT 198 15 Wittgenstein on the Myth of Mental Processes 208 16 Wittgenstein on Psychological Verbs 215 17 Other Minds 229 18 Wittgenstein-A Dictionary Entry 243 Godfrey Vesey-A Chronological Bibliography 247 Name Index 253 Subject Index 256 Acknowledgements The author and publishers acknowledge the first appearance in print of the essays in this volume, as listed below, in the publications named, and express their gratitude to all concerned in their publica tion. 'The Princess and the Philosopher', in Godfrey Vesey (ed.), Philos ophy in the Open (Milton Keynes: The Open University Press, 1974). 'Volition', Philosophy, 36 (1961). 'Agent and Spectator - the Double Aspect Theory', in Godfrey Vesey (ed.), The Human Agent, Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures, 1, 1966-67 (London: Macmillan, 1968). 'Hume on Liberty and Necessity', in Godfrey Vesey (ed.), Philoso phers Ancient and Modem, Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 20 (Cambridge University Press, 1986). 'Free Will', in A. Phillips Griffiths (e d.) Key Then res in Philosophy, Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 24 (Cambridge University Press, 1989). 'Unthinking Assumptions and their Justification', Mind, 63 (1954). 'Seeing and Seeing As', in Proceedings of tire Aristotelian Society, 56 (1956). 'Sensations of Colour', in J. B. Schneewind (ed.), Mill (New York: Doubleday, 1968). 'Of the Visible Appearances of Objects', in John Fisher (e d. ), Perceiv ing Artworks (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1980). 'The Location of Bodily Sensations', Milrd, 70 (1961). 'The World Without', in Godfrey Vesey (ed.), Pl1ilosophy in the Open (Milton Keynes: The Open University Press, 1974). 'Is Talk a Mode of Transport?', The Gadfly, a Quarterly Review of English Letters, 5 (1982). 'Self-acquaintance and the Meaning of "I" ', in George W. Roberts (ed.), Bertrand Russell Memorial Volume (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1979). 'Wittgenstein on the Myth of Mental Processes', The Philosophical Review, 77 (1968). 'Wittgenstein on Psychological Verbs', in Donald F. Gustafson and Bangs L. Tapscott (eds), Body, Mind and Method (Dordrecht, Holland: Reidel, 1979). vii viii Acknowledgements 'Other Minds', in Godfrey Vesey (ed.), Understanding Wittgenstein, Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures, 7, 1972-73 (London: Macmillan, 1974). 'Wittgenstein', in Godfrey Vesey and Paul Foulkes, Dictionary of Philosophy (London and Glasgow: Collins, 1990). 1 Introduction PRELIMINARIES The essays in this collection are on a philosophical myth. I call it 'the myth of the inner and outer'. It is behind what Gilbert Ryle calls 'the myth of the ghost in the machine'. 1 But it is also behind what might be called 'the myth of a machine with a ghost in it', or, more generally, 'the myth of the world as external'. In brief, the myth divides what, to the philosophically unindoctrinated (and even to the indoctrinated in their non-philosophical moments) is undivided, into two distinct things - one inner ('mental') and one outer ('physical'). The myth manifests itself in philosophical theories of voluntary action, perception and communication. In regard to voluntary action, the myth finds expression in the theory that my raising my arm is really two distinct things, one of them inner (my perform ing a mental act of willing, a 'volition') and one outer (my arm rising). In the case of perception, the myth finds expression in the so-called 'representative theory': I do not really see physical things; instead I apprehend inner things ('ideas' or 'sensations') that represent outer things (things in the 'external' world). In the case of communication, there is what Jonathan Bennett called 'the translation view of language':2 my saying something involves my translating inner things (ideas or thoughts) into outer things (aud ible sounds), and my understanding what someone says involves my translating outer things (audible sounds) into inner things (ideas or thoughts). Such is the power of the myth that we fall over our selves to embrace it when we first start philosophising about volun tary action, perception and communication. How is the myth to be combated? One way is the 'ordinary lan guage' way. We draw attention to how we ordinarily talk about voluntary action, perception and communication, and we try to show that anyone under the spell of the myth has distorted ordinary talk and thought. For example, suppose someone asserts that what 1 2 Introduction he is immediately aware of when he perceives something is really only an impression made on his mind by an external object. We can say, with Thomas Reid (1710-96): There is a figurative meaning of impressions on the mind but this meaning applies only to objects that are interesting. To say that an object which I see with perfect indifference makes an impression on my mind is not, as I apprehend, good English. If philosophers mean no more but that I see the object, why should they invent an improper phrase to express what every man knows how to express in plain English? ... When I look upon the wall of my room, the wall does not act at all, nor is capable of acting; the perceiving is an act or operation in me. That this is the common apprehension of mankind with regard to perception, is evident from the manner of expressing it in all languages. :1 Reid himself did not rest content with making the ordinary lan guage response. He wanted to combat John Locke (1632-1704) and David Hume (1711-76) on their own, metaphysical, ground. Someone who embraces the myth of the inner and outer thereby lays himself open to the question 'How can we be sure that the inner things, our ideas or concepts, conform to the outer things? In other words, how can we be sure that our concepts are real, and not fantastical or chimerical?' Locke's answer, in the case of our simple ideas of whiteness and coldness, was that we can be sure because the ideas are the effects in us of powers in things without. Different ideas or sensations in us correspond to different powers (qualities) in external things. In the case of secondary quali ties, correspondence does not mean resemblance, but resemblance is not needed for ideas to be real. The reality of simple ideas lies in the steady correspondence they have with their causes, the dis tinct constitutions of real beings. In short, simple ideas are real because they have a foundation in nature ... As might be expected, Locke's answer was entirely in accord with the representative theory of perception. By 'nature' he meant the external world. Reid accepted the question about the reality of our concepts as a proper one to ask, but rejected Locke's empiricist answer to it. The only 'nature' that matters, he said, is our own nature, our God-given constitution. The difference between Locke and Reid can be brought out with

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.