ebook img

Induction, Acceptance and Rational Belief PDF

240 Pages·1969·13.82 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Induction, Acceptance and Rational Belief

INDUCTION, ACCEPTANCE, AND RATIONAL BELIEF SYNTHESE LIBRARY MONOGRAPHS ON EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, SOCIOLOGY OF SCIENCE AND OF KNOWLEDGE, AND ON THE MATHEMATICAL METHODS OF SOCIAL AND BEHAVIORAL SCIENCES Editors: DONALD DAVIDSON, Princeton University J AAKKO HINTIKKA, University of Helsinki and Stanford University GABRIEL NUCHELMANS, University of Leyden WESLEY C. SALMON, Indiana University INDUCTION, ACCEPTANCE, AND RATIONAL BELIEF Edited by MARSHALL SWAIN University of Pennsylvania D. REIDEL PUBLISHING COMPANY / DORDRECHT-HOLLAND ISBN-13: 978-94-010-3392-3 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-010-3390-9 DOl: 10.1007/978-94-0 I 0-3390-9 © 1970. D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland Softcover reprint of the hardcover I st edition 1970 No part of this book may be reproduced in any form, by print, photoprint, microfilm, or any other means, without written permission from the publisher PREFACE The papers collected in this volume were originally presented at a sym posium held at the University of Pennsylvania in December of 1968. Each of the papers has been revised in light of the discussions that took place during this symposium. None of the papers has appeared in print previously. The extensive bibliography that appears at the end of the volume was originally distributed during the symposium and was revised on the basis of many helpful suggestions made by those who participated. The symposium was made possible by a grant from The National Science Foundation and funds contributed by the Philosophy Depart ment of the University of Pennsylvania. On behalf of the contributors to this volume, I would like to express my thanks to these organizations for their generous support. In addition, I would like to express my gratitude to the members of the Graduate Philosophy Students Organization at the University of Penn sylvania for the considerable assistance they gave me during the sym posium. My thanks, also, to Judith Sofranko and Lynn Luckett for their very responsible efforts in the preparation of the manuscript. Finally, I would like to thank Professor James Cornman for his invaluable advice and encouragement. M.S. TABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE V EDITOR'S INTRODUCTION 1 FREDERIC SCHICK / Three Logics of Belief 6 MARSHALL SWAIN / The Consistency of Rational Belief 27 HENRY E. KYBURG, JR. / Conjunctivitis 55 GILBER T H. HARMAN / Induction. A Discussion of the Relevance of the Theory of Knowledge to the Theory of Induction (with a Digression to the Effect that neither Deductive Logic nor the Probability Calculus has Anything to Do with Inference) 83 KEITH LEHRER / Justification, Explanation, and Induction 100 ISAAC LEVI/Probability and Evidence 134 RICHARD C. JEFFREY / Dracula meets Wolfman: Acceptance vs. Partial Belief 157 RALPH L. SLAGHT / Induction, Acceptance, and Rational Belief: A Selected Bibliography 186 INDEX OF NAMES 228 INDEX OF SUBJECTS 229 EDITOR'S INTRODUCTION The papers collected in this book are all devoted to the problem of the role that induction plays in theories of knowledge and rational belief. Nearly all of the papers are programmatic, and yet they contain many specific and original suggestions toward solutions of isolated problems in the area. The volume opens with an essay by Frederic Schick in which he delineates and compares three apparently competing theories about the conditions under which we are obligated or entitled to believe propositions. Schick calls these theories subjectivism, empiricism, and pragmatism; he refers to the writings of H. E. Kyburg, Jr. as one source of the subjectivist theory (not to be confused with the subjective theory of probability!), to the work of J. Hintikka as an example of empiricism, and to the work of I. Levi as an example of pragmatism. Schick argues that each of these theories is operative only in the context of a certain type of issue; empiricism and pragmatism provide principles relevant to fundamentally different (indeed, incompatible) types of issues, and there fore the results of these theories are not comparable. Consequently, the theories are not incompatible. Moreover, Schick argues, subjectivism is most plausibly interpreted in such a way that, depending on the issue, it will yield the same results as the other two theories. He suggests that a truly comprehensive theory of rational belief will incorporate all three of these theories. Schick also distinguishes the principles that individuate each of these theories from certain other principles which the theories might have in common; the latter are called 'overarching principles'. For example, the principle that the set of propositions one believes ought (rationally) to be deductively closed might be an overarching principle. The subject of overarching principles is the topic of my paper, which follows Schick's essay. In this paper, I construct a general theory of rational belief, which is intended to provide, among other things, principles governing the admissibility of propositions into sets of rationally believed proposi- 2 EDITOR'S INTRODUCTION tions. A distinction is made between propositions one is obligated to believe and propositions one is permitted to believe, from the point of view of rationality. I argue that the principles governing obligatory belief are quite different from those that govern permissible belief; this differ ence is illustrated in a solution given to the lottery paradox. The theory that I construct is intended to be 'overarching' in that it hopefully can serve as a framework within which rules of rational acceptance can be constructed. The theory is presented as an extension of Hintikka's logic of knowledge and belief, although many of the basic concepts of his system are considerably revised. The problem of overarching principles is also the subject of the essay by Henry E. Kyburg, Jr. Kyburg discusses several general principles that have been adopted, either implicitly or explicitly, by a number of writers on acceptance. He distinguishes 'weak' and 'strong' versions of principles governing the consistency as well as the deductive closure of sets of rationally accepted statements; in addition, he considers a principle of conjunction, which stipulates that if statements Sl and S2 are rationally accepted, then their conjunction ought to be accepted. After tracing a number of connections that hold among these various principles, Kyburg considers acceptance rules proposed by Hempel, Hintikka and Hilpinen, Levi, and Lehrer, all of which satisfy the conjunction principle and some or all of the other principles as well. Kyburg argues that each of these systems has flaws, and that many of the flaws are most plausibly attribut able to the fact that they satisfy the conjunction principle. He points out that his own system of rational belief, developed in earlier writings, abandons the conjunction principle and is consequently able to avoid many of the problems that the other systems face. Although his primary concern is to cast doubt on the conjunction principle, Kyburg also presents us with lucid expositions of the above theories and discusses many of their interesting aspects. Overarching principles of the type discussed above have an obvious relevance to the problem of constructing an adequate acceptance rule. Once these principles have been agreed upon, they can be used to formu late a partial criterion of adequacy for acceptance rules; any adequate acceptance rule must at least satisfy the demands of the overarching principles. In his contribution to this collection, Gilbert Harman introduces another kind of consideration that is relevant to the adequacy of accept- EDITOR'S INTRODUCTION 3 ance rules; namely, the connection between inferences warranted by such rules and the analysis of knowledge. Harman suggests that one partial test of adequacy for a proposed acceptance rule is whether inferences in accordance with that rule could provide one with knowledge. He discusses the causal theory of knowing developed by Alvin Goldman, and points out that this theory suggests a theory of inductive inference; namely, that inductive inference is inference to the best of competing causal statements. That theory has defects, however, and Harman proposes that we replace it with the theory that inductive inference is inference to the best of competing explanatory statements, a view that he has developed in pre vious writings. In the present paper, Harman expands and clarifies this interesting doctrine. The relation between explanation and justified belief is also the subject of the highly original essay by Keith Lehrer. Lehrer suggests that a belief is justified either because of what it explains or because of what explains it; he dubs this theory of justification expJanationism. Warranted inductive inference is viewed by Lehrer as one source of justified belief; if a hypo thesis h is inducible from one's background knowledge, then h is explained by that knowledge, and given the theory of explanationism, it follows that h is justified by that background knowledge. Lehrer provides us with a number of overarching principles governing the explanation of a hypo thesis or set of hypotheses relative to given background knowledge, and constructs an inductive acceptance rule such that inductive inferences warranted by that rule satisfy the demands of these overarching principles. Lehrer then argues that hypotheses inducible in accordance with this rule are also explained by the background knowledge from which they are induced. Consequently, he argues, his rule satisfies the demands of ex planationism; that is, a hypothesis is justified by inductive inference in accordance with his rule only if it is explained by the background know ledge. In the course of his discussion, Lehrer sheds new light on many interesting problems; for example, he discusses the problem of self justified (but fallible) beliefs within the context of explanationism. The papers discussed thus far have been directed primarily at problems surrounding the concept of rational acceptance, or rational belief. It is often supposed that a theory which assumes that there is such a thing as acceptance is fundamentally opposed to theories which instead speak of (rational) degrees of belief, or degrees of credence. In his important essay, 4 EDITOR'S INTRODUCTION Isaac Levi argues that this is not necessarily so. He points out that a theory of rational probability judgement will consist of conditions that determine rational degrees of credence at a given time as well as rational revision of degrees of credence over time. He rejects the Carnapian image of such conditions as a set of norms for an ideally rational man on the grounds that such a view has untoward consequences. He suggests, instead, that the conditions for rational probability judgement be viewed as necessary conditions for a state of 'equilibrium', analogously to a comparative static theory of consumer demand. In order to avoid subjectivism, Levi argues that the conditions for rational probability judgement must ground such judgements empirically, and he suggests a way in which this can be done. The resulting theory, he points out, presupposes that it is legitimate for one to accept some statements as evidence, contrary to a proposal made by Richard Jeffrey that rational credence judgements can be empirically grounded even though no state ments are accepted as evidence. Levi concludes that an adequate empir icistic theory of rational probability judgement must allow for the accept ance of statements as evidence; and, in turn, an adequate theory of acceptance will presuppose a theory of problem solving, which utilizes rational probability judgement. Thus, rather than being incompatible, the theory of rational credence judgement and the theory of acceptance are mutually dependent. Isaac Levi is to the theory of acceptance as Richard Jeffrey is to the theory of partial belief. In his contribution to this collection, Jeffrey offers a defense of his approach to the problem of rational belief; he is concerned especially to answer some standard criticisms of his approach (some of which have been raised by Levi). The Bayesian theory espoused by Jeffrey is, he points out, a pragmatic theory intended to provide a framework for rational deliberation which issues in action. The theory uses the term 'degree of belief' as a technical term which refers to an attribute of ones' attitude toward risks; the ordinary sense of belief, which seems to be used by those who speak of acceptance, is only vestigially present in this concept. One of the conditions that a set of partial beliefs must satisfy if it is to be rational is conformity to the laws of the elementary probability calculus. The theory is often criticised on the grounds that if this is sufficient for rationality, then any coherent set of partial beliefs will do in a given situation. But, Jeffrey argues, this is a misunderstanding;

Description:
The papers collected in this volume were originally presented at a sym­ posium held at the University of Pennsylvania in December of 1968. Each of the papers has been revised in light of the discussions that took place during this symposium. None of the papers has appeared in print previously. The
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.