ebook img

Imposing Values: An Essay on Liberalism and Regulation (Oxford Political Philosophy) PDF

505 Pages·2009·0.98 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Imposing Values: An Essay on Liberalism and Regulation (Oxford Political Philosophy)

IMPOSING VALUES OXFORD POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY General Editor: Samuel Freeman University of Pennsylvania Oxford Political Philosophy publishes books on theoretical and app- lied political philosophy within the Anglo-American tradition. The series welcomes submissions on social, political, and global justice, indi- vidual rights, democracy, liberalism, socialism, and constitutionalism. N. Scott Arnold Imposing Values: An Essay on Liberalism and Regulation IMPOSING VALUES An Essay on Liberalism and Regulation N. Scott Arnold 1 2009 1 Oxford University Press, Inc., publishes works that further Oxford University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education. Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With offi ces in Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Copyright © 2009 by Oxford University Press, Inc. Published by Oxford University Press, Inc. 198 Madison Avenue, New York, New York 10016 www.oup.com Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Oxford University Press. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Arnold, N. Scott. Imposing values : an essay on liberalism and regulation / N. Scott Arnold. p. cm. ISBN 978-0-19-537496-4 1. Liberalism. 2. Deregulation. I. Title. JC574.A75 2009 320.51'3—dc22 2008029351 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper To My Father There is, in fact, no recognized principle by which the propriety or impropriety of government interference is customarily tested. People decide according to their personal preferences. Some, whenever they see any good to be done, or evil to be remedied, would willingly instigate the government to undertake the business, while others prefer to bear almost any amount of social evil rather than add one to the departments of human interests amenable to governmental control. —John Stuart Mill, On Liberty Preface Perhaps the most basic and fundamental question of politi- cal philosophy concerns the moral justifi cation for the state. Why should there be government? And if there should be govern- ment, what kind of government should it be, and what should be its proper scope? The question of the proper scope of government is an enduring one in liberal polities and has a salience that it does not have in societies where the line circumscribing the legitimate role of the state is drawn as an afterthought. This is because liberals of all persuasions believe that there are certain areas of social life that are and ought to be off limits to government. A philosophically adequate response to the question of the proper role of government would seem to require an argument from fi rst prin- ciples. In On Liberty, John Stuart Mill argues for the Harm Principle, which says that the only legitimate grounds for social coercion is to prevent harm to others. The argument of that book is of course utili- tarian. If Mill were asked why utilitarian considerations should be determinative, he would refer the questioner to Utilitarianism, specif- ically chapter 4, “Of What Sort of Proof the Principle of Utility Is Sus- ceptible.” In this way, his answer to the question of the proper scope of government is rooted in deeper political, and ultimately moral, principles. As a philosopher, my fi rst inclination was to approach the subject matter of this book in this way. I soon recognized, how- ever, that whatever answer I gave to any of these deeper philosophical questions would be unlikely to be persuasive to those inclined to dis- agree with me about the proper scope of government. Another strat- egy suggested itself, but it required that I resist the impulse to try to answer fundamental philosophical questions. Instead, a more modest goal might be to seek agreement among my fellow liberals, leaving to others the task of justifying more fundamental principles. As I understand it (and as defended in chapter 1), to be a liberal involves a commitment to limited constitutional government, which in turn involves a belief in equal liberty, democratic governance, and viii PREFACE a more or less free market in which most of the means of production are privately owned. Although many parts of the world are ruled by illiberal governments, Western (and some Asian) societies are not, and it is for members of these societies that this book is written. Fur- thermore, although there are many immigrants from nonliberal polit- ical traditions living in contemporary Western societies, liberalism remains, in one form or another, the dominant ideology in the West. There is an important sense in which “there’s no one here but us liber- als,” though that may change in the future. This in turn permits a use- ful discussion about the proper scope of a liberal state, which would not be possible if fi rst principles were up for discussion. Besides, the resolution of the deepest disputes in political philosophy are, how shall we say, a long way off. As I began to write this book, I cast it in terms intended to cover all liberal societies but soon recognized that this would not work. I had to come down from the level of philosophical abstraction at which I am accustomed to writing and talk at the level of particular policies and laws. Since I know U.S. society best, that became my topic, though it should be accessible and (I hope) of interest to non- Americans as well. Still, this is a very ambitious project. The fi rst four chapters are intended to be a comprehensive survey of the differences between classical liberalism and modern liberalism regarding the proper scope of government. Chapter 1 offers a prelimi- nary characterization of classical liberalism and modern liberalism and explains the main areas of agreement between them. Although all liberals believe in limited constitutional government, classical liber- als are inclined to favor a more limited role for government, whereas modern liberals are inclined to favor a more extensive role for govern- ment. This is aptly captured in the epigraph to this book from Mill’s On Liberty. Chapter 2 begins a discussion of these differences. Classi- cal liberals and modern liberals differ on the extent to which the state should own productive assets in an essentially private enterprise economy. It turns out, however, that these differences are not deep: classical liberals do not oppose all state ownership of productive assets, and modern liberals are open to privatizinggovernment-owned assets and indeed have supported the latter. Deeper (philosophical) differences are to be found regarding tax policy and transfer pro- grams, however. I argue that modern liberalism presupposes a form of social ownership of productive assets even though, at the end of the day, they favor private property in (most) of the means of p roduction. PREFACE ix A presupposition of social ownership best explains modern liberal attitudes and beliefs about tax policy and transfer policy. These include, but are not limited to, redistributive taxation and transfer programs. Classical liberals, by contrast, believe that property rights in the fi rst instance reside with private parties, either on grounds of natural rights or on utilitarian grounds. Government has the right to take some of that property—classical liberals are not anarchists—but government is much more constrained in what it may legitimately do in the name of tax policy and in transfer programs than in the modern liberal vision. In keeping with my methodology, I make no effort to resolve this philosophical difference. Chapter 3 outlines the points of agreement and disagreement between modern and classical liberals on the extent to which owner- ship rights should be restricted by the state through regulation. Prop- erty is a complex of rights, terms, and conditions, and there are major and systematic differences between classical liberalism and modern liberalism about what regulatory restrictions they will countenance. Chapters 1 through 3 constitute a comprehensive statement of the points of agreement and disagreement between classical liberals and modern liberals about the proper role or scope of the government in modern U.S. society. One of the purposes of this book is to articulate a range of plausible forms of classical liberalism. It is unfortunate that classical liberalism has typically been identifi ed with libertarianism. Libertarians believe that the sole legitimate function of government is to protect and enforce people’s rights to life, liberty, and property. Some libertarians also allow that the state can legitimately supply some public goods. Classical liberalism need not be so narrowly understood, however. Indeed, historically, it has not been. There are versions of classical liberalism that do not presuppose the extremely stringent rights to private property and freedom of contract favored by contemporary libertarians, which their critics have used as a stick to beat them with. One purpose of this book is to outline a more mod- erate version of classical liberalism. Chapter 4 identifi es what I call “the modern liberal regulatory agenda,” which consists of the various regulatory regimes that mod- ern liberals are inclined to favor and classical liberals are inclined to oppose. The fi rst section of this chapter distinguishes economic from noneconomic regulation. The former includes rate regulation, regulation of entry and exit, antitrust law, and wage and price con- trols. It is argued that the traditional disputes between modern lib- erals and classical liberals about economic regulation have become

Description:
A major question for liberal politics and liberal political theory concerns the proper scope of government. Liberalism has always favored limited government, but there has been wide-ranging dispute among liberals about just how extensive the scope of government should be. Included in this dispute ar
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.