Imagination Also available from Bloomsbury Comparative Philosophy without Borders, edited by Arindam Chakrabarti and Ralph Weber Doing Philosophy Comparatively, by Tim Connolly Landscape and Travelling East and West, edited by Hans-Georg Moeller and Andrew K. Whitehead Wisdom and Philosophy, edited by Hans-Georg Moeller and Andrew K. Whitehead Imagination Cross-Cultural Philosophical Analyses edited by Hans-Georg Moeller and Andrew K. Whitehead BLOOMSBURY ACADEMIC Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square, London, WC1B 3DP, UK 1385 Broadway, New York, NY 10018, USA BLOOMSBURY, BLOOMSBURY ACADEMIC and the Diana logo are trademarks of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published in Great Britain 2019 Copyright © Hans-Georg Moeller and Andrew K. Whitehead, 2019 Hans-Georg Moeller and Andrew K. Whitehead have asserted their rights under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as Editors of this work. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. Bloomsbury Publishing Plc does not have any control over, or responsibility for, any third-party websites referred to or in this book. All internet addresses given in this book were correct at the time of going to press. The author and publisher regret any inconvenience caused if addresses have changed or sites have ceased to exist, but can accept no responsibility for any such changes. A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN: HB: 978-1-3500-5013-6 ePDF: 978-1-3500-5014-3 eBook: 978-1-3500-5015-0 Typeset by Integra Software Services Pvt. Ltd. To find out more about our authors and books visit www.bloomsbury.com and sign up for our newsletters. Contents Introduction Andrew K. Whitehead 1 Part 1 Imagination in Chinese and Japanese Philosophies 11 1 Truth and Imagination in China: Opposition and Conciliation in the Tradition Richard John Lynn 13 2 Zhuangzi and Fantasy Literature Nicolas Le Jeune 29 3 Visual Zen: The Role of Imagination in Shaping a Zen Aesthetics Rudi Capra 45 Part 2 Comparative Studies on Imagination 57 4 The Imaginary and the Real in Zhuangzi and Plato May Sim 59 5 Is There Imagination in Daoism? Kant, Heidegger, and Classical Daoism: Rethinking Imagination and Thinking in Images Steven Burik 79 6 Daoism, Utopian Imagination, and Its Discontents Ellen Y. Zhang 103 Part 3 Post-Comparative Conceptions of Imagination 127 7 Imagination beyond the Western Mind Julia Jansen 129 8 Time, Habit, and Imagination in Childhood Play Talia Welsh 141 9 Images of Me in the Roles I Live: An Existentialist Contribution to Confucian Role Ethics Andrew K. Whitehead 153 10 Imagination, Formation, World, and Place: An Ontology John W. M. Krummel 163 11 Imagination and the Lives of Others Victoria S. Harrison 187 12 Between Truth and Utopia: Philosophy in North America and the Narrowing of the Social-Political Imagination Gabriel Soldatenko 203 Index 221 Introduction Andrew K. Whitehead The imagination has been a topic of fascination and examination throughout the history of Western philosophy. From the writings of Plato and Aristotle, drawing on the etymological links between idea (ιδέα from the Greek “to see” εἴδω) and image (εικόν), and between fantasy (φαντασία) and appearance (“phainomenon” φαινόμενο), through to contemporary scholarship in phenomenology, aesthetics, philosophy of mind, and psychoanalysis, the imagination in its various senses has consistently been afforded significance in how the world is encountered, experienced, and conceived. The role of the imagination may be understood negatively, as the capacity to depart from the real, or as deceptive and illusory, and therefore as demanding correction or critique. It may also be understood positively, as reproductive or even constructive, as an invaluable source for our making present what is not itself present, and as necessary for the projection of alternative scenarios and possible worlds. Despite this notable difference in the many senses in which the imagination is understood, it is not clear that this difference indicates a rigid distinction, as the negative and positive conceptions of the imagination can also be understood as different aspects of one and the same phenomenon. The ebb and flow of philosophical scholarship on the imagination evidences the correlative emergence of divergences in perspective and situated critique. Turning to non-Western philosophy, although the idea of imagination as the mental faculty of an individual mind makes less sense, we still encounter comparable notions of imaginative engagement. Conceptions of the illusory and deceptive, the development of fantastic narratives and metaphors, the relation between projection and truth, and the use of images and allegories abound in all schools. Even more relevant material is found in implicit engagements with issues of the imagination, which do not necessarily make use of concepts and do 2 Imagination not necessarily address questions commonly associated with the imagination in Western discourses. However, the imagination is of interest to comparative philosophy in particular not only as a topic of investigation, but also as an indispensable means. Comparative philosophy often takes place in a non-place, if you will, in an imagined place where comparisons can take place. The imagination here acquires a crucial methodological role, providing possibilities for intercultural and trans- temporal dialogue and critical engagement. As comparative philosophers, we do not simply analyze and examine, but we also imagine collectively, in a social imaginary that we might come to call a post-comparative place, to the extent that this imagined place focuses on method as opposed to disciplinary affiliation, and to the extent that we imagine it to go beyond simple comparisons. Over the last several decades, there seems to be an increasing tendency first to co-opt the nomenclature of comparative philosophy, and then, in turn, to argue for more refined and sophisticated nomenclature, such as “fusion philosophy,” “contrastive philosophy,” and “synthesizing philosophy.” Here we find attempts to draw out the legitimacy of non-Western philosophical schools of thought in terms appropriate to “philosophy proper,” that is, to evidence their legitimacy for inclusion in a canon of “philosophy simpliciter” by translating them into the language of the existing (Western) canon. In this sense, such scholarship embellishes upon boundaries and borders that it has itself erected, under the (false) presupposition that the penultimate intention of such scholarship is to eradicate these very same borders. The following volume looks to move beyond precisely this “appropriating” type of comparative philosophy. In other works, Hans-Georg Moeller1 has insisted on a turn to post-comparative philosophy. My understanding of this turn is as a response to a marked need to turn back to comparative philosophy as it was initially conceived and practiced, as a call to an “imaginary” neutral territory for the sake of allowing pluralism and its efforts to speak for themselves. As I see it, it is also a liberating turn, a turn away from the distorting constraints produced by the disciplinary tendencies of the neo-liberal university, such as an overzealous preoccupation with “novel” analyses, “high-impact” and “groundbreaking” research, and an unprecedented demand for research “output” in general. Eduardo Galeano reminds us in the book Open Veins of Latin America that “in an incarcerated society, free literature can exist only as denunciation and hope” (1997: 13). I choose to paraphrase his sentiment and note that in an incarcerated institution such as the neo-liberal university, free philosophy can exist only as denunciation and hope. The denunciation of the collective imbecilization that Introduction 3 has permeated our institutions of higher education for the last fifty years has already begun, indicating a marked hope for an imagined alternative. There are increasingly more venues where we are free to imagine such alternatives freely, collectively, and critically. If Galeano (1997: 13) is correct in his existential finding that “we are what we do, especially what we do to change what we are,” then our commitment now, to imagine and enact a return to philosophy proper, to a sustained and systematic articulation of how we are for the sake of drawing us to how we should be, is what we are. I find myself inspired by and resolutely empathetic with a story that Galeano articulates in his Book of Embraces. He writes: There was an old and solitary man who spent most of his time in bed. There were rumors that he had a treasure hidden in his house. One day some thieves broke in, they searched everywhere and found a chest in the cellar. They went off with it and when they opened it they found that it was filled with letters. They were the love letters the old man had received all over the course of his long life. The thieves were going to burn the letters, but they talked it over and finally decided to return them. One by one. One a week. Since then, every Monday at noon, the old man would be waiting for the postman to appear. As soon as he saw him, the old man would start running and the postman, who knew all about it, held the letter in his hand. And even St. Peter could hear the beating of that heart, crazed with joy at receiving a message from a woman. (1997: 10) While tempted to identify with the old man, I believe our role and our function are and need to be closer to that of the thieves and the postman. We must re- appropriate what has been hidden away for the sake of re-distribution. We must yoke the social affect that is to be so crazed with joy by instigating collective hope. We must reinvigorate the social imaginaries. In so doing, we must endeavor to take up legitimate comparative philosophical methods, free, as much as possible, from the constraints imposed by current disciplinary orders and from the analytic critiques which support and facilitate the imposition of illegitimate terms of differentiation and reconciliation. We must endeavor to practice comparative philosophy anew. This then is what can be meant by post-comparative philosophy: comparative philosophy, free from the pomp and presumption that has worked to undermine it in the name of something like “global philosophy,” at least insofar as this suggests that distinct perspectives can be amalgamated and their differences somehow dissolved. Insofar as I have a pluralist understanding of comparative philosophy, I remain skeptical of such tendencies. If comparative philosophy really is not only rigorous, but also “open,” then it must remain receptive to objections and revisions. I believe this volume