ebook img

Human Flourishing and the Dialectic of Happiness PDF

273 Pages·2015·1.36 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Human Flourishing and the Dialectic of Happiness

Echoing  Demystified  Aspirations:     Human  Flourishing  and  the  Dialectic  of  Happiness     By     Patrick  Ahern     Dissertation     Submitted  to  the  Faculty  of  the     Graduate  School  of  Vanderbilt  University     in  partial  fulfillment  of  the  requirements       for  the  degree  of     Doctor  of  Philosophy     In     Philosophy     May,  2015     Nashville,  TN     Approved:     Idit  Dobbs-­‐Weinstein,  Ph.D.   Gregg  Horowitz,  Ph.D.   Jose  Medina,  Ph.D.   Andrew  Cutrofello,  Ph.D. Table  of  Contents                                            Page                 DEDICATION……..………………………………………………………………………………………………..iv     ACKNOWLEDGEMENT…………………………………………………………………………………….......v     CHAPTER     I. Introduction……………………………………………………………....……………………...…1     II. Constructing  the  Royal  Road  to  Happiness:  The  Case  of  Hobbes……….…..24     The  Physics  of  Happiness   Hobbesian  Individual  and  Displacements  of  Power   Passions  and  the  Science  of  Politics   The  Construction  of  the  Commonwealth   The  Paradoxes  of  Hobbesian  Happiness     III. Spinoza’s  Happiness:  Beatitude  and  the  Economy  of  Affect………….……….90     Beatitudo  as  the  Greatest  Happiness   Happiness,  Joy,  and  the  Power  of  the  Affects   Constructing  the  Politics  of  Happiness:  Multitude,  Transindividuality,     and  State  Power   The  Free  State  and  the  Economy  of  Affect   The  Most  “Natural”  State,  or  the  Most  Absolute  Power     IV. Marx’s  Critical  Relation  to  Happiness:  Ambivalence,  Sacrifice,  and   Revolutionary  Possibilities………………………………………………………….148                                    Marxian  Practice  and  the  Poetics  of  Production                  The  Science  of  Emancipation                  The  Myth  of  Origins  and  the  Commodification  of  Labor                  Revolutionary  Chasm  and  the  Materiality  of  Time                  Conjunctures  of  Unhappiness                  Revolutionary  Constellations  and  Happiness     V. Decayed  Bodies,  Redeemed  Past:  Adorno,  Benjamin,  and  the  Deformation   of  Happiness……………………………………………………………………………..224                    Costly  Flights                  A  Tiger’s  Leap                  Kafka’s  Cough                  Hunchback’s  Perspective   ii VI. Epilogue…………………………………………………………………………………………..253     REFERENCES...................................................................................................................................262                                                                                           iii To  mom  and  dad         To  loving  Katie         and           To  Natalie  and  Jane,  who  remind  me  daily  that  laughter  and  fun  is  also  a  central  part   of  substantial  happiness                                             iv Acknowledgements     This  work  would  not  have  been  possible  without  the  financial  support  of  the   Vanderbilt  Philosophy  Department  and  the  Graduate  School  of  Vanderbilt   University.  I  am  grateful  to  my  professors  and  peers  with  whom  I  have  had  the   fortune  of  working  and  learning  during  my  time  at  Vanderbilt.     I  am  grateful  to  the  members  of  my  dissertation  committee  who  have  taken   the  time  to  engage  with  my  work.  I  owe  a  debt  of  gratitude  to  Gregg  Horowitz  for  his   close  reading  and  critical  engagement  with  my  work.    In  the  dialogue  he  generated   with  my  work,  he  has  offered  an  exemplary  model  of  what  it  means  to  be  a  careful   and  critical  reader.  I  would  especially  like  to  thank  my  philosophical  mentor  and   dissertation  advisor,  Idit  Dobbs-­‐Weinstein.  She  has  challenged  me  to  think   historically,  and  for  that  I  am  eternally  grateful.       I  would  like  to  thank  my  parents,  who  have  been  infinitely  supportive  my   desire  to  follow  my  passion  for  philosophy.  And  last,  but  certainly  not  least,  I  would   like  to  thank  Katie  for  her  loving  support  and  patience.                   v Chapter  One     Introduction     The  question  of  the  possibility  or  even  the  concern  for  human  happiness  has   proven  to  be  a  point  of  contention  for  political  thinkers  confronting  the  ideological   injunction  to  “be  happy”  in  the  face  of  material  conditions  that  stifle  the  capacity  for   human  flourishing.  It  can  be  argued  that  the  appeal  to  human  happiness  as  a   political  norm  occludes  as  much  as  it  may  reveal,  and  that  the  cult  of  happiness  is   the  domain  of  the  internalized  oppressor,  severing  the  avenues  of  self-­‐reflection,   social  critique,  or  political  praxis.  Simone  de  Beauvoir,  in  her  defense  of  addressing   the  issue  of  liberty  over  happiness,  expresses  such  a  concern  when  she  writes,  “It  is   not  clear  what  the  word  happy  really  means  and  still  less  what  true  values  it  may   mask.  There  is  no  measuring  the  happiness  of  others,  and  it  is  always  easy  to   describe  as  happy  the  situation  in  which  one  wishes  to  place  them.”1  Out  of  a   concern  for  the  struggle  of  women’s  liberation,  de  Beauvoir  views  the  topic  of   happiness  as  regressive,  giving  itself  over  to  un-­‐reflexive  and  positivistic  impulses,   thus  reinforcing  the  authority  of  oppressive  power  structures.  These  concerns  are   well  founded,  especially  in  light  of  the  most  predominant  iterations  of  happiness  in   the  form  of  utilitarian  ethics  and  the  ‘cult  of  happiness’  founded  within  fetishized   consumer  culture.  The  deceptive  character  of  the  evaluation  of  the  concept  of   happiness  as  a  feeling,  particularly  amongst  subjects  immersed  and  interpellated   within  an  ideological  field  that  reinforces  the  interests  of  the  ruling  powers,  bears                                                                                                                   1  Simone  de  Beauvoir,  The  Second  Sex,  trans.    Constance  Borde  and  Sheila  Malovany-­‐Chevallier  (New   York:  First  Vintage  Books,  2009),  16.   1 the  dangers  of  masking  the  conditions  that  prevent  the  flourishing  of  human  beings   in  their  active  relations.2  What  may  appear  as  ‘self-­‐evident’  to  the  empirical   observer,  the  fulfilled  experience  of  subjective  activity,  turns  out  to  be  that  which   the  concept  of  happiness  in  such  instances  serves  to  occlude.     The  struggle  for  human  flourishing  guided  de  Beauvoir’s  admonition  of  the   explicit  concern  for  human  happiness,  and  the  gain  of  resisting  cooptation  into  all   consuming  ideological  forces  moves  to  the  fore  instead.  However,  might  not  the   decisiveness  and  enthusiasm  of  incorporation  of  the  norm  of  happiness  into   dominant  ideology  perhaps  give  pause  to  those  opposing  the  forces  that  stifle   human  flourishing?  Rather  than  resigning  to  the  fate  of  the  loss  of  happiness  as  a   mode  of  expressing  or  experiencing  the  aspirations  for  human  flourishing,  might  not   a  resuscitation  of  the  demand  for  human  flourishing  call  for  a  revaluation  of   happiness  in  opposition  to  the  forces  that  deploy  the  deflated  notion  toward   ideological  ends?  While  Theodor  Adorno  sympathizes  with  the  reluctance  to   address  happiness  in  a  direct  manner  because  of  the  ideological  menace  that  haunts   the  naïve  notion  of  happiness,  he  also  acknowledges  the  critical  importance  of  a                                                                                                                   2  A  similar  concern  against  a  positivist,  subjectivist  account  of  happiness  is  expressed  by  Sigmund   Freud,  though  emerging  from  decidedly  different  interests,  when  he  writes,  “We  shall  always  tend  to   consider  people’s  distress  objectively  –  that  is,  to  place  ourselves,  with  our  own  wants  and   sensibilities,  in  their  conditions,  and  then  to  examine  on  what  occasions  we  should  find  in  them  for   experiencing  happiness  or  unhappiness.  This  method  of  looking  at  things,  which  seems  objective   because  it  ignores  the  variations  in  subjective  sensibility,  is,  of  course,  the  most  subjective  possible,   since  it  puts  one’s  own  mental  states  in  the  place  of  any  others,  unknown  though  they  may  be.   Happiness,  however,  is  something  essentially  subjective.  No  matter  how  much  we  may  shrink  with   horror  from  certain  situations  –  of  a  galley-­‐slave  in  antiquity,  of  a  peasant  during  the  Thirty  Years’   War,  of  a  victim  of  the  Holy  Inquisition,  of  a  Jew  awaiting  a  pogrom—it  is  nevertheless  impossible  for   us  to  feel  our  way  into  such  people  –  to  divine  the  changes  which  original  obtuseness  of  mind,  a   gradual  stupefying  process,  the  cessation  of  expectations,  and  cruder  or  more  refined  methods  of   narcotization  have  produced  upon  their  receptivity  to  sensations  of  pleasure  and  unpleasure.   Moreover,  in  the  case  of  the  most  extreme  possibility  of  suffering,  special  mental  protective  devices   are  brought  into  operation.”  Sigmund  Freud,  Civilization  and  Its  Discontents,  trans.    James  Strachey   (New  York:  W.W.  Norton  &  Co.,  1961)  41.   2 dialectical  account  when  defining  happiness  as,  “the  only  part  of  the  metaphysical   experience  that  is  more  than  impotent  longing,”  that  “gives  us  the  inside  of  objects   as  something  removed  from  objects.”  The  cost  of  conceding  the  idea  of  happiness  to   the  powers  that  thwart  the  possibility  of  human  flourishing  becomes  evident,   despite  the  precariousness  of  the  resistance  to  cooptation,  when  he  continues,  “Yet   the  man  who  enjoys  this  kind  of  experience  naively,  as  though  putting  his  hands  on   what  the  experience  suggests,  is  acceding  to  the  terms  of  the  empirical  world  –   terms  he  wants  to  transcend,  though  they  alone  give  him  the  chance  of   transcending.”3  According  to  Adorno,  happiness  bears  a  close  affinity  to  the  capacity   for  embodied,  historical  experience  that  enables  the  possibility  to  resist  rather  than   submit  to  either  the  collective  delusions  or  resignation  that  accompanies  “naïvely”   experienced  happiness.  However,  in  a  twist  of  irony,  the  failure  to  harness  the   critical  power  that  a  dialectical  conception  of  happiness  can  provide  undermines  the   capacity  to  transcend  the  conditions  that  foster  the  force  of  ideological  or  idolatrous   notions.  In  the  passage  above,  Adorno  touches  upon  a  paradoxical  relation  to  the   idea  of  happiness,  both  as  the  ruse  to  keep  human  beings  under  the  thumb  of  the   forces  that  prolong  their  demise,  and  as  the  source  of  liberation  from  those  very   same  forces.  I  will  claim  that  the  dialectic  of  happiness,  in  its  affinity  with  embodied   and  historical  experience,  forms  the  negative  relief  upon  which  the  demand  for   human  happiness  can  find  expression.  The  challenge  of  sustaining  this  dialectical   play  has  impeded  historical  attempts  to  conceive  of  a  constructive  politics  in   resistance  to  the  forces  that  stifle  human  flourishing.  It  will  be  the  task  of  this                                                                                                                   3  Theodor  Adorno,  Negative  Dialectics,  trans.    E.B.  Ashton  (New  York:  Continuum  International   Publishing  Group,  1973),  374.     3 dissertation  to  elaborate  the  manner  in  which  historical  attempts  to  construct  a   politics  in  the  service  of  human  flourishing  have  succeeded  or  failed  in  light  of  the   dialectic  of  happiness,  and  how  this  dialectic  reveals  the  possibility  of  happiness   remaining  in  the  present.     It  would  seem  counterintuitive  that  a  concern  for  human  flourishing  could   rely  upon  what  Adorno  refers  to  as  a  “metaphysical  experience”  without  regressing   into  the  futility  of  escapist  flight  from  the  conditions  that  are  the  source  of  misery.   The  critical  strength  of  a  dialectical  conception  of  happiness  emerges  from  an   understanding  of  the  experience  that  dissolves  the  claims  of  empirical  experience   while  providing  the  possibility  of  material  transformation.  Adorno  locates  the   possibility  of  illuminating  what  is  deformed  in  empirical  experience  in  both   aesthetic  and  theoretical  terms.  Both,  however,  only  have  the  capacity  to  express   these  experiences  in  the  manifestations  of  failure  or  loss,  for  it  is  in  the  loss  or   failure  that  the  deformation  of  “naïve”  happiness  emerges  in  its  deformity.  The  work   of  Walter  Benjamin  is  largely  dedicated  to  taking  on  this  challenge  of  expressing  the   “metaphysical  experience”  in  which  the  domination  of  either  the  subjective  or   objective  elements  of  living  are  dissolved.  The  ‘method,’  if  one  is  to  speak  loosely,  of   Benjamin’s  work  is  to  delve  into  the  depths  of  experiential  life  from  the  profane   minutiae  of  daily  life  to  the  seemingly  lofty  heights  of  messianic  possibility.  The   guiding  thread  of  Benjamin’s  writings  is  the  desire  and  possibility  for  happiness,  and   even  to  the  extent  that  the  philosophical  relationship  between  Adorno  and  Benjamin   became  strained  at  various  points  of  their  lives,  one  could  fairly  note  that  their   4 differences  arose  from  a  divergence  in  the  appropriate  representations  of  the   dialectic  of  happiness;  that  is,  a  shared  commitment  to  the  “promise  of  happiness.”4   In  the  “Theologico-­‐Political  Fragment,”  Benjamin  deploys  the  theological   concept  of  the  messianic  in  order  to  express  the  possibility  of  happiness  in  the   secular  world.  In  setting  up  a  peculiar  alliance  of  the  messianic  and  the  secular,   Benjamin  gestures  toward  the  manner  in  which  the  idea  of  happiness  resonates   with  both  secular  and  messianic  intensity.  He  writes,   “The  secular  order  should  be  erected  on  the  idea  of  happiness.  The  relation  of  this   order  to  the  messianic  is  one  of  the  essential  teachings  of  the  philosophy  of  history.   It  is  the  precondition  of  a  mystical  conception  of  history,  encompassing  a  problem   that  can  be  represented  figuratively.  If  one  arrow  points  to  the  goal  toward  which   the  secular  dynamic  acts,  and  another  marks  the  direction  of  messianic  intensity,   then  certainly  the  quest  of  free  humanity  runs  counter  to  the  messianic  direction.   But  just  as  a  force,  by  virtue  of  the  path  it  is  moving  along,  can  augment  another   force  on  the  opposite  path,  so  the  secular  order  –  because  of  its  nature  as  secular  –   promotes  the  coming  of  the  Messianic  kingdom.  The  secular,  therefore,  though  not   itself  a  category  of  this  kingdom,  is  a  decisive  category  of  its  most  inobtrusive   approach.”5     The  relation  of  the  secular  and  the  messianic  arrives  in  the  form  of  a  problem  and  a   possibility,  one  that  engenders  all  of  the  risks  of  a  ‘mystical’  conception  of  history   (i.e.  one  that  stymies  the  possibility  for  happiness),  as  well  as  the  reward  of  the   potentiality  of  the  happiness  in  the  category  of  the  secular.  Benjamin  encounters  the   relation  of  the  messianic  and  the  secular  as  most  significant  for  the  realization  of   happiness,  and  the  ordering  of  this  relationship  will  be  decisive  in  the  struggle  for   human  flourishing.                                                                                                                     4  Adorno  notes  that  the  movement,  or  “digressiveness,”  of  Benjamin’s  writings,  “stems  from  a  quality   which  intellectual  departmentalization  otherwise  reserves  for  art,  but  which  sheds  all  semblance   when  transposed  into  the  realm  of  theory  and  assumes  incomparable  dignity  –the  promise  of   happiness.”  Theodor  Adorno,  “A  Portrait  of  Walter  Benjamin,”  Prisms,  trans.    Samuel  and  Shierry   Weber  (Cambridge,  MA:  The  MIT  Press,  1967),  230.   5  Walter  Benjamin,  “Theological-­‐Political  Fragment,  ”Selected  Writings:  Volume  3,  1935-­‐1938,  305.   5

Description:
critique of capitalist social order is grounded in the critique of fetishism . of happiness, is that it does not stagnate as a reification of the poles of the
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.