ebook img

Hobbes and modern political thought PDF

271 Pages·2016·0.859 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Hobbes and modern political thought

HOBBES AND MODERN POLITICAL THOUGHT HOBBES AND MODERN POLITICAL THOUGHT Yves Charles Zarka Translated and with an Introduction by James Griffith Edinburgh University Press is one of the leading university presses in the UK. We publish academic books and journals in our selected subject areas across the humanities and social sciences, combining cutting-edge scholarship with high editorial and production values to produce academic works of lasting importance. For more information visit our website: www.edinburghuniversitypress.com © Yves Charles Zarka, 1995 [year of publication of original text] © editorial matter and organisation James Griffith, 2016 Edinburgh University Press Ltd The Tun – Holyrood Road 12(2f) Jackson’s Entry Edinburgh EH8 8PJ Typeset in Sabon and Gill Sans by Servis Filmsetting Ltd, Stockport, Cheshire, and printed and bound in Great Britain by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon CR0 4YY A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN 978 1 4744 0121 0 (hardback) ISBN 978 1 4744 0120 3 (webready PDF) ISBN 978 1 4744 0513 3 (epub) The right of Yves Charles Zarka to be identified as the author of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, and the Copyright and Related Rights Regulations 2003 (SI No. 2498). CONTENTS Translator’s Introduction vii Foreword xiii 1 Journey: To the Foundations of Modern Politics 1 Part I Individual and State 13 2 Gracián’s Hero and Hobbes’s Antihero 15 3 The Hobbesian Idea of Political Philosophy 34 Part II Language and Power [Pouvoir] 51 4 Theory of Language 53 5 The Semiology of Power [Pouvoir] 72 Part III Fundamental Concepts of Politics 105 6 On War 107 7 On Law 123 8 On Property 146 9 On the State 168 10 On the Right to Punish 195 Part IV Hobbes According to Two Contemporaries 217 11 Hobbes and Filmer: Regnum Patrimoniale and Regnum Institutivum 219 vi Hobbes and Modern Political Thought 12 Hobbes and Pascal: Two Models of the Theory of Power [Pouvoir] 234 Conclusion 247 Bibliography 251 Index 257 TRANSLATOR’S INTRODUCTION Yves Charles Zarka is indeed one of the most important philosophers in France, though he has been little recognised in the Anglophone world, at least beyond Hobbes scholarship. He is currently the Chair of Political Philosophy as well as director of the Centre de philoso- phie, d’épistémologie et de politique at the Université Paris Descartes (Sorbonne). He is also the director of several imprints at the Presses universitaires de France, is the editor of the journal Cités, and has col- laborated with Jürgen Habermas and Axel Honneth. As to his work on Hobbes, he is the director of Vrin’s Œuvres de Hobbes, in addition to several writings – including this book, La décision métaphysique de Hobbes and L’autre voie de la subjectivité – as well as a number of edited volumes. Thus, while his work on Hobbes is what he is primar- ily known for in English, his research extends to political philosophy broadly, both in its history and its current articulations. Perhaps the fact that I feel the need to state that Zarka’s work covers political philosophy in its historical and contemporary registers explains some of the reasons why he is not as well known to English- language readers as he could be. It does not seem to be a great stretch to claim that Hobbes scholarship in the English-s peaking world has been influenced by the work of Quentin Skinner, whose fundamental philosophical positions lead him to ask ‘why [texts] were written in the form in which we have them’.1 This question leads to detailed exami- nations of the surrounding contexts of the material he examines; of other texts of the time that may have influenced by, or been in imme- diate conversation with, say, Leviathan; and so on.2 This approach is, in its way, laudable, leading to any number of insights as to how and why a certain text came to be written in the way that it did. However, it is not the only approach to historically grounded philosophy, and vii viii Hobbes and Modern Political Thought I would argue that it is a limiting and limited approach in its way as well. The limits to Skinner’s approach can be seen at the end of the same sentence cited above, where he articulates a problematic approach to the history of political philosophy: ‘what can I hope to learn from this text about politics’.3 Such is not Zarka’s approach. For Zarka, what can never be forgotten when reading the history of philosophy, political or otherwise, is that ‘thinking philosophically always means thinking from a certain point of view’ and that ‘thinking philosophically always means interpreting’.4 That is, both the philosopher being read and the philosopher doing the reading think from a perspective, a perspective that is both an act of interpretation and itself requires interpretation. Thus, reading the history of philosophy is itself a philosophical act, and an act that requires historical precision. It is for these reasons that Zarka understands his own position in The Amsterdam Debate as being ‘antihistoricist’.5 If we take Skinner’s his- toricism seriously as a philosophical position,6 then it is a philosophical position that ‘refutes itself’ insofar as it ‘denies its interpretative char- acter in order to make out that it is a pure restoration of the content of a text’.7 In other words, for Zarka, Skinner’s approach, if it is itself philosophical, forgets that it thinks from a certain point of view and also fails to understand that it is interpreting in its thinking from that forgotten perspective. The other author from whom Zarka departs is Leo Strauss. While Strauss is to some degree an ally of Zarka’s in the argument against his- toricism, they are not involved in identical projects. Like Zarka, Strauss argues that historicism is a self-d estructive historiographical position, insofar as it takes up the essentially ahistorical position of asserting that all past political philosophical texts can be reduced to their histori- cal circumstances.8 However, for Strauss, classical and modern politi- cal philosophy are distinguished through ‘the discovery of history’ in the nineteenth century as a scientific discipline, where history can be engaged, like nature, in the discovery of its laws.9 Because of this dis- covery, modern political philosophy contains ‘the notion of a guaran- teed parallelism between intellectual and social progress’ as the laws of history unveil a movement towards, for instance, greater freedom and, like the discoveries of the laws of nature, establish progressive floors ‘beneath which man can no longer sink’.10 Insofar as this parallelism and movement fail, the notion of progress reaches a crisis and ‘leads Translator’s Introduction ix to the suggestion that we should return’ in the form of a repentance with an eye towards redemption.11 It is for this reason that political phi- losophy ‘is today in need of a critical study of its history’, and that this history ‘presupposes that one understand the great thinkers of the past as they understood themselves’ in order to redeem our own world with a fuller knowledge of those political ideas that both inform our world and should have been able to sink into inherited knowledge if progress were not in crisis.12 For Zarka, if this return is not precisely the mark of historicism insofar as it does not approach the history of political philosophy as a relativistic engagement of a series of equally valid ideas engaged from the distance of an objective observer, its interest in a repentant return to that history fails to take up political philosophical concepts in a philosophical manner. If Skinner fails to attend to both of Zarka’s understandings of thinking philosophically, Strauss primarily fails to attend to Zarka’s second understanding of thinking philosophically because either he does not think or he refuses to acknowledge that he is engaged in interpretation. Strauss’s careful historical analyses, critical though they may be, still presuppose an understanding of the philosophical concepts at hand as the thinkers themselves under- stood them, and thus at least obliquely adjure responsibility for the interpretation, the philosophical thinking in which they are engaged. It is in fidelity to both his understandings of thinking philosophi- cally that Zarka will explain, in La décision métaphysique de Hobbes, that his interest is in ‘putting the whole of the work into motion, not in order to repeat it, but in order to rethink it’.13 Whereas Strauss does not claim to be engaged in the interpretive work of rethinking the concepts of the history of political philosophy, for Zarka such a philosophical or speculative approach to those concepts is indeed the only way to give those concepts the full historical appreciation they deserve. That Zarka’s work offers a methodological alternative to the reading of the history of political philosophy from what is more standard in the English- speaking world means making his work more avail- able to English speakers is important. That his alternative involves a non-r eductive, speculative and philosophical approach to the history of philosophy means he offers a philosophical methodology that should be taken seriously in its own right. Finally, that, here, this non- reductive approach shows us some of the crucial concepts that Hobbes

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.