ebook img

Great Dialogue of Nature and Space PDF

215 Pages·1970·7.671 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Great Dialogue of Nature and Space

THE GREAT DIALOGUE OF NATURE AND SPACE Yves Simon the great ideas of mankind on the understanding of nature, time, space and the philosophy of science The Great Dialogue of Nature and Space Yves Simon Edited by Gerard J. Dalcourt jsixAGI BOOKS, INC. 33 Buckingham Dr. Albany, New York 12208 Copyright © 1970 by Paule Y. Simon Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 78-121000 SBN 87343-035-2 Manufactured in the United States of America by the Hamilton Printing Co. BOOKS BY YVES SIMON Introduction a l’ontologie du connaitre Critique de la connaissance morale La Campagne d’Ethiopie et la pensee politique Fran^aise Trois lemons sur le travail Nature and Functions of Authority La grande crise de la Republique Fran^aise The March to Liberation Prevoir et savoir Community of the Free Philosophy of Democratic Government Freedom of Choice A General Theory of Authority The Tradition of Natural Law Freedom and Community The Great Dialogue of Nature and Space CONTENTS EDITOR’S PREFACE xiii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS xvii I THE GREAT DIALOGUE OF NATURE AND SPACE First main character is Aristotle, 1. Importance of recent research on him, 2. Second main character is Descartes, 3. Both wanted to develop a true science and philosophy of nature, 4. History of the “saving the appearances’’ theory, 5. It is rejected by both Aristotle and Descartes, 8. The notions of place, order and goodness, 9. Descartes adopted a mathematical notion of order, 10. Aristotle’s view of the sciences, 10. Mathematics not a natural science, 11. Des¬ cartes’ mathematization of nature, 13. Cartesian roots of Idealism, 14. Main differences between Aristotle and Des¬ cartes, 17. II HOW WE EXPLAIN NATURE Wonder is the beginning of science, 21. So, art may serve well as an introduction to philosophy, 22. Materialism is the everlasting answer to the problem of change, 22. Mean¬ ings of materialism, 23. The importance of the anti-posi¬ tivist, Meyerson, 24. The early positivists, 24. Comte, 25. Mach, 26. Meyerson’s notion of scientific explanation, 27. Difficulties encountered in the interpretation of philosophers, 28. Meyerson’s Identity and Reality, 29. Materialism is Parmenidean, 30. The kinds of change, 30. Meanings of motion, 33. vii Vlll Contents III THE SCIENCE AND PHILOSOPHY OF INERTIA Both Aristotle and Descartes with all the mechanists grant local motion a privileged position, 37. Descartes rejected the Aristotelian notion of motion in favor of a mathematical one, 37. Its fundamental feature is homogeneity, 39. Dif¬ ficulties involved by it, 41. Philosophical implications of the principle of inertia, 43. The Galilean-Cartesian revolu¬ tion, 44. Philosophical interpretation of inertia still a ques¬ tion, 46. Evolution of Maritains’s views on inertia, 47. The privilege of local motion in Aristotle results from his theory of contrariety, 50. It is further based on the continuity of motion that is entailed by the homogenity of quantity, 53. Main differences between Descartes and Aristotle, 54. IV THE PHILOSOPHY OF CHANGE Aristotle defined motion in metaphysical terms, 59. Meyer- son’s misinterpretation of the Aristotelian notion of potency, 60. The meaning of potency, 61. The logic of analogical terms like act and potency, 63. Motion as an imperfect act, 66. Aristotle’s examples of perfect acts, 67. Peirce, on the contrary, considered thought to be only an action in motion, 69. A further illustration: the difference between a painter and a philosopher, 70. Motion involves two rela¬ tions of potentiality, 71. Bergson’s attempt to grasp the reality of motion, 71. The difference between arrestation and motion as exemplified in artistic activity, 73. Another example: Zeno’s arrow, 74. The basic alternatives are a teleological Aristotelianism and an anti-teleological mecha¬ nism, 74. Meyerson’s notion of teleology as an irrational, 77. His notion of reason seems similar to Kant’s, 78. And to Polanyi’s, 74. Teleological explanations of nature are neces¬ sary but possible only to a limited extent, 80. The problem is whether motion is a univocal or analogous concept, 81. Aristotle considered it analogous, 82. The general criterion of analogy applied to motion, 82. The broader concept of motion, 83. Why philosophers use terms in extended senses, 83. In its broader senses motion is a metaphorical term, 84. The difference between contemplation in God and in crea¬ tures, 85. But activity is an analogy of proper propor¬ tionality, 86. Contents ix V THE REAL AND THE IDEAL IN NATURE The problem of the reality of motion, 89. Our concept of motion has a unity that is not supplied by the real itself, 90. The same is true of time, 91. It is also true of non- corporeal multitudes, 92. This helps explain the rise of idealism, 93. This problem of motion is an instance of the broader one of beings of reasons, 93. The meaning of “being of reason,” 94. Logic is concerned primarily with them, 95. They should not be confused with psychological realities, 97. The meaning of “object,” 98. The relation between logic and the real, 98. The degradation of logic, 99. Mathe¬ matical entities may also be beings of reason, 101. And they always imply a condition of reason, 101. The myth of mathematics, 102. The problem of abstraction versus con¬ struction, 103. It was falsified by the empiricists, 104. Metaphysics also has its beings of reason, 105. Beings of reason without a foundation in reality, 105. Relations may also be beings of reason, 106. The unity of motion is a being of reason, 107. This view does not entail the subjectivizing of nature, 109. The error of confusing time as real and as a being of reason, 109. VI PLACE AND SPACE The meaning of place and space: continuation of the Aristotelico-Cartesian dialogue, 113. Modern thinkers tend to consider space a primitive notion, 113. But Aristotle did not, 114. Aristotle’s categories and place, 114. His theory of place is the main one, 115. It is based on the fact of anti-metastasis, 115. The relation of philosophy to facts, 115. Aristotle’s notion of place, 116. His final elaboration of it, 117. His classic definition of it, 118. The motionlessness of place entails difficulties, 118. As a result, scientists prefer to speak of space, 119. The relation between place and space, 119. Space may be real or a being of reason, 114. Space and idealism, 121. For Descartes there are no natural places, 121. Aristotle and teleology, 122. For him finality involved place being natural, 123. The teleology of place is relative to the universe, 123. The Stoics, 123. The Stoic universe, 124. Aristotle’s relation to the Stoics, 125. Sum¬ mary, 125. Conclusion, 126. X Contents VII TIME The Aristotelian discussion of time is basic, 129. Analysis of Aristotle’s procedure, 129. The problem of the reality of time, 131. Time is a being of reason, 131. Time not identical with motion, 132. Time as duration, 132. Dura¬ tion with and without motion, 133. Activity and duration without motion are qualitatively supreme but brief, 133. Notion of duration is analogous, 134. Usefulness of poets on the subject of time, 136. Newtonian and Kantian time a simulacrum, 136. VIII PHILOSOPHERS AND FACTS I. The Notion of Empirical Science. Ambiguity of the terms “empirical science” and “deductive science,” 139. The points of view from which the various sciences may be said to be rational or empirical, 139. Since all sciences are based on facts, the problem is to determine the nature of the facts on which philosophy is founded, 144. II. The Notion of Fact. Facts are empirical absolutes, 144. The differentiation of the various sorts of facts, 145. It is impossible to incor¬ porate into philosophy a scientific fact as such, 149. III. The Myth of a Philosophy Based on Scientific Facts. Scientism is rife among scientists, 149. It has also been adopted by various philosophers, 150. As Bergson has shown, it is sophistic, 151. IV. Common, Scientific and Philosophical Ex¬ perience. All the fundamental philosophical facts are derived from common experience, 153. But many vulgar facts are not philosophical ones, 154. Philosophical facts may also be derived from scientific experience, 155. The establish¬ ment of moral facts, 158. IX SCIENCE, SCIENTISM AND REALISM I. Epistemological Pluralism. Scientism and its opponents, 163. Philosophical disciplines are the most truly scientific, 165. Science has evolved pluralistically, 166. The reaction of various Thomists, 167. Scientism the counterpart of ontological integralism, 169. Pluralism justified by the analogy of being, 169. II. The Reality of Scientific Objects. Some apologists make use of a faulty epistemology, 170. Contents xx Some principles of criticism, 171. Philosophy seeks to know the real just as it is, 172. The problem of scientific theories of structure, 173. The physicist as such seeks the real but as mathematician does not, 174. III. Philosophical Experi¬ ence. The philosopher must establish his own facts, 177. X CHANCE AND DETERMINISM IN PHILOSOPHY AND SCIENCE I. Chance. Chance for the physicists, 181. And for com¬ mon sense, 181. And for Cournot, 183. Common sense view is governed by practical concerns, 183. II. Chance and Determinism. Indeterminacy presupposes determinacy, 184. Contingent beings have an historical necessity, 185. Some have claimed for them an essential necessity, 185. But chance events do not have a real cause, 186. Why rationalists deny the reality of chance, 187. Common sense explanations of chance, 188. Chance and providence, 190. III. Chance on the Microphysical Level. Chance here plays a greater role, 190. So, statistical laws replace causal ones, 191. This constitutes perhaps the most radical of all scientific revolu¬ tions, 192. It has led some to deny any order in the world, 194. IV. Indeterminism in Physics. Different philosophical frames of reference possible, 195. Determinism for the physicists, 197. Physics’ “Crisis of Indeterminism,” 198. Philosophic consequences, 198. V. Philosophy within Sci¬ ence. Planck’s realism, 200. Antinomic tendencies of scien¬ tists, 202. Two states of the philosophy of nature, 203. Im¬ portance of cosmic images, 203. EDITOR’S PREFACE Yves Simon was born in Cherbourg in 1903. Despite a child¬ hood illness which left him lame, he pursued his studies vigor¬ ously. After attending the Lycee Louis Le Grand in Paris, he did graduate work at the University of Paris where, besides tak¬ ing his licenciate in letters, he also received a diploma of higher studies in philosophy and a certificate of studies in the sciences. After four years in medical school he decided to dedicate him¬ self totally to philosophy and so went on to take his licenciate and then his doctorate in philosophy at the Catholic Institute in Paris. After teaching for eight years at the Catholic University of Lille, he was invited in 1938 to the University of Notre Dame, where he stayed for ten years. He then joined the Committee of Social Thought of the University of Chicago Graduate School, where he taught until 1959 when illness forced his retirement. During his whole teaching career he was also in great demand as a lecturer; the reasons why this was so are well exemplified by his Aquinas Lecture at Marquette on The Nature and Func¬ tions of Authority and the Charles Walgreen Lectures at the University of Chicago, entitled Philosophy of Democratic Government. They manifest the same qualities which made him one of the great teachers of our time: depth and clarity of vision combined with a flashing lucidity. He died in 1961. Simon’s voluminous output deals mainly with three areas: political philosophy, metaphysics and ethics. Especially note¬ worthy are his Introduction a I’ontologie du connaitre, Critique Xlll

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.