GOTTLOB FREGE The Arguments of the Philosophers EDITOR: TED HONDERICH The purpose of this series is to provide a contemporary assessmenta nd history of the entire course of philosophical thought. Each book constitutes a detailed, critical introduction to the work of a philosopher of major influence and significance. Plato J. C. B. Gosling Augustine Christopher Kinvan The PtwocvaticP bilosopks Jonathan Barnes Plotinus Lloyd P Gerson TbeS~-@ics R. J. Hankinson Socratu Gerasimos Xenophon Santas Be&&y George Pitcher DesEartes Margaret Dauler Wilson Hobbs Tom Sore11 Lxx&e Michael Ayers Spinoza R. J, Delahunty Btntbatn Ross Harrison Hme Barry Stroud Butler Terence Penelhum John Smart Mill John Skorupski TbornasR eid Keith Lehrer Kant Ralph C. S. Walker Htgd M. J. Inwood Scbopenbauer D. W. Hamlyn Kierkegaard Alastair Hannay Nicmrchc Richard Schacht Karl Marx Allen W. Wood Got& Prcgc Hans D. Sluga Meinong Reinhardt Grossmann Hl/sscrl David Bell G. E. Mm Thomas Baldwin Wttgenttcin Robert J. Fogelin Russdl Mark Sainsbury W&m Jatm Graham Bird P&m Christopher Hookway Santayana Timothy L. S. Sprigge Dewy J. E. Tiles Bergson A. R. Lacey J. L.. At&n G. J. Warnock Karl Popper Anthony O’Hear Ayer John Foster Sarttv Peter Caws GOTTLOB FREGE The Argzlments of the Philosophers Hans D. Sluga London and New York First published 1980 by Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd This edition reprinted in hardback 1999 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Rotrtlea’gei s an imprint of the Tayior G Francis Gro44p 0 1980 Hans D. Sluga Printed and bound in Great Britain by Antony Rowe Ltd. Chippenham, Wiltshire All rights reserved. No part of rhis book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, ot in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library CataIogtdng in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Cong*eJsC ataloguing in Ptlbliration Data A catalogue record for this book has been requested ISBN 0-415-20374-O ISBN O-41 5-20392-9 (set) Publisher’s note The publisher has gone to great lengths to ensure the quality of this reprint but points out that some imperfections in the original book may be apparent. To ask historically means this: to release the happening resting and bound in the question and to set it in motion. Martin Heideggw Contents Preface page ix Introduction I I Analytic philosophy: a f&miIy tree I 2 The non-historical character of analytic pbihsopby 2 3 How analytic philosophy misinterprsts its own history 4 4 Two pbilosopbid conceptionso f kznguage 6 I Philosophy in Question 8 I Tbe the phases of ninetcwtth-century pbilosopby 8 2 Logic in Getvnan pbilosopby 10 3 Tbe trinmpb of iakdism 12 4 Pbihsopby in transition 15 5’ Tbe emergenceo f naturalism I7 6 Grnppe3 hgmistic naturalism I9 7 Czolbe3 pbysiologiurl psycbologism 26 8 Tbe ahline of naturahm 32 II Philosophical Reconstruction 35 I New mownents of he-nineteenth-century pbihsopby 35 2 Ftvge’s jkndational intcmrts 41 3 Ptvge’s pwBegrit5schrifi writings 44 4 Tmna%lenbuq and tbe iaha of a Iogid kanguage 48 5 Lotze’s coweption of a ptwv logic 52 6 Tbe in+nce of Leibnix and Kknt on Prege’s tbongbt 58 7 bgicd f-/km as tbe root of tbe analytic tradition 61 III A Lmnguage of Pure Thought 65 I Frcgc’s iaha of a Begrifkhrift 65 2 c,Ogical symboh2m and ksngwge 71 3 Frege’s Proparitiona~ logic 76 4 Tbe ejection of subject and prediute 82 vii CONTENTS 5 Frege’s logid notion of a function 85 6 Tbe anaIy.ris of general sentences 87 7 The priority of judgments over concepts 90 IV In Search of Logical Objects 96 I Frege’s metbodologikal critique of mathematics 96 2 The strategy of Frege’s anti-empiricism 100 i Logical laws as univcrJal 108 4 &g&al laws as laws of truth 112 5 Prcge’s Lotzcan notion of objtztiuity 117 6 Frege’s mncept of an objtrt 121 7 The logical anaIysis of natural numbers 123 V The Analysis of Meaning 129 I The akvelopment of Frcgc’s views in the 1890s 129 2 The t&ion between a thy and its conttitutizrc concepts 130 3 The assignment of loghal structure I34 4 Concepts as functions I37 5 Functions and value-ranges 144 6 Value-rangcJ and set theory 146 7 The logiurl jnst#ication of w&e-range I49 8 Truth as the rcftmn of sentences I57 VI The End of Logicism 162 I Russell’s contradiction 162 2 Fmge’s way out 165 3 The stitrb fw new fkzdations 170 4 Russell 176 5 CarnaP 178 6 Wittgenstein 181 Notes 187 Index I99 . . : VIII Preface This boc#t is the result of a long development. For almost twenty years my interest in Frege has been part of a journey fmm Munich through Oxford and London to Berkeley. At each stage my thoughts about Frege were influenced by teachers, colleagues, and students. When it comes to acknowledging their help, I feel at a loss to describe it adequately. My interest in Prege was aroused by one of my htst philosophy teachers, Wilhelm Britzlmayr of the University of Munich. A close friend of Heinrich Scholz-the collector of Frege’s writings when they were hugely ignored- Britzhnayr had gathered a circle of students to work on Frege’s logic and philosophy of mathematics. In this circle I first learnt to admire Frege’s clarity of thought and precision of style. At Oxford, in Michael Dummett’s seminar, I became acquainted with a more probing, critical examination of Frege’s thought. The continuing philosophical debate drew my attention for the first time to Frege’s theory of meaning. For some time my reading of Frege was strongly colored by Dummett’s tastes and outlook. If I find myself now in disagmment with some of his churns, I must still acknowledge that he has taught me an independence of mind that i value. When I went to University College London, my friends Hide Ishiguro, Jerry Cohen, and Richard Wollheim provided new stimuli by making me think about Frege in relation to Leibnizian rationalism, nineteenth-century materialism, and late-nineteenth-century idealism. As editor of the series in which this book is now appearing, Ted Hot&rich first encourPgcd me to undertake the project of writing it and then nursed it along with infinite patience. Of particuhu importance for me was the contact with Imre Lakatos and Paul Feyerabend. Their critical assessment of the prevailing philosophy of science and their insistence that science could be understood only as a historical phenomenon raised in my mind the question whether a similar criticism could not be made of the account analytic philosophers had given of philosophical theorizing. ix PREFACE These teflections were of the greatest importance in the formation of the outlook adopted in this book. In Berkeley this direction of thought was reinforced by Barry Stroud, who encouraged me in the study of Wittgenstein and helped me to understand his ideas more deeply. He and other colleagues and friends, in particular Hubert Dreyfus and John Searle, prodded me on with encouragement and critical questions. Berkeley in the early 1970s was a place of intellectual turmoil. I believe that being there forced me to think more radically about Frege and the analytic tradition that has come out of his work. The demands of my students fix clarification and elaboration proved immensely helpful in the process. Among those students Peter Eggenberger perhaps most deserves notice fix his unfailing interest and his many helpful suggestions. As I look over the final result it seems to me that I can recognize in it also the subtle influence of Oskar Becker, my very first teacher in philosophy. I remember with admiration his profound scholarship in logic and mathematics, combined with a deep appreciation of Heidegger’s historical understanding of the human world. By recording these various influences I am trying to make clear that my book has a wider focus than is usual in the literature on Frege. Given the role Fregean considerations have played and continue to play in logic, the philosophy of mathematics, and the philosophy of language, it is difficult to write comprehensively about Frege’s thought. In the pursuit of such a comprehensive picture I have tried to take into account as much of the existing literature as possible, but I have not tried to detail and discuss all the important issues raised in it. Throughout the book I have bund it necessary to refer back to Michael Dummett’s writings on Frege, both because they reflect an important stage in the current discussion of the topic and also because I consider the shortcomings of his account sympto- matic. However, my discussion does not presuppose detailed knowledge of his extensive and difficult writings. One chief difIixence in my treatment of Frege as compared with Dummett’s and that of most of the literature is its greater historical orientation. I hope to show that this approach generates a sharper and more coherent picture of Frege’s thought, a picture that di&rs from the predominant one in substance and not only in minor additions and revisions. I also hope that this reassessment will be of more than historical interest. It seems to me plausible to assume that we always understand ourselves only historically, i.e., as creatures who have reached the present moment via a certain route. If one could show that we have reached that moment along a path different from the one we believe we have traveled, that would deeply change our understanding of who we are. My purpose in trying to reassess the roots of the analytic tradition is to change the current self-interpretation of that tradition. X
Description: