ebook img

Globalisation: Sovereignty or Anarchy Beyond Modernity? PDF

22 Pages·2002·0.06 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Globalisation: Sovereignty or Anarchy Beyond Modernity?

EUROPEAN UNIVERSITY INSTITUTE, FLORENCE DEPARTMENT OF POLITICAL AND SOCIAL SCIENCES EUI Working Paper SPS No. 2002/10 Globalisation: Sovereignty or Anarchy Beyond Modernity? CHIARA BOTTICI BADIA FIESOLANA, SAN DOMENICO (FI) All rights reserved. No part of this paper may be reproduced in any form without permission of the author. [email protected] © 2002 Chiara Bottici Printed in Italy in November 2002 European University Institute Badia Fiesolana I – 50016 San Domenico (FI) Italy GLOBALISATION: SOVEREIGNTY OR ANARCHY BEYOND MODERNITY? * by Chiara Bottici According to a common view, globalisation implies a loss of control over our lives. By depleting the decision-making capacity of individuals and governments, it questions one of the basic conditions for the exercise of politics. Whereas some celebrate this new condition as the triumph of the global market over politics, others point to the danger that it implies for the achievements of modernity. Both sides, however, conceive of globalisation as a kind of natural phenomenon taking place above our heads and with no possibility of arrest. Consequently, it is often presented as a condition of disorder. Zygmut Bauman, for instance, argues that since social order means being able to keep things under control - as has been the case during the modern era, globalisation is simply another name for the new world disorder, for the fact that our destiny is slipping out of our hands.1 The diffusion of this perception of impotence is the starting point of this paper. However, I will suggest that this condition is not the result of the decline of politics as such, but that it is – rather - a sign of the crisis of its modern version. Modern thinkers have conceived of politics as the privileged place for the ambivalent pursuit of rational mastering and individual autonomy that has been described as the distinctive feature of modernity, and they have identified the sovereign state as the main agency in charge of its implementation: once this latter was brought to a crisis point, the impression was that politics was declining altogether. As a privileged point of view to show how globalisation has questioned the modern conception of politics, I will focus on the sovereignty versus anarchy dichotomy. By this expression I mean the tendency of modernity to conceive of politics in terms of a dichotomous view which separates its internal domain, subject to sovereignty, from the external one, dominated by mere anarchy. I will start by analysing the dichotomy “sovereignty versus anarchy”, illustrating the crucial role that it has played within modern political theory (§.1). I will then move on to globalisation and to the issue of its relationship with political modernity, arguing that the former has crucially questioned the latter (§.2). Subsequently, I will try to demonstrate that globalisation, together with political modernity, has also undermined the conceptual apparatus through which this latter conceived of itself, and particularly the sovereignty versus anarchy dichotomy. Following the * I am grateful to Carol Gould, Gianfranco Poggi, and Peter Wagner for their comments on earlier drafts of this paper. I am also indebted to the “Democracy in the age of globalisation” research group, directed by Furio Cerutti (Universita’ di Firenze), for support and critical feedback. 1 See Baumann 1998 p. 67. 1 distinction between the regulative and constitutive roles played by this dichotomy in modern political thought, I will try to show that globalisation has placed both the former (§.3) and the latter (§.4) in question. 1. Sovereignty and anarchy: two dichotomous concepts As first pointed out by Thomas Kuhn, every theory operates within the boundaries of a scientific paradigm whose assumptions may be not recognised immediately, but which are adopted as an unquestioned research framework. These presuppositions provide the conceptual coordinates of the problems that are important for researchers, and at the same time they then orient towards a possible set of solutions. Only during scientific revolutions are these assumptions questioned - by encountering their intrinsic limits, scholars open the path for the onset of a new scientific paradigm.2 This remark also seems to hold true for political theory. The conceptual apparatus by which political thinkers tried to capture the reality they were witnessing operated within specific assumptions, working through the centuries as guidelines, as the boundaries within which thought was expected to move. In this paper, I argue that one of these unquestioned presuppositions was the dichotomy of sovereignty versus anarchy. Stemming from the early theorists of modern state, this assumption operated in Western political thought by identifying the problems which had to be faced as well as the main strategies for solving them. To support this view, I will first show in what sense the pair sovereignty versus anarchy can be considered as a dichotomy, moving on to analyse its relationship with modern political thought.3 According to Norberto Bobbio, a dichotomy is a pair of concepts acting to divide a universe into two jointly exhaustive and reciprocally exclusive spheres, i.e. such that all the members of our universe belong to one of them and, at the same time, those who belong to one cannot belong contemporarily to the other. A dichotomy also has to be principal, in the sense that other conceptual couples can converge in it. The two concepts may then either be defined one independently of the other, or the first may be defined in a positive and the second in a negative 2 See Kuhn 1962. 3 Among those emphasising the importance of this dichotomy, see Ashley 1988a and 1988b. Even if I share Ashley’s interest in the construction of knowledge, my analysis differs from his postmodernist approach because I do not aim at putting forward an holistic critique of modernity as such, but rather at analysing how some of its conceptual tools have worked through the centuries. As a consequence, I do not share his method, aiming at showing that such a dichotomy is the result of the “heroic practice” of the Western reasoning man and his “narrative of domestication of politics” (Ashley 1988b, p.103). On the contrary, I hold that it is not a prerogative of the modern Western rationality to think in terms of dichotomies. 2 way; in this case, the first is held to be the strong term, whilst the second, the derivate, is called the weak term.4 Let us move to the pair sovereignty versus anarchy. These constitute a dichotomy for they are able to divide the universe of politics into two jointly exhaustive spheres - so that what does not belong to the domain of sovereignty is commonly considered to belong to that of anarchy – and, at the same time, they are mutually exclusive, because what is included in the first cannot be part of the second. As we can see, sovereignty is the strong term, i.e. it is defined positively, whilst anarchy is usually defined negatively as the lack of sovereignty. We may also argue that both terms stem from the two faces of sovereignty, the internal and the external: on the one hand, there is the internal domain of sovereign power which does not recognise any superior power; on the other, we have the external anarchical domain of equally sovereign powers facing each other.5 According to its classical formulation, by “sovereignty” we mean the existence of a supreme power, which is defined territorially and has the exclusive right to resort to force both internally, against private violence, and externally, against other sovereign entities.6 From its very first formulations the concept of sovereignty was strictly linked with that of the state, where this latter, following Max Weber, may be defined as an institution characterised by the (tendentially) successful claim of the monopoly of legitimate physical coercion over a specific territory.7 Sovereignty, as the claim to superiorem non recognoscens power within a specific territory, is indeed the political and juridical concept which supported the modern state in its fight against the two universalistic coordinates of the Pope and the Emperor. Whilst the medieval system was characterised by a set of overlapping and interwoven authorities, the modern organization of power appears as a system of homogeneous political entities which are territorially defined and aspire to the exclusive exercise of power.8 This is an absolute novelty in history: before modern times no power has ever presented itself as claiming exclusive sovereign power within a clearly defined territory.9 However, political power need not be territorial 4 See Bobbio 1985, p.3. 5 Among recent contributions on the concept of sovereignty see Bartelson 1995, Biersteker 1996, Ferrajoli 1997, Gilson 1984, Hinsley 1966, Hoffmann 1998, Klein 1974, Krasner 1999, Weber 1995. 6 See Bodin 1583. 7 See Weber 1919, p.55. 8 There is a huge literature on this topic. See for instance recent contributions by Matteucci 1993,Pierson 1996, Poggi 1990, Spruyt 1994. For a more philosophical approach see Morris 1998. 9 One could here object that modern federalism represents an alternative to this conception, since the federal power cannot claim exclusiveness of power. However, in my view, modern federal polities were still completely within the paradigm of sovereignty: if we look at sovereign power from the point of view of participants, the power may appear as shared, balanced and divided, but if we look at it from the outside, i.e. from the point of view of an external observer, it will still reveal a certain unitary character, in the sense that it is always possible to identify an 3 and need not be territorially fixed. Furthermore, even where systems of rule are territorial, and even where territoriality is relatively fixed, the prevailing concept of territory need not entail mutual exclusion – the archetype of non-exclusive territorial rule being medieval Europe with its patchwork of geographically interwoven and overlapping rights of government.10 These two features of modern power - territoriality and exclusivity - create the conditions for a dichotomous view of politics, presenting the two spheres of sovereignty and anarchy as mutually exclusive. Once political power began to be conceived of as corresponding to a territorially defined political space and as recognising no superiors within it, i.e. as internally sovereign, then it appeared unavoidable to conceive of the external relationships between these political entities as the anarchic clash among equally sovereign powers. According to the conceptual context, anarchy may be understood either in its etymological meaning as a mere absence of government or - with a semantic slide - as a condition of chaos. This semantic slide is in fact typical of modern political thought. By presenting sovereignty as the only alternative not just to the absence of government, but also to chaos, some modern political theorists have pushed the concept of anarchy from its etymological meaning towards the idea of a condition of disorder from which we must escape. That is to say, in their attempt to provide a justification for sovereign power, they present sovereignty as the only alternative to disorder and, thus, as the sine qua non condition of social order, i.e. as the necessary – if not sufficient - condition of it. The thought of Thomas Hobbes seems in this case to be paradigmatic: in his attempt to provide a justification for political obligation, he presents a condition of anarchy, both domestic and international, as necessarily implying chaos and disorder. Witness to the English civil war, Hobbes devoted all his energy to showing that sovereignty was the only alternative to anarchy, where this is the defining feature of the category of the state of nature. Since, according to his pessimistic anthropology, he conceived this latter as a condition of war, where isolated individuals moved by antagonistic passions were continuously exposed to the danger of violent death, sovereignty was presented as an alternative not only to the absence of government – anarchy in its etymological meaning, but also to a condition of chaos where homo homini lupus: only by associating with each other and placing themselves in awe of a sovereign power through a social covenant (respectively, pactum unionis and pactum subjectionis) can individuals escape the state of nature. ultimate authority, no matter in what way and at which level this latter is exercised. The very fact that modern federalism has been unable to go beyond the dichotomy federation versus confederation is, in my view, a clear a sign that it was still within the paradigm of sovereignty. 10 See Ruggie 1993, p.149. 4 Inaugurating a long tradition, Hobbes then applied this description of the state of nature to international relations.11 After saying that although there had never been any time wherein particular men were in a condition of war one against another, he argued that this was what normally happened in relationships among sovereign states.12 Because states were not subject to any common power, they all enjoyed the same freedom to do everything that they judged to be in their own interest as individuals enjoyed in the state of nature. We may now ask why, if the state of international anarchy is analogous to the state of nature, states are not induced, like individuals, to exit from such a condition. Hobbes’ answer was clear: the sovereignty of individual states, which determines a “posture of warre” in relations among them, was the same that enabled them to maintain that condition of peace where social life could flourish internally.13 According to Hobbes, then, sovereignty, which guaranteed peace within states, necessarily led the condition of international anarchy. It was no chance that Hobbes devoted only few pages of his main work, the Leviathan, to international relations: his problem was civil, not international, anarchy. As we shall see, this is a very common approach in modern political philosophy, however different the single conceptions of anarchy may be. The sovereign state is more or less implicitly assumed as the telos and perfect model of political life. Political theorists seem to dedicate all their energy to the discussion of issues surrounding it, whilst international relations seem to deserve only secondary attention, an appendix chapter. One may now object that Hobbes’ conception is not representative of the contractualist tradition as a whole and even less so of modern political theory. I will try to answer this problem in two steps. Concentrating on only those aspects which are relevant, I will first analyse the relationship between Hobbes’ thought and contractualism and, second, its relationship with modern political theory. This will enable us to introduce a distinction between the regulative and constitutive roles of the dichotomy sovereignty versus anarchy, which will be the starting point of the second part of this paper. As many scholars have noticed, Hobbes occupies a particular position within modern contractualism. The conceptual syntax by which this tradition is defined (state of nature, civil society and social contract) can have very different outcomes according to the philosophical and anthropological context. However, we could argue that lying behind the dichotomy between civil society versus state of nature, which is defining to this tradition, there is always the dichotomy sovereignty versus anarchy. Thus, however much conceptions of the state of nature may differ (sometimes being considered as a war of everybody against everybody, sometimes 11 On the influence of the concept of state of nature over international relations theories see Beitz 1979. 12 See Hobbes 1651, I, 13. 13 See Hobbes 1651, I, 13, 5. For a detailed discussion of this point see Bull 1981. 5 as an imperfect social condition, and sometimes as the original phase of humankind when man was free and happy) this remains a condition from which we must exit in order to enter a civil society characterised by the existence of a sovereign power. Be this the absolute sovereignty of Thomas Hobbes, the limited type proposed by John Locke or, lastly, the popular sovereignty of Jean Jacques Rousseau, the establishment of sovereignty is always justified by contraposition with a state of nature that, however positively it is conceived, is still viewed as a condition of anarchy. This is the reason why the dichotomy civil society/ state of nature has such a normative potential: by opposing sovereignty to the disadvantages of an anarchic state of nature - ranging from the uncertainty of law enforcement (Locke) to the danger of violent death (Hobbes), it provides grounds for political obligation, i.e. a justification for loyalty towards the sovereign power. In modern contractualism, then, the dichotomy sovereignty versus anarchy plays a rather crucial role. First, it points to the relevant problems, i.e. those which deserve most attention - among these the anarchy problematique, that is to say, the fact that anarchy started to be conceived of as a problem because it was viewed as implying social disorder, and the related issue of the justification of sovereign power. Second, it orients towards certain guidelines in order to outline specific solutions – as is the case, for example, of the contraposition between state of nature/civil society. I will call the former the constitutive role, because by identifying the significant questions it contributes towards drawing the contours of the discipline, whilst I call the latter the regulative role because it consists in orienting towards a set of possible solutions. Let us now move to modern political theory. Even if we admit that the dichotomy sovereignty versus anarchy played the kind of role described above within contractualism, it is difficult to see how this could hold true for modern political theory as a whole. A first remark concerns the importance of this tradition of thought. It occupies a crucial place within modernity, not so much because of the language through which it is expressed - inherited from previous traditions - as because of the central place it accords to proper modern issues. From this point of view, we can argue that with respect to the set of theories usually indicated as “modern political theory”, the dichotomy sovereignty versus anarchy plays a constitutive role, i.e. it operates by pointing out which problems are relevant. Most of the issues raised by modern political theorists are, for instance, related to some extent with the issue of sovereignty - how to organise it, how to limit it, how to make it accountable, and so on. However much particular points of view may differ, sovereign statehood is always the necessary assumption, and if it is not the solution to everything, it is at least the starting point. The lesser attention devoted by Hobbes to international relations was not unusual. As Martin Wight has pointed out, the real question must focus on why there is no tradition of international theory, certainly none as conspicuous as that of political theory. In my view, if political philosophy seems to have rejected taking international relations as the subject of its analysis, this is because it devotes all of 6 its energies to the sovereign state: this latter appeared for centuries to be the culminating and exhaustive point of political life, beyond which there only remain mere “relations”. This is also the reason why, according to Wight, political theory is usually held to be a theory of “good life”, whilst International Relations is considered as a theory of survival: what is the extreme case (revolution or civil war) within state borders, is between states the rule. In other words, the international is the domain of repetition where no progress is possible, so that the appropriate point of view is not that of political theory, but that of mere historical interpretation.14 Therefore we can conclude that the dichotomy sovereignty versus anarchy is also principal, in the sense proposed by Bobbio, i.e. it works by recalling other dichotomies such as those we have just seen: internal versus external, progress versus repetition, political theory versus international relations.15 The first of these, which refers to the two faces of sovereignty, is the spatial presupposition of the dichotomy sovereignty /anarchy, whilst the second represents its temporal corollary: inside the sovereign space we can speak of justice, democracy, human rights and progress, while outside there can be only the repetition of the clash between sovereign powers. The third and final dichotomy points instead to the disciplinary boundaries between political theory and international relations. 2. Globalisation and the modern configuration of power Having shown in what sense the two terms sovereignty and anarchy may be said to constitute a dichotomy, and having reconstructed the relation between this latter and modern political theory, I will turn now to the issue of globalisation. I will first briefly delineate my approach to globalisation and to the problem of its relationship with political modernity. Thereby, I will also start arguing that it is not politics as such that is questioned by globalisation, but - rather – politics in its specifically modern version. One of the features of the contemporary globalisation discourse16 is the idea that the mobility of capitals and the trend toward the unification of the labour market are progressively reducing politics to the role of ancilla oeconomiae. Whereas some celebrate this new condition as the victory of the market over politics, others, deprecating it, try to negate its existence by talking of a “myth of globalisation”. Analysing the way in which this myth has spread the neoliberist dogma of the “absence of alternatives”, Pierre Bourdieu tends, for instance to minimise the trend 14 See Wight 1966. One of the main exceptions to this observation is the thinking of Immanuel Kant, who takes relations among states as his primary object of analysis. All the same, we can argue that his fluctuation from the proposal of a Weltrepublik to that of a Völberbund is due to his incapacity to rid himself from the model of the sovereign state. 15 See Walker 1993. 16 By “discorse” I mean a series of linguistic and social practices. 7 toward a single labour market.17 According to Paul Hirst and Grahame Thompson, instead, what we are witnessing is no novelty, but rather an intensification of the internationalisation of economy which started during the belle époque: in their view, not only the globalisation of production – and therefore the role of truly transnational enterprises – but also the globalisation of financial markets – according to many, the hard core of the whole process - is overestimated, for this has been perceptible for more than a century.18 All these approaches share the tendency to look at globalisation in its purely economical aspect – a trend which, paradoxically, unites neoliberists as well as their adversaries. In my view, however, it is not by disputing the existence of the globalisation of economics, or its novelty, that the neoliberist dogma “there are no alternatives” can be questioned. A much more efficient strategy consists in pointing out that economic globalisation is only one side of a process which encompasses all spheres of human life: in this perspective, the “mythical” assumption in the globalisation discourse is in fact the idea of a separation between politics and economics, together with the image of the market as a self-propelling mechanism which can emerge only when politics is left to one side. On the contrary, as Stubbs and Underhill, following Polanyi, argue, a market is a political device to achieve certain outcomes, conferring relatives benefits on some and costs on others in both political and economic terms.19 Therefore, I will look at globalisation in a multidimensional perspective, because it is only in this way that the interplay between economy and the complex institutional framework in which it takes place can emerge. Globalisation, in its numerous aspects – economic, financial, environmental, technological, political and cultural, has created such a situation that events, decisions and activities in one part of the world can have significant consequences for individuals and communities in other quite distant parts of the globe. It has, therefore, been conceived of as a set of processes which shift the spatial form of human organisation and activity to transcontinental and inter-regional patterns of activity, interactions and exercise of power.20 It involves a stretching and deepening of social relations and institutions across space and time such that, on the one hand, day-to-day activities are increasingly influenced by events happening on the other side of the globe and, on the other, the practices and decisions of local groups or communities can have significant global reverberations. The stretching of the social chains of interdependence, which - from Rousseau to Elias – had been identified as the sign of the civilising process, has gone well beyond the West, their birthplace, and tends now to become global in its scope. 17 See Bourdieu 1998 18 See Hirst and Thompson 1997. 19 See Stubbs, Underhill 1994, pg.19. The same line of reasoning is pursued by Hardt and Negri who, by developing their concept of empire, point out that there cannot be any economic system which is not supported by a juridical and political order (Hardt, Negri 2000, pg 9-10) 20 See Mcgrew 1992 or Held, Mcgrew, Goldblatt, Perraton 1999. 8

Description:
According to a common view, globalisation implies a loss of control over our lives. By depleting the decision-making capacity of individuals and governments, it questions one of the basic conditions for the exercise of politics. Whereas some celebrate this new condition as the triumph of the global
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.