ebook img

Genes and Cultures - Stanford University PDF

21 Pages·2003·0.18 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Genes and Cultures - Stanford University

Current Anthropology Volume44,Number1,February2003 (cid:1)2003byTheWenner-GrenFoundationforAnthropologicalResearch.Allrightsreserved0011-3204/2003/4401-0004$3.50 The recent publication of the first draft of the human genome (e.g., Venter et al. 2001, Lander et al. 2001) has ✩ CA FORUM ON broughttopublicattentiontherelationshipbetweentwo concepts, genotype and phenotype—a relationship that ANTHROPOLOGY IN PUBLIC hadpreviouslybeendiscussedlargelybyacademics.The genotype of an organism is encoded in the DNA thatis held in chromosomes and other structures inside its Genes and Cultures cells.Thephenotypeiswhatweareabletoobserveabout that organism’s biochemistry, physiology, morphology, and behaviors. We will use the term “phenome” tocir- cumscribeasetofphenotypeswhosepropertiesandvar- iabilitywewishtostudy.Ourfocuswillbeonthatpart What Creates Our Behavioral ofthehumanphenomethatisdefinedbybehaviorsand Phenome? especiallyonthebehavioralphenome’sconnectionwith the human genome. Our understanding of human behavioral traits has evolved; explanations of the control of those traits of- by Paul Ehrlich and fered50yearsagodifferfromthosemostcommontoday. In prewar decades genetic determinism—the idea that Marcus Feldman1 genes are destiny—had enormous influence on public policyinmanycountries:onAmericanimmigrationand racial policies, Swedish sterilization programs, and, of course,Nazilawsonracialpurity(Ehmann2001,Ehrlich and Feldman 1977, Fisher 2001). Much of this public Acentralthemeofthefloodofliteratureinrecentyearsin“evo- policywasbuiltonsupportfrombiological,medical,and lutionarypsychology”and“behavioralgenetics”isthatmuchor socialscientists(e.g.,Brigham1923,Goddard1917,Ter- evenmosthumanbehaviorhasbeenprogrammedintothehu- mangenomebynaturalselection.Weshowthatthisconclusion man1916),butafterHitler’sgenocidalpoliciesitwasno iswithoutbasis.Evolutionarypsychologyisaseriesof“just-so” longerpoliticallycorrecttofocusonputativehereditary storiesrootedinpartintheerroneousnotionthathumanbeings differences. The fading of genetic determinism was an duringthePleistocenealllivedinthesameenvironmentofevo- understandable reaction to Nazism and related racial, lutionaryadaptation.Behavioralgeneticsisbasedonaconfusion oftheinformationcontainedinatechnicalstatisticcalled“heri- sexual, and religious prejudices which had long been tability”withthecolloquialmeaningoftheterm,exacerbatedby prevalentintheUnitedStatesandelsewhere.Thus,after oversimplificationofstatisticalmodelsforthebehavioralsimi- WorldWarII,itbecamethenorminAmericanacademia larityoftwins.Infact,informationfromtwinstudies,cross-fos- to consider all of human behavior as originating in the tering,sexualbehavior,andtheHumanGenomeProjectmakes itabundantlyclearthatmostinterestingaspectsofthehuman environment—inthewaypeoplewereraisedandtheso- behavioralphenomeareprogrammedintothebrainbytheenvi- cial contexts in which they lived. ronment.Thegeneralconfusioncreatedbythegeneticdetermin- Gradually,though,beginninginthe1960s,bookslike istshashadandwillcontinuetohaveunfortunateeffectson Robert Ardrey’s Territorial Imperative (1966) and Des- publicpolicy. mond Morris’s The Naked Ape (1967) began proposing explanationsforhumanbehaviorsthatwerebiologically reductionist and essentially genetic. Their extreme hereditarianbiasmayhavebeenstimulatedbytherapid progress at that time in understanding of the role of DNA, which spurred interest in genetics in both scien- tists and the public. But perhaps no publication had broadereffectinreestablishinggeneticcredibilityinthe behavioral sciences than Arthur Jensen’s (1969) article “HowMuchCanWeBoostIQ?”Althoughroundlycrit- icizedbyquantitativegeneticistsandshowntobebased on the fraudulent data of Sir Cyril Burt (Kamin 1974), Jensen’s work established a tradition that attempts to allocate to genetics a considerable portion of the varia- tioninsuchhumanbehaviorsasforwhomwevote,how religiousweare,howlikelywearetotakerisks,and,of course, measured IQ and school performance. This tra- dition is alive and well today (e.g., Plomin, Owen and McGuffin 1994, Plomin et al. 1997). Within the normal range of human phenotypic vari- 1.DepartmentofBiologicalSciences,StanfordUniversity,Stanford, Calif.94305-5020,U.S.A.([email protected]). ation, including commonly occurring diseases, the role 87 88 F current anthropology Volume44, Number1, February2003 ofgeneticsremainsamatterofcontroversyevenasmore isaboutthedegreetowhichdifferencesintoday’shuman isrevealedaboutvariationatthelevelofDNA(Pritchard behavioral patterns from person to person, group to 2001, Reich and Lander 2001). Here we would like to group, and society to society are influenced by genetic reexamine the issue of genetics and human behaviorin differences,thatis,aretraceabletodifferencesinhuman light of the enormous interest in the Human Genome geneticendowments.Domen“naturally”wanttomate Project,theexpansionofbehavioralgeneticsasdescribed with as many women as possible while women “natu- above,andtherecentproliferationofbooksemphasizing rally” want to be more cautious in choosing their cop- the genetic programming of every behavior from rape ulatorypartners(Bermant1976,Symons1979,Birkhead (ThornhillandPalmer2000)tothelearningofgrammar 2000;seealsoSmall1993:chap.7)?Istherea“gaygene” (Pinker 1994). The philosopher Helena Cronin and her (Hameretal.1993,Huetal.1995,Riceetal.1999)?Are coeditor,OliverCurry,tellusintheintroductiontoYale human beings “innately” aggressive (Ehrlich 2000: University Press’s “Darwinism Today” series that 210–13)? Are differences in educational achievementor “Darwinian ideas . . . are setting today’s intellectual income “caused” by differences in genes (Bowles and agenda” (1999). In the New York Times,NicholasWade Gintis 2001, Jacoby and Glauberman 1995, Lewontin, (2000) has written that human genes contain the “be- Rose,and Kamin 1984,Taubman1976)?Andarepeople havioralinstructions”for“instinctstoslaughterorshow ofallgroupsgeneticallyprogrammedtobeselfish(Ham- mercy, the contexts for love and hatred, the taste for ilton 1964, Richerson and Boyd 1978)? A critical social obedienceorrebellion—theyarethedeterminantsofhu- issue to keep in mind throughout our discussion is man nature.” what the response of our society would be if we knew the answer to these questions. Two related schools of thought take the view that genetic evolution explains Genes, Cultures, and Behavior muchofthehumanbehavioralphenome;theyareknown as evolutionary psychology and behavioral genetics. Itisincontrovertiblethathumanbeingsareaproductof evolution,butwithrespecttobehaviorthatevolutionary process involves chance, natural selection, and, espe- Evolutionary Psychology cially in the case of human beings, transmission and alteration of a body of extragenetic information called Evolutionary psychology claims that many human be- “culture.” Cultural evolution, a process very different haviors became universally fixed as a result of natural from genetic evolution by natural selection, has played selectionactingduringtheenvironmentofevolutionary acentralroleinproducingourbehaviors(Cavalli-Sforza adaptation (Tooby and Cosmides 1992), essentially the and Feldman 1973, 1981; Ehrlich 2000; Feldman and Pleistocene.Ashortcomingofthisargument,asempha- Cavalli-Sforza 1976; Feldman and Laland 1996). sized by the anthropologist Robert Foley (1995–96),lies Thisisnottosaythatgenesareuninvolvedinhuman in the nonexistence of such an environment. Our an- behavior.Everyaspectofaperson’sphenomeisaproduct cestorslivedinawidediversityofhabitats,andtheim- ofinteractionbetweengenomeandenvironment.Anob- pacts of the many environmental changes (e.g., glacia- viousexampleofgeneticinvolvementinthebehavioral tions)overthepastmillionyearsdifferedgeographically phenome is the degree towhich mostpeopleusevision amongtheirvariedsurroundings.Evolutionarypsychol- to orient themselves—in doing everything from hitting ogists also postulate that natural selection produced a baseball to selecting new clothes for their children. modules (“complex structures that are functionally or- Thisisbecausewehaveevolvedgeneticallytobe“sight ganized for processing information” [Tooby and Cos- animals”—our dominant perceptual system is vision, mides 1992: 33]) in the brain that “tell” us such things with hearing coming in second. Had we, like dogs, as which individuals are likely to cheat, which mates evolved more sophisticated chemical detection, we arelikelytogiveusthebestormostoffspring,andhow might behave very differently in response to the toxic to form the best coalitions (Kurzban, Tooby, and Cos- chemicals in our environment (Ehrlich 2000). The in- mides2001).Thesebrain“modules,”whichareassumed formationinourDNArequiredtoproducethebasicmor- to be biological entities fixed in humans by evolution, phologyandphysiologythatmakesightsoimportantto also have other names often bestowed on them by the ushasclearlybeenmoldedbynaturalselection.Andthe same writers, such as “computational machines,” “de- physical increase in human brain size, which certainly cision-making algorithms,” “specialized systems,” “in- involved a response to natural selection (although the ference engines,” and “reasoning mechanisms” (Du- precise environmental factors causing this selection re- chaine,Cosmides,andTooby2001).Theresearchclaims mainsomethingofamystery[Allman1999,Klein1999]), of evolutionary psychology havebeenheavilycriticized has allowed us to evolve language, a high level of tool by,amongothers,colleaguesinpsychology(e.g.,Bussey use, the ability to plan for the future, and a wide range and Bandura 1999). of other behaviors not seen in other animals. Those critics are correct. There is a general tendency Thus at the very least, genetic evolution both biased for evolutionary psychologists vastly to overestimate ourabilitytoperceivetheworldandgaveusthecapacity how much of human behavior is primarily traceable to to develop a vast culture. But the long-running nature- biologicaluniversalsthatarereflectedinourgenes.One versus-nurturedebateisnotaboutsightversussmell.It reason for this overestimation is the ease with which a ehrlich and feldman Genes and Cultures F 89 little evolutionary story can be invented to explain al- engraved in our genetic makeup is without basis, espe- most any observed pattern of behavior. For example, it cially in light of the enormous cultural differences in seems logical that natural selection would resultinthe sexual preferences. coding of a fear of snakes and spiders into our DNA,as Foranyculture,Ellis’sevolutionaryargumentswould the evolutionary psychologist Steven Pinker thinks require that in past populations of women there were (1997: 386–89). But while Pinker may have genes that DNA-based differences that made some more likely to makehimfearsnakes,astheevolutionistJaredDiamond choose in those ways and others more likely to seek pointsout,suchgenesareclearlylackinginNewGuinea mates with other characteristics. And those that chose natives. As Diamond says, “If there is any single place as Ellis predicts would have to have borne and raised in the world where we might expect an innate fear of morechildrenthatsurvivedtoreproducethanthosewith snakes among native peoples, it would be in New other preferences. Might, for example, a woman who Guinea, where one-third or more of the snake species married a stingy male who kept her barefoot and preg- are poisonous, and certain non-poisonous constrictor nant out-reproduce the wife of a generous and consid- snakesaresufficientlybigtobedangerous.”Yetthereis erate mate? That is the way genetic evolution changes no sign of innate fear of snakes or spiders among the the characteristics of populations over time: by some indigenouspeople,andchildrenregularly“capturelarge geneticvariants’out-reproducingothers.Whenthathap- spiders, singe off the legs and hairs, and eat the bodies. pens, we say that natural selection has occurred. But, The people there laugh at the idea of an inborn phobia unfortunately, there are no data that speak to whether about snakes, and account for the fear in Europeans as there is (or was) genetic variation in human mate pref- a resultof theirstupidityinbeingunabletodistinguish erences—variationin,say,abilitytoevaluatespecifically whichsnakesmightbedangerous”(1993:265).Further- whether a potential mate is “ambitious”—upon which more, there is reason to believe that fear of snakes in selection could be based. And there are no data for any other primates is largely learned as well (Mineka, Keir, population showing that women who seek those char- and Price 1981, Mineka and Cook 1993). acteristics in their sexual partners are more successful Anotherexampleisthesetofpredictionsadvancedby reproductively—arerepresentedbymorechildreninthe BruceEllis(1992)aboutthematingbehaviorthatwould subsequent generation—than women who seek hus- bands with other characteristics.Ellis issimplyconfus- befoundinapreviouslyunknownculture.Thefirstfive ing the preferences of women he knows in his society characteristics that “the average woman in thisculture with evolutionary fitness. willseek...inheridealmate,”hepredicts,are(p.283): 1. He will be dependable, emotionally stable and mature, and kind/consideratetoward her. Behavioral Genetics and Heritability 2. He will be generous. He may communicate a spirit of caring through a willingness to share time Another reason laypersons tend to overestimate how and whatever commodities are valued in this culture much of our behavior is genetically determined derives with the woman in question. from the claims of some scientists that the variation 3. He will be ambitious and perceived by the between individuals in behaviorsisduetotheirgenetic woman in question as clever or intelligent. differences.Oftenthesesamescientistslooktoadvances 4. He will be genuinely interested in the woman in moleculargeneticsasakindofjustification.Thefol- in question, and she in him. He may express his in- lowing quote from a recent book by the biochemists terest through displays of concern for her well-being. Dean Hamer and Peter Copeland (1998) reflects the at- 5. He will have a strong social presence and be titude of many behavioral geneticists: “The emerging well liked and respected by others. He will possess a science of molecular biology has made startlingdiscov- strong sense of efficacy, confidence, and self-respect. eriesthatshowbeyondadoubtthatgenesarethesingle most important factor that distinguishes one person Evolutionary theory does not support such predictions, from another. We come in large part ready-made from even if an “average woman” could be defined. First of thefactory.Weacceptthatwelooklikeourparentsand all,itwouldbenosmalldevelopmentaltrickgenetically other blood relatives; we have a harder time with the to program detailed, different, and independent repro- idea that we act like them” (p. 11). ductive strategies into modules in male and female Hamer and Copeland’s view has a long history. For brains. Those brains, after all are minor variants of the example, in his influential monograph, Arthur Jensen same incredibly complex structures, and, furthermore, (1969) claimed that the high heritability (a statistical the degree to which they are organized into modules is value) of IQ made it unlikely that environmentalinter- far from clear (Ehrlich 2000: 115–19). If the women in ventioncouldsucceedinimprovingtheeducationalper- the unknown culture actually chose mates meeting El- formanceofdisadvantagedchildren;thefaultlayintheir lis’s criteria, a quite sufficient alternative evolutionary genes.Thenextthreedecadessawthegrowthofbehav- explanationwouldbethatwomen(simultaneouslywith ioralgenetics,apartofpsychologybuiltaroundthesta- men)haveevolvedbigbrains,arenotstupid,andrespond tisticalcomparisonofidenticalandfraternaltwins.Most tothenormsoftheircultures.Scientifically,thenotion of these studies follow Jensen’s example and produce a that the detailed attributes of desirable mates must be highheritability,whichiswronglyinterpretedasamea- 90 F current anthropology Volume44, Number1, February2003 sure of how important genes are in determining differ- This broad-sense heritability has no predictive value ences between individuals in the behavior under study. and indeed cannot be legitimately used in the human For instance, the law professor Kingsley Browne (1998: behavioral context to predict anything. Ithas,however, 27) tells us that “evidence from behavioral genetics in- been widely misinterpreted as diagnostic of the under- dicatesthatmanypersonalitytraitsarehighlyheritable; lying causes of variation. Thus, in a recent perspective thatis,muchoftheirindividualvariationisattributable in the widely read magazine Science,the behavioralge- to genetic differences among individuals.”Weoftensee neticistsP.McGuffin,B.Riley,andR.Plomin(2001)infer headlines in major newspapers that summarize the that“DNAvariationsareresponsiblefortheubiquitous claims of behavioral geneticists with “Gene for Happi- geneticinfluenceinbehavior”fromtheclaimthat“the nessFound”or“WeVotewithOurGenes.”Butthetext most solid genetic findings about individualdifferences is not really about genes but about the behavioral ge- in human behavior come from quantitative genetic re- neticists’ interpretation of their own estimates of heri- search such as twin and adoption studies that consis- tability computed from twin studies. tentlyconvergeontheconclusionthatgeneticvariation The behavioral genetics literature is based on studies makesasubstantialcontributiontophenotypicvariation of identical and fraternal twins combined with a set of for all behavioral domains.” In other words, they claim statisticalassumptionsaboutgeneticandenvironmental thatthestatisticalmeasureofbroad-senseheritabilityis contributions that are used to extract estimates of how tellingusaboutthecausesofthebehavioraldifferences, important genes are in determining behaviors (e.g., in particular how “genetic” they are. Plomin et al. 1997). We shall examine this heritability The kind of statistical reasoning that underlies this paradigm in some detail andthenseewhatnewknowl- imputedconnectionbetweentheinformationcodedinto edge about the human genome can tell us about it. DNAandheritabilityreliesonaparticularmodelofhow Heritabilitywas originallyintroducedinthe1930sas that information causes behaviors, a model that is not an indexofamenabilitytoselectivebreedingofagricul- verifiable because we have no idea about how thecom- tural animals and plants (e.g., Lush 1945; Falconer and plexinteractionsbetweengenes,regulationofgenes,pro- Mackay 1996: chap. 10). Under carefully controlled en- tein structures, protein concentrations, and environ- vironmental conditions it measures the fraction of ge- ments would be manifest in a measurable trait or netic variation that would respond to selection by the behavior. Scientists don’t know what model to use to breeder on a trait such as fat content in milk or egg compute the degree of“geneticcausation.”Inoneclass production in chickens. An accurate measure of herita- of such models, for example, Robert Cloninger and col- bility requires that parents and offspring be raised in leagues(1979)showedthatheritabilitiesweremadevery identical environments. This original narrowdefinition highbyusingthedoubtfulassumptionthatidenticaland waspredictive—ittoldtheexperimenterwhathadtobe fraternaltwinshadthesamedegreeofsimilarityintheir done to move the desired trait in a given direction bya environments.Inanotheranalysis,Devlin,Daniels,and given amount. The definition of heritability was later Roeder (1997) showed that omission of a contribution modified,broadenedinfact,toincludegeneticvariation fromthesharedprenatalenvironmentoftwinsalsoleads thatwasunresponsivetoselectionandtoaccommodate to elevated estimates of heritability. In fact, calculated thefactthatgenotypesandenvironmentsmightinteract heritabilities give us no information concerning the in a way that could not be estimated or controlled, es- causes of our actions. The basic reason is that it is im- pecially in the case of human behaviors2 (Falconer and possibletodistinguishhumanbehavioralphenomesthat Mackay 1996: 123). are shared because of genetic similarities from those caused by shared environments. We might act like our 2.Theusualmodelinbehavioralgeneticstakesthephenotypeto parents because they gave us our genes; however, as bealinearcombinationofgeneticandenvironmentaleffects:Pp RichardLewontinpointedout,“IntheUnitedStates,the hG (cid:1) eE. In this statistical representation, the square of h is the highestcorrelationsbetweenparentandoffspringforany broad-senseheritability,anumberbetween0and1.0(or100%),e socialtraitsareforreligioussectandpoliticalparty.Only isthecorrespondingfractionofthephenotypeduetothe(nontrans- mitted)environmentE,andGandEoperateindependently.Itisin the most vulgar hereditarian would suggest that Epis- the quantityG that the action ofthe DNAis summarized.Fora copalianismandRepublicanismaredirectlycodedforin single gene, the contributions to an individual’s phenotype that the genes” (Lewontin, Rose, and Kamin 1984: 256). come from maternal and paternal contributions (alleles) may be Much has been recently made by behavioral geneti- independentandsummed,inwhichcasetheactionofthatgeneis purelyadditive,ortheymayinteractinsomewaythatismeasured cists of heritabilityestimatesforbehavioraltraitsbased bygeneticdominance.Whentwoormoregenesinteracttoproduce on data compiled in two twin studies: the Minnesota theircontributionstothephenotype,wecallthegenes“epistatic,” StudyofTwinsRearedApart(MISTRA)andtheSwedish andthepartoftheircontributiontothevariabilityofthephenotype Adoption-Twin Study of Aging (SATSA). Results from thatisnotthesumoftheirindividualcontributionsiscalledepis- these studies are widely cited in textbooks on the ge- tasis.Theseareallstatisticalnotionsaboutvariancethatarevery difficulttotranslateintogeneticstructuralorregulatoryphenom- neticsofhumanbehaviors(e.g.,Plominetal.1997),but ena. The fraction of the variance of P that is due to variation in it is only recently that the statistical assumptions un- theadditivecontributionstoGiscalledthe“narrow-sense”heri- derlying these analyses and the inconsistencies in the tability.ThefractionofthevarianceofPduetoGandtopossible reportingofestimateshavecomeundercarefulscrutiny interactions between G and E is called the “broad-sense”herita- bility.Thelatteriswhatismostoftenreferredtoastheheritability (Devlin, Daniels, and Roeder 1997, Feldman and Otto inbehavioralgenetics. 1997, Goldberger and Kamin 2002). Goldberger and Ka- ehrlich and feldman Genes and Cultures F 91 min point out that “the only genetical theory involved ius”level.Woulditthenbegoodpolicytogiveremedial in their analysis are the numbers 1, 1/2, and 1/4 repre- aidtoallwhitesandnonetoanyblacks?Orwoulditbe senting3 the genotypic correlations for identical twins wisertogiveadditionalhelptothosewhohadlowscores and the additiveandnon-additivegenotypecorrelations regardlessofskincolor?What,infact,wouldbetherea- for fraternal twins.” Not only do these authorsfindthe sonforevenbotheringtocalculatethegroupaverageIQ conclusionsfromMISTRAandSATSAunconvincingbut scores? Wouldwe calculatethemforpopulationsdiffer- they raise the important question, ignored in the now entiated on the basis of other characteristics, such as large literature on behavioral correlations among rela- bloodgroups?Infact,theusualphysicaland/orcultural tives, “What conceivable purpose is served by theflood criteria used to define ethnic groups may have little to of heritabilityestimates generated by these studies?” dowiththegeneticclassificationofsuchgroups(Wilson et al. 2001). It is only because people live in socially stratifiedso- Policy Implications of Heritability cietiesandhaveafascinationwithskincolor(orheight, or nose shape—after all, we are sight animals) that dif- Perhapsmostimportant,degreeofheritabilitycarriesno ferences between certain groups are singled out for in- message about how easily a characteristic can be vestigationviaheritabilities.IfaveragedifferencesinIQ changed, and, normally, knowledge of it will have few test scores are correlated withskincolorinoursociety, if any policy implications. Heritable diseases are rou- shouldwetrytoreducetheincidenceoflowtestscores tinely treated (e.g., phenylketonuria),asarediseasesbe- by treating skin-color groupsdifferently?Ofcoursenot, lieved to have little relationship to the victim’sgenetic anymorethanwewouldattempttolowertheincidence endowment (e.g., endocarditis). Similarly, even if a be- ofskincancer(towhichlighter-skinnedpeoplearemore havior had a high degree of heritability in one environ- susceptible) by doling out sunscreen on the basis of IQ ment, a small environmental alteration could totally testscores.Smartsocialpolicywouldbetoaidindividual change that behavior. The literature on quantitative students with low scores regardless of skin color and traits in plants, insects, and animals is replete with ex- regardless of what role genes played in determining in- periments that show the sensitivity of measured heri- dividual IQs. tability to changes in the environment. Jensen’s proposed heritability of 80% for IQ should Furthermore,itwouldbefoolishtomakesocialpolicy never have been used to blame the failure in school of designedtoalterbehavioronthebasisofgroupaverages some groups of students on their genes. Nor should in characteristics, regardless of the reasons for the dif- Herrnstein and Murray have used their value of 60% ferencesinthosecharacteristics.Considerathoughtex- (whichtheyfeel“mayerronthelowside”)tounderpin perimentonthefrequentlypromoted(withnoevidence) their claim that “chances of success in life are increas- view that there are differences between populations in ingly affected by genes” (1994: 109–10) and their reit- genes influencing intelligence. Suppose that,counterto eration 25 years later of Jensen’s claim that environ- everythinggeneticistsknow,thereweresomethingthat mentalinterventioninthelivesofthedisadvantagedin could be called “genetic IQ” and some way were dis- the United States was doomed to failure (pp. 551–52). coveredtoassessit—somesortofcognitivelitmuspaper It has been fascinating and disturbing for us as biolo- on which, when placed on the forehead, a number mi- gists to watch the legacy of Jensen’s 1969 opus unfold raculously appeared, faultlessly indexing the “genetic in psychology. Thus, one of the leading proponents of IQ”ofthatindividual.Supposefurtherthataverage“ge- theuseofheritability,RobertPlomin,writingintheThe netic IQ” litmus-test scores tended to be somewhat Psychologist, claims that “during the 1980s and espe- higherintheblackpopulation,eventhoughmanywhites ciallythe 1990s psychologybecamemuchmoreaccept- scoredmuchhigherthanmanyblacks,someatthe“gen- ingofgeneticinfluence,ascanbeseenintheincreasing numberofbehavioralgeneticarticlesinmainstreampsy- 3.Referringtothemodelofn.1,PphG(cid:1)eE,foranytwoindi- chology journals and in research grants” (Plomin2001). viduals labeled 1 and 2, we can write P p hG (cid:1) eE and P p He goes on to describe this change in psychology as a hG (cid:1) eE wherethegeneticandenviro1nmenta1lcontr1ibution2sto “waveofacceptanceofgeneticinfluenceinpsychology.” 2 2 thephenotypesP1andP2ofthetwoindividualsareG1,G2andE1,E2, Thisacceptanceisentirelyduetothewidespreadaccep- respectively.Now,foridenticalormonozygous(MZ)twinsG and 1 tance of the statistical methodology that leads to the G are the same because their complete complement of genes is th2esame;thecorrelationbetweenG andG is1.Ifindividuals1 reportingofbroad-senseheritabilityanditsmisinterpre- 1 2 and2aresibs,thenitcanbeshownthatthecorrelationbetween tation as an index of genetic causality, not to any the additive contributionstoP andP containedinG andG is neurogeneticadvancesthathavetiedhumanbehavioral 1 2 1 2 1/2 while that between the dominance contributions is 1/4 (see, differences to variation in DNA. In a similar vein, the e.g., Falconer and Mackay 1996 for more details). Almost all be- psychologistM.McGue(1997)claims,forexample,that havioral genetic studies assume that the correlation between en- vironments E and E when individuals 1 and 2 are MZ twins is “the IQ debate now centers on whether IQ is 50% to 1 2 the same as when they are fraternal or dizygous (DZ) twins. Yet 70% heritable.” whenthereareenoughdataforthesecorrelationstobecompared, Our point is that the assumptions used to build the for example,forIQ,theMZvalueislargerthantheDZ value.If statistical models that produce these estimates do not this difference in environmental correlations is ignored, a higher permit us to infer from such heritability estimates the estimate for heritability is reported (Cloninger, Rice, and Reich 1979,FeldmanandOtto1997). actual extent of “genetic influences” on IQ. Further, 92 F current anthropology Volume44, Number1, February2003 these estimates do not inform potential strategies for ior—the very attributes that make our behavior less determiningthenatureofsuchgeneticinfluences,ifthey rather than more genetically determined. But to under- exist. Applications of broad-sense heritabilitytopredic- stand the development of and variation in specific hu- tive situations are, we repeat, biologically and statisti- man behaviors such as creating charities and cheese- cally erroneous (Feldman and Lewontin 1975). Evolu- cakes, we must invoke culture, its evolution, and its tionary psychologists and behavioral geneticists persist potential interaction with biology. in confounding a technically defined statistic named Itmightbearguedthatsincearelativehandfulofgenes “heritability” with the colloquial use of thatterm.The can control our basic body plan—one’s height depends conceptofoverallheritabilityshouldberestrictedinits on millions of the body’s cells’ being stacked pre- employmenttoplantandanimalbreeding,whereitcan cisely—a handful could also determine our behavioral bebettermeasuredandtheresultsputtosomepractical phenome. Genes initiate a process of developmentthat use—such as in applying selection to increase the rate might be analogized with the way a mountain stream of growth of beef cattle or the weight of swine. entering a floodplain can initiate the development of a complexdelta.Why,then,couldn’tjustafewgeneshave evolvedtoprogrammillionsofourbehaviors?Intheory What Does Determine the Behavioral theymighthave,butinthatcasehumanbehaviorwould be very stereotyped. Consider the problem of evolving Phenome? human behavioral flexibility under such circumstances of genetic determination. Changing just one behavioral Geneticists know that a large portion of the behavioral pattern—say, making women more desirous of mating phenomemustbeprogrammedintothebrainbyfactors with affluent men—would be somewhat analogous to intheenvironment,includingtheinternalenvironment changing the course of one distributary (branch in the in which the fetus develops and, most important, the delta) without altering the braidedpatternoftherestof cultural environment in which human beings spend thedelta.Itwouldbedifficulttodobyjustchangingthe their entire lives. Behavioral scientists know, for in- flowofthemountainstream(equivalenttochangingthe stance,thatmanydramaticpersonalitydifferencesmust genes)buteasilyaccomplishedbythrowingbigrocksin betracedtoenvironmentalinfluences.Perhapsthemost the distributary(changing the environment). important reason to doubt that genetic variation ac- This partial analogy seems particularly apt in that it counts for a substantial portion of observed differences is apparently difficult for evolution to accomplish just in human behavior is simply that we lack an extensive one thing at a time. There are two principalreasonsfor enoughhereditaryapparatustodothejob—thatwehave this. The first is the complexity of interactions among a “gene shortage” (Ehrlich 2000). To what extent could alleles and phenotypic traits, especially pleiotropy and genes control the production of these differences? epistasis. Because there are relatively so few of them, It is important to remember that behaviors are the most genes must be involved in more than one process results of charge changes that occur in our network of (pleiotropy).Thenifamutationleadstobetterfunction- neurons,thespecializedcellsthatmakeupournervous ingofoneprocess,itmaynotbeselectedforbecausethe system. Behaviors are ultimately under some degree of changemightdegradethefunctioningofanotherprocess. control in the brain. Neuron networks are the locus of And changes in one gene can modify the influence of the memories that are also important to our behavior. another in very complex ways (epistasis). Second, be- That genes can control some general patterns is un- cause they are physically coupled to other genes on the questioned;theyareobviouslyinvolvedintheconstruc- same chromosome, the fates of genes are not indepen- tionofourbrains.Theymightthereforealsobuildinthe dent.Selectionthatincreasesthefrequencyofoneallele potentialforexperiencetoaffectalargepartofthedetails inapopulationwilloften,becauseoflinkage,necessarily involvedintheneuralcircuitry.Buttheycannotbecon- increase the frequency of another. Selection favoring a trolling our individual behavioral choices. gene that made one prefer tall mates might also result Human beings have only three times as many genes in the increase of a nearby gene that produced greater as have fruitflies (manyofthosegenesappeartobedu- susceptibility to a childhood cancer. plicatesofthoseintheflies,andthebiochemistryoffly nerve cells seems quite close to ours) (Zigmond et al. 1999: figs. 9.8, 9.9). But in addition to having sex and The Mysteries of Environmental Control eating (what flies mostly do) we get married, establish charities,buildhydrogenbombs,commitgenocide,com- Behavioral scientists are still, unhappily, generally un- posesonatas,andpublishbooksonevolution.Itisalittle able to determine the key environmental factors that hardtocreditallthistothedeterminingactionofthose influence the behavioral phenome. For instance, in the fewadditionalgenes(Ehrlich2000:124–26).Thosegenes case of the Dionne quintuplets, quite subtle environ- are,however,likelytohavecontributedtotheincreased mental differences—perhaps initiated by different posi- brainsizeandcomplexitythatsupportthevastcultural tions in the womb or chance interactionsamongyoung superstructurecreatedbytheinteractionofourneurons quints, their parents, and their observers (Blatz andtheirenvironments.Theymayalsocontributetothe 1938)—clearly led to substantially different behavioral wonderful flexibility and plasticity of human behav- and health outcomes in five children with identical ge- ehrlich and feldman Genes and Cultures F 93 nomes.As theirstoryshows,wereallyknowverylittle havior were completely genetically determined and in- about what environmental factorscanmodifybehavior. teractions between its genes and its environments did For example, some virtuallyundetectabledifferencesin not exist. Even single-celled organisms respond to environments may be greatly amplified as developing changes in their surroundings. Without substantial en- individualschangetheirownenvironmentsandthoseof vironmental inputs, evolution would not occur and life their siblings. Equally, subtle and undetected environ- could not exist. mental factors may put individuals with the same ge- Biological evolution has avoided that problem by al- netic endowments on similar life courses even if they lowing our behavior to be deeply influenced by the en- arerearedapart,perhapsexplaininganecdotesaboutthe vironments in which genes operate. In normal human similarities of some reunited identical twins. environments, genes are heavily involved in creating a We also know too little about the routes through basic brain with an enormous capacity for learn- which genes may influence behavior, where again ing—taking in information from the environment and changes may be behaviorally amplified. Suppose that a incorporatingthatinformationintothebrain’sstructure. study shows that identical twins, separated at birth, Itislearningthatproceedsafterbirthasaninfant’sbrain nonetheless show a high correlation of personality uses inputs such as patterns of light from the eyes to type—both members of twin pairs tend to be either in- wire up the brain so that it can see, patterns of sound troverted or extraverted. This is interpreted as a high that wire up the brain so that it can speak one or more heritabilityofintroversionandextraversion.Whatreally languages,andsoon.AsthebrainscientistJohnAllman is heavily influenced by genetics, however, could be putit,“thebrainisuniqueamongtheorgansofthebody height, and tall people in that society (as in many in requiring a great deal of feedback from experienceto societies) may be better treated by their peers and thus developitsfullcapacities”(1999:177).Andthesituation more likely to become extraverted (Buss 1994: 39–40). is notsodifferentforheight.Therearen’tenoughgenes Genesinthiscasewillclearlybeinvolvedinpersonality tocontrolachild’sgrowthratefromdaytoday—adding type but by such an indirect route as to make talk of cells rapidly in favorable (e.g., food-rich) situations and “genes for introversion or extraversion” essentially slowly or not at all under starvation. And there aren’t meaningless. enough genes to govern the growth of each column of And, of course, scientists do know that what appears cells,sometoregulatethoseineachcolumnontheright to be “genetic” is often simply a function of the envi- side of the spine, some for each in the left. Instead, all ronment. An example suggested by the philosopher El- growth patterns depend on environmental feedback. liott Sober (personalcommunication)illustratesthis.In England before the 18th century, evolutionary psychol- ogists (had there been any) would have assumed that Does Cortical Mapping Change This View? maleshadageneticproclivityforknitting.Theknitting gene wouldhave beenassumedtoresideontheYchro- But hasn’t all the above been shown to be incorrect by mosome. But by the 19th century, evolutionary psy- recentmappingstudies(Thompsonetal.2001)ofcortical chologistswouldhaveclaimedthatwomenhadthatge- structuresinthebrainsofmonozygousoridentical(MZ) netic proclivity, with the knitting gene on the X and dizygousorfraternal(DZ)twins?Thishasbeenthe chromosome. With historical perspective, we can see interpretationofthosestudiesbythepopularpress(Mo- that the change was purely culture-driven, not due toa tluk 2001).Thompsonandhiscolleaguescomputeddif- geneticchange.Asitdidwithknitting,theenvironment, ferences in the quantity of gray matter of MZ and DZ especiallytheculturalenvironment,seemstodoagood twins and unrelated individuals for various regions of job of fine-tuning our behavior. A major challenge for thecortex.Notonlydidtheyclaimtohavedemonstrated sciencetodayistoelucidatehowthatfine-tuningoccurs. that genetic factors significantly influence a number of structuralregionsofthebrainbuttheyarguedthattheir gene maps revealed how genes determine individual brain differences. These are indeed strong claims. Would Selection Generally Favor Genetic Thompsonetal.’sdataanalysisofthebrainmapssuf- Control of Behavior? fers from many of the defects mentioned above as per- meating the behavioral genetic literature. Environmen- Wouldwebebetteroffifwehadmorethanenoughgenes tal contributions are ignored: “Because non-genetic toplayacontrollingroleineveryoneofourchoicesand familial effects contribute to the resemblance between actions and those genes could operate independently? relatives, such effects were accommodated, if not en- Probably not. One could imagine a Hobbesian battle in tirely eliminated, by assuming the same common en- whichgeneswouldcompetewitheachothertoimprove vironmentalvarianceforMZandDZpairs”(Thompson theperformanceofthereproducingindividualsthatpos- et al. 2001: 1257). Then, a squared correlation greater sessedthem—genesforcautionbeingfavoredinoneen- than 0.8 having been claimed for volumes of cortical vironment one day and genes for impulsiveness in an- structures between MZ twins, the squared correlation otherenvironmentthenext(“Lookbeforeyouleap,”“He for DZ twins in the same areas varied from 0.6 to 0.89. whohesitatesislost”).Itisdifficulttoimaginehowany ThereisanobviousdifficultyhereinthatsuchlargeDZ organism could make the grade evolutionarily if its be- correlations suggest important environmental contri- 94 F current anthropology Volume44, Number1, February2003 butions.4TherelationshipbetweentheMZandDZcor- turalidentitiestothedebatesbetweenmaterialandcul- relationscertainlydoesnotsuggest“stronggeneticcon- turaldeterminismdescribedbySahlins(e.g.,1976),were trolofbrainstructure”(p.1254)oreven“tightcoupling proudlynonquantitative.Recentdiscussionsontheide- of brain structure and genetics” (p. 1256) as claimed. ational or symbolic nature of the subjects of cultural Strangely, in the analysis by Thompson et al. of the evolution(e.g.,Durham1991),whilecriticalofattempts relationship between cortical gray matter and Spear- to construct dynamical models of cultural evolution man’sg,aquantityoftenusedasameasureofcognitive based onindividual-to-individualculturaltransmission, performance(fromsubtestsoftheWechslerAdultIntel- nevertheless acknowledge the centrality of cultural ev- ligence Scale), unrelated individuals were omitted and olution to human behavioral analysis. Thus, although only the 40 twins receivedthe cognitivetests.Ahighly the quantitative paradigms used in behavioral genetics significant relationship between frontal matter volume donotinformevolutionaryanalysis,thisdoesnotmean and g is reported. It is not clear how the correlations that we cannot or should not take an evolutionary ap- between the twins were controlled here, especially in proachtotheunderstandingandmodificationofhuman lightoftheveryhighDZcorrelationsinthebrainimages behavior.Geneticallyevolvedfeaturessuchasthedom- and the well-established effects of gender on some con- inanceofourvisualsenseshouldalwaysbekeptinmind, tributorstog,especiallythegreatervariabilityofmales’ but an evolutionary approach to changing behavior in scores than females’ (e.g., Jensen 1998:537). In sum, our species must primarily focus on culturalevolution. Thompson et al. cannot be regarded as having demon- In the last 40,000 years or so, the scale of that cultural strated a gene-brain relationship, nor do their “genetic evolution has produced a volume of information that brain maps” contribute to our understanding of how dwarfs whatiscodedintoourgenes.Justconsiderwhat genes influence cognition. is now stored in human memories, libraries, photo- graphs, films, video tapes, the Worldwide Web, blue- prints,andcomputerdatabanks—inadditiontowhatis inherent in other artifacts and human-made structures. Conclusions Althoughtherehavebeenpreliminaryinvestigationsby Cavalli-Sforza and Feldman (1981) and Boyd and Rich- WhattherecentevidencefromtheHumanGenomePro- erson (1985),scientists havebarelybeguntoinvestigate ject tells us is that the interaction between genes, be- the basic processes by which that body of information tween the separate components of genes, and between changes (or remains constant for long periods)—a task controllingelementsoftheseseparatecomponentsmust thatsocialscientistshavebeentakinguppiecemealand be much more complex than we ever realized. Simple largely qualitatively for a very long time (e.g., Bischof additivemodelsofgeneactionoroftherelationshipbe- 1978; Cronk 1999; Durham 1991; Ehrlich 2002; Jacobs tween genes and environments must be revised. They and Campbell1961;JohnsonandEarle2000;Kotlerand have formed the basis for our interpretation of pheno- Zaltman1971;Murdock1956;PiragesandEhrlich1974; type-genotyperelationshipsfor84years,eversinceR.A. Rogers 1995; Stark 1996, 1999). Developing a unified Fisher’sfamouspaper(1918)thatforthefirsttimerelated quantitativetheoryofculturalchangeisoneofthegreat Mendelian genes to measurable phenotypes. Newmod- challengesforevolutionaryandsocialscienceinthe21st els and paradigms are needed to go from the genome to century. the phenome in any quantitative way. The simplistic Identifying the basic mechanisms by which our cul- approach of behavioral genetics cannot do the job. We ture evolves will be difficult; the most recent attempts must dig deeper into the environmental and especially using a “meme” approach (Blackmore 1999, Dawkins culturalfactorsthatcontributetothephenome.Theas- 1989 [1976]) appear to be a dead end. Learning how to cendancyofmolecularbiologyhas,unintentionally,mil- influencethatevolutionislikelytobemoredifficultstill itated against progress in studies of cultural evolution. and fraught with pitfalls. No sensible geneticist envi- Theories of culture andits evolutioninthe20thcen- sions a eugenic future in which people are selected to tury, from Boas’s insistence on the particularity of cul- showcertainbehavioraltraits,andmostthinkingpeople areawareoftheethical(ifnottechnicalandsocial)prob- 4.Referrington.2,ifindividuals1and2areMZtwinsandifthey lems of trying to change our behavior by altering our are raised in identical environments (so that E p E), thentheir 1 2 genetic endowments. Society has long been mucking correlationshouldbe1.If,ontheotherhand,theyareDZtwins, aroundinculturalevolution,despitewarningsofthepo- all the genetic contributions to the quantity of gray matter are additive,andE andE arenotcorrelated,theircorrelationshould tential abuses of doing so (e.g., Huxley 1932). Nazi eu- 1 2 be0.5(whichwouldmakethesquaredcorrelation0.25).Dominance genic policies and Soviet, Cambodian, Chinese, and effects will increase this, but in most cases the increase will not other social engineering experiments stand as monu- be sufficient to bring the DZ correlation into the ballpark ofthe ments to the ethical dangers that must be guarded MZcorrelation.FortheseDZtwins,fromthesimplemodelofnn. 1and2theonlyotherpossibleexplanationforthehighDZtwin againstwhentryingsystematicallytoaltereithergenetic correlation would be a correlation between environments E and or cultural evolution. 1 E2.ThestudyincludedfivepairseachoffemaleandmaleMZand Nevertheless,wearetodayallinvolvedincarryingout DZ twins. Despite acknowledging that gender affectsvolumesof or (with our taxes) supporting experiments designed to brainstructures,imagesforthesexeswerepooledwithineachzyg- change behavior. This is attested to by the advertising osity. It is very difficult to invoke statistical contributions from genestoexplaintheapparentlycloseMZandDZvaluesreported. business, Head Start programs, and the existence of in- ehrlich and feldman Genes and Cultures F 95 stitutions such as Sing Sing Prison and Stanford Uni- consensus that phenomena such as exaptation (Gould versity. The data used by evolutionary psychologiststo 2002), accident as an agent of direction of change itself infer the biological antecedents of human behavior, ratherthanonlyasourceofvariation(Kimura1983),and while not telling us anything about genetic evolution, moleculardrive(Dover2000)areallcausalmechanisms may actually be helpful in improving our grasp of cul- of evolutionarynovelties (Goodwin 2002). turalevolution.Whatseemscleartoday,however,isthat Assigning adaptive significance to an organ orbehav- evolutionarypsychologyandbehavioralgeneticsarepro- iour pattern presumesthata problemexiststowhichit motingavastoveremphasisonthepartplayedbygenetic isasolution(Dubrovsky2002).However,organismsnot factors(andaseriousunderestimationoftheroleofcul- onlysolveproblemsintheenvironmentbutcreatethem. tural evolution) in shaping our behavioral phenomes. AsWaddington(1976:18)hasputit,“Asurprisinglylarge amountoftheenvironmentwhichaffectsnaturalselec- tionoutcomesonanimalsisthemoreorlessdirectresult of the animal’s own behavior.” Consideringthesefacts, Comments Lewontin (2000) has suggested that a more faithful de- scription of the organism-environment interaction is “construction” rather than “adaptation.” In human ev- bernardo dubrovsky olution, the usual relationship between organism and McGill University,3445Drummond St.,701, environment has become virtually reversed in adapta- Montreal, PQ, Canada H3G1X9([email protected]. tion. Cultural invention has replaced genetic change as mcgill.ca). 5 x 02 the effective source of variation. Consciousness allows peopletoanalyzeandmakedeliberatealterationsassit- Ehrlich and Feldman advance serious and valid criti- uations require, with the result that adaptation of en- cismsofthemethodsusedbyevolutionarypsychologists vironmenttoorganismhasbecomethedominantmode andbehavioralgeneticistsandidentifyfactualerrorsfre- (Dubrovsky 2002). quently made by them. While in conceptual agreement OskarKempthorne(1978)hascriticizedtheexclusive withthem,Iproposeheretolookatsomeotheraspects use of observational data in the debate about inherited of the problem. and environmental factors contributing to intelligence. Cosmides and Tooby’s new version of evolutionary Observational data are used by behavioural geneticists psychology(1987,1995;ToobyandCosmides2000)com- (e.g.,Plominetal.1997)notwithstandingtherecognition bines teleological, adaptationist, and rigid formalist in- since the beginning of modern science that only exper- terpretationsofbiologicalevolutionwiththeviewofthe imentation can test the validity of rival causal hypoth- mindasasortofcomputerprogramorinformationpro- eses(Bunge1967).KempthorneandlaterJacquard(1983) cessor. The adaptationist program considers every evo- have criticized the use of analysis of variance of one lutionarynoveltyasafeaturethatfavourssurvivaland/ feature in a population to check for causality, arguing orreproduction(Gould2002,KirmayerandYoung1999). that variance only measures dispersion of data around Adaptationistsregardeachaspectoftheorganism’smor- thevalueofthemean;itisameasureofdiversity,some- phology, physiology, and behaviour as a specific adap- times inappropriately referred to as “variability.” What tation of the entire organism. For them the problem of is important in considerations of causality, however, is evolutionary science is finding out what an adaptation the magnitude of an effect which can be attributed to isfor,wheninfactthefirstquestionshouldbewhether variation or change in one or more independent varia- it exists (Fodor 2000; Mahner and Bunge 1997:423). bles. Variance cannot point to any causal factor. The It is extremely difficult to trace traits back in time, parallel with statistical correlation is clear. The latter andanyhypothesisregardingthehistoryofatraitmust measuresthedegreeofassociationoftwovariables(e.g., bebasedonprobability(Northcutt1999).Fewtraitshave been examined in sufficient detail in enough species in sizeandpopulationofacountry)neitherofwhichcauses different radiations to allow a meaningful evaluationof the other but variation in one of which can induce them. The problem of identifying traits is compounded changesintheother.Ithasneverbeendemonstratedthat by the frequency with which some psychologists and IQs(Jacquard1983)aredeterminedbythegenome,since psychiatristsarbitrarilyqualifytheconditionofthestate causal relations are valid only for events and not for or trait for various phenotype components (Paris 1998). attributes. Questionable concepts such as “brain design in re- Moreover, linear additive models in the absence of a sponsetoenvironmentaldemands”(KirmayerandYoung theory of interaction are invalid (Lewontin 2000). That 1999) and concepts difficult to verify such as “adaptive both genes and environment produce a given outcome evolutionoftraits”(Buss1999,Paris1998)lackheuristic isatruism,butweareseriouslymistakenwhenwepre- value, and there is no evidence whatsoever for an in- sumethatwecanbestexpressthisprinciplebyassigning structive component in the appearance of evolutionary percentages and stating, for example, that behaviour A novelties (Dover 2000, Gould 2002, Lewontin 2000). is 40% genetic and 60% environmental. Such reduc- Adaptationists fail to recognize other factors besides tionist expressions go beyond simple mistakes to enter natural selection as causally associated with evolution. the domain of the meaningless. Genetics and environ- Whileitisnotacriterionoftruth,thereisameasureof ment do interact to build a totality, but we need to un- 96 F current anthropology Volume44, Number1, February2003 derstandwhytheresultingwholesareirreducibletosep- It is made possible by innate machinery designed to arate components. do the learning. The claim that there are several in- nate modules is a claim that there are several innate learning machines, each of which learns according edward hagen to a particular logic. Institute for Theoretical Biology, Humboldt Further, the New Guineans’ opinion that “the fear in University, Berlin, Germany ([email protected]. Europeans [is]a resultoftheirstupidityinbeingunable hu-berlin.de) 6 ix 02 to distinguish which snakes might be dangerous” sup- ports rather than refutes Pinker (1997:388): Because Ehrlich and Feldman fail to provide them, I sketch evolutionary psychology’s basics here. The world is a dangerous place, but our ancestors It has long been recognized (e.g., Galen, Paley) that could not have spent their lives cowering in caves; organisms consist of functional mechanisms—hearts, there was food to gather and mates to win. They had lungs,livers,bones,intestines,prostates,uteruses,etc.— to calibrate their fears of typical dangers against ac- but before 1859 their origin was unknown. Darwinand tual dangers in the local environment (after all, not Wallace proposed that these mechanisms—termed ad- all spiders are poisonous) and against their own abil- aptations—evolved by natural selection and, thus, nec- ity to neutralize the danger: their know-how [etc.]. essarily were designed to promote reproduction. . . . Between the ages of three and five, children be- Psychologists have demonstrated that cognitive pro- come fearful of all the standard phobic objects cesses, like the body’s other mechanisms, have func- —spiders, the dark, deep water, and so on—and then tionalstructure.Evolutionarypsychologistsproposethat master them one by one. Most adult phobias are this structure evolved by natural selection to serve re- childhood fears that never went away. That is why production.Giventhatthebrainmechanismsunderpin- it is city-dwellers who most fear snakes. ning vision, hearing, motor control,pain,memory,etc., have obvious reproductive utility, this proposition is Finally,Minekaandcolleagues’research,whichEhrlich compelling. Further, these examples suggest that the and Feldman apparently believe undermines evolution- brainismadeupofmanyfunctionallyspecializedparts. arypsychologicalhypothesesofspecializedfearlearning, Anadaptationisrarelydiscoveredordescribedbyiden- actually strongly supports them. Cook and Mineka tifying the specific genes that directed its construction showed that lab-raised monkeys readily learned to fear or by documenting heritable variation and differential toysnakesbutnottoyrabbitsorflowers,suggestingthat reproduction in ancestral populations. Rather, adapta- there is an innate predisposition to learn fears of evo- tions are recognized by the close functionalfitbetween lutionarily salient dangers, such as snakes. O¨hman and an adaptive problem and some aspect of phenotypic Mineka(2001)synthesize30yearsofresearchonfearin structure; it is their evidence of design, not genes, that humans and other primates in an article subtitled “To- assures us that hearts,lungs,andliversareadaptations. ward an Evolved Module of Fear and Fear Learning.” Although Ehrlich and Feldman believe that the envi- Against hypothesized sex differences in mating psy- ronment of evolutionary adaptedness refers to a fixed chology, Ehrlich and Feldman claim that “it would be time or place, it actually refers to the recurring aspects nosmalldevelopmentaltrickgeneticallytoprogramde- of the environment that were necessary for the evolu- tailed,different,andindependentreproductivestrategies tion,development,functioningofaparticularadaptation into modules in male and female brains.” Well, natural (Tooby and Cosmides 1990a). The environment of evo- selection somehow “programmed” uteruses in females lutionaryadaptednessofthelung,forexample,includes but not males. Evolutionary psychology argues that an oxygen atmosphere. Recurring aspects of ancestral men’s and women’s brains, like the restoftheirbodies, environments that had an impact on reproduction in- are probably identical in most ways but profoundlydif- clude interactions with the opposite sex, children, par- ferent in some. ents, kin, nonkin, plants, animals, predators, and prey Whereasbehavioralgeneticsfocusesonindividualdif- and the need to avoid toxins, pathogens, and injuries. ferences,evolutionarypsychologyfocusesalmostexclu- Much evolutionary psychological research has been sively on human universals (age and sex excepted). Ad- based on the certainty that in the environment of evo- aptationsaregroundedinthevastmajorityofgenesthat lutionaryadaptednesswomengotpregnantandmendid are identical (or nearly identical) in all humans. Impor- not. tant individualdifferences arisenotfromminorgenetic To say “There is reason to believe that fear of snakes differences but “from exposing the same human nature in other primates is largely learned”impliesthatlearn- todifferentenvironmentalinputs”(ToobyandCosmides ing and psychological adaptations are opposing hypoth- 1990b:23). eses. But, as Pinker (1997:33) and virtually every other Accused of spinning “just-so stories,” evolutionary evolutionary psychologist repeatedly emphasize: psychologists have, in fact, tested their hypotheses in Yes, every part of human intelligence involves cul- hundredsofstudieswithmanythousandsofsubjectsin ture and learning. But learning is not a surrounding scores of different cultures and have published their re- gas or force field, and it does not happen by magic. sults in the world’s top science journals. Empirical re-

Description:
Current Anthropology Volume 44, Number 1, February 2003. 2003 by The tering, sexual behavior, and the Human Genome Project makes it abundantly clear
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.