G.E. Moore’s Naturalistic Fallacy and Open Question Argument Reconsidered by William Piervincenzi Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy Supervised by Professor Robert L. Holmes and Senior Lecturer John Gates Bennett Department of Philosophy The College Arts and Sciences University of Rochester Rochester, New York 2007 ii © 2007, William Piervincenzi iii Curriculum Vitae The author was born in Bethpage, New York on May 24, 1969. He attended the University at Stony Brook from 1988 to1992 and graduated with a Bachelor of Arts degree in Philosophy. He came to the University of Rochester in the Fall of 1994 and began graduate studies in Philosophy. He received a Rush Rhees Fellowship in 1994 and held teaching assistantships for the subsequent four years. He pursued his research in Ethics under the direction of Professor Robert Holmes and received a Master of Arts degree from the University of Rochester in 1999. iv Acknowledgments Completion of this dissertation would not have been possible for me without the kindness and generosity of people too numerous to mention. I wish to extend special thanks, however, to the following: Eileen Daly and Eva Cadavid for inspiring me to stick with it and to question others instead of myself; Greg Janssen for his friendship and encouragement over the years; Keith McPartland for his enthusiasm and comments, with Greg, on chapter drafts over coffee at Canal Town; my family, and especially my parents, Bill and Edna Piervincenzi who stopped asking “when will you be done?” just in time; Mary Schweizer for good times and pizza; the Diggin family, especially Cecilia for love and support and especially for Kerry; John G. Bennett who gave so much of himself through the final months of writing; Robert L. Holmes for his patience and calming influence; Joe and Jeanne Norwin for being our spiritual sherpas; all of the Delaware Park Olde Tymers for whom it is always summer; and Chewbacca, Goldie, and Quincy for quiet comfort when it was needed most. I extend the most special thanks and love to my wife, Kerry Diggin, to whom this work is dedicated. (Heaven knows she’s earned it). v Abstract G.E. Moore is justly famous for his arguments against ethical naturalism; however, after one hundred years of commentary, Moore’s arguments of the opening chapters of Principia Ethica—his claim that most ethical theories commit the naturalistic fallacy and his argument that moral goodness is a simple, indefinable property—are poorly understood. This work seeks to augment our understanding of these crucial arguments. This work offers an interpretation of what it means to commit the naturalistic fallacy that is maximally consistent with Moore's text and examples, distinguishes Moore’s claims about the naturalistic fallacy from the open question argument, and corrects mistaken interpretations of the open question argument. In pursuing these goals, I find that the naturalistic fallacy and the open question argument are complementary, rather than redundant, arguments. I also find that, contrary to the traditional reading, Moore’s open question argument actually consists of two arguments, one of which is supported by at least five sub-arguments, most of which turn on our intuitions about language and meaning, and none of which is wholly successful. Moore uses the open question argument to show that goodness is not identical with any complex natural or metaphysical property. This still leaves the possibility that goodness is identical with a simple natural or metaphysical property. His claim that philosophers who attempt to define goodness commit the naturalistic fallacy vi undermines support for any such identification, even if it does not conclusively refute such definitions. vii Table of Contents Chapter 1 The Legacy of Principia Ethica 1 Chapter 2 Goodness, Simple and Indefinable 15 Chapter 3 What is the Naturalistic Fallacy? 35 Chapter 4 The Naturalistic Fallacy: A New Interpretation 88 Chapter 5 Moore’s Proof that ‘Good’ Refers to a Simple, Non-natural Property 136 Chapter 6 Conclusions 194 Bibliography 211 1 Chapter 1 The Legacy of Principia Ethica I. Introduction It is safe to say that after G.E. Moore published Principia Ethica,1 just over one hundred years ago, philosophical ethics underwent a dramatic change. All forms of ethical naturalism and metaphysical ethics,2 theories that accounted for the majority of approaches to ethics, were under attack. Moore offered an ambitious and vexing collection of arguments that inspired, and continues to inspire, high praise and scathing criticism.3 And while his arguments did not sound a death knell for naturalism, they did inspire the development of plenty of alternative views.4 Moore’s intent in Principia Ethica was to create a new science of ethics, one that better captured what we had in mind when we called an action or a state of affairs good. He tried to accomplish this through observations about how we 1 G.E. Moore, Principia Ethica (1903). There are two versions of Principia Ethica in wide use, which have the same text and different pagination. The newer version is the “revised edition” of 1993. Since this new version contains a useful, previously unpublished preface to a planned but never written second edition of Principia Ethica, all future citations will be to the newer version. The appropriate citation is G.E. Moore, Principia Ethica, revised edition, Thomas Baldwin, ed. (Cambridge 1993) [henceforth ‘Principia Ethica’]. 2 Broadly defined, these are theories that hold that hold that goodness is identical with some natural or metaphysical property. See, e.g., Principia Ethica, § 27. 3 Alisdair MacIntyre holds Moore’s arguments to play a key role in the decline of Anglo- American ethical thought, and in the ongoing decay of Western culture. See Brian Hutchinson, G.E. Moore’s Ethical Theory (Cambridge 2001) p. 3, citing Alisdair MacIntyre, After Virtue, 2nd ed. (University of Notre Dame Press) 1984, pp 14-19. 4 Most notably, by those who rejected Moore’s positive views, like A.J. Ayer and C.L. Stevenson. 2 use moral language, what we intend, what it is we seem to be attributing to an action when we call it good, and through arguments that appear to demonstrate that whatever we have in mind when we use moral language, it can not be anything like what is proposed by ethical naturalists. II. Overview of Principia Ethica. Moore begins Principia Ethica by attempting to identify the scope of ethical inquiry. He wants to answer the questions: What is the subject matter of ethics? and, What is it that we purport to study when we engage in moral reasoning? Clearly, the answer is conduct. But there are other disciplines besides ethics that study conduct, so in order to differentiate ethics from those, Moore takes his study a step further. What Ethics studies is good conduct. And since “all conduct is not good; for some is certainly bad, and some may be indifferent,”5 Moore looks to see what all ethical judgments have in common as their subject and determines that this common subject is goodness. This prompts Moore to accept that ethics is the “general enquiry into what is good.”6 To determine what the nature of goodness is, in chapter I, Moore examines what we mean by the word ‘good.’ We use the word ‘good’ in many ways, most of which have nothing to do with ethics. For instance, I may say, “This eggplant is really good” or write, “Good soil and high moisture ensure acceptable rates of 5 Principia Ethica, p. 54. 6 Principia Ethica, p. 54. 3 propagation.” In these contexts, ‘good’ means tasty or fertile, clearly not what we mean when using ethical language. There is one sense of this word that Moore concludes is the uniquely moral sense of the word. This is the sense that Moore calls ‘intrinsic goodness’ or sometimes ‘intrinsic value.’ For simplicity, I will refer to this predicate as ‘goodness,’ throughout this work. When it appears in single quotes, as in ‘goodness’ I am talking about the word that refers to the property goodness. When it appears in regular text, without quotes, I use it to refer to the property itself. Moore asserts throughout Principia Ethica that people make a mistake when they attempt to define ‘good.’ But clearly, the problem is not in defining the word ‘good.’ Linguistic definition is not what Moore is after. He writes, “A definition does indeed often mean the expressing of one word’s meaning in other words. But this is not the sort of definition I am asking for. Such a definition can never be of ultimate importance in any study except lexicography.”7 A linguistic definition might tell us how people tend to use a word, or it might define a word by stipulation. One mistake people make is in claiming that a mere verbal definition is supposed to be an analysis of the uniquely moral sense of ‘good,’ namely, the property goodness. While it is a mistake to confuse a verbal definition with a property analysis, Moore is concerned to illustrate and avoid a different mistake— 7 Principia Ethica, p. 58.
Description: