Contributions To Phenomenology 90 Anders Odenstedt Gadamer on Tradition - Historical Context and the Limits of Reflection Contributions To Phenomenology In Cooperation with The Center for Advanced Research in Phenomenology Volume 90 Series Editors Nicolas de Warren, KU Leuven, Belgium Dermot Moran, University College Dublin, Ireland Editorial Board Lilian Alweiss, Trinity College Dublin, Ireland Elizabeth Behnke, Ferndale, WA, USA Rudolf Bernet, Husserl Archive, KU Leuven, Belgium David Carr, Emory University, GA, USA Chan-Fai Cheung, Chinese University Hong Kong, China James Dodd, New School University, NY, USA Lester Embree, Florida Atlantic University, FL, USA Alfredo Ferrarin, Università di Pisa, Italy Burt Hopkins, Seattle University, WA, USA José Huertas-Jourda, Wilfrid Laurier University, Canada Kwok-Ying Lau, Chinese University Hong Kong, China Nam-In Lee, Seoul National University, Korea Rosemary R.P. Lerner, Pontificia Universidad Católica del Perú, Peru Dieter Lohmar, University of Cologne, Germany William R. McKenna, Miami University, OH, USA Algis Mickunas, Ohio University, OH, USA J.N. Mohanty, Temple University, PA, USA Junichi Murata, University of Tokyo, Japan Thomas Nenon, The University of Memphis, TN, USA Thomas M. Seebohm, Johannes Gutenberg-Universität, Germany Gail Soffer, Rome, Italy Anthony Steinbock, Southern Illinois University at Carbondale, IL, USA Shigeru Taguchi, Hokkaido University, Japan Dan Zahavi, University of Copenhagen, Denmark Richard M. Zaner, Vanderbilt University, TN, USA Scope The purpose of the series is to serve as a vehicle for the pursuit of phenomenological research across a broad spectrum, including cross-over developments with other fields of inquiry such as the social sciences and cognitive science. Since its estab- lishment in 1987, Contributions to Phenomenology has published more than 80 titles on diverse themes of phenomenological philosophy. In addition to welcoming monographs and collections of papers in established areas of scholarship, the series encourages original work in phenomenology. The breadth and depth of the Series reflects the rich and varied significance of phenomenological thinking for seminal questions of human inquiry as well as the increasingly international reach of phe- nomenological research. The series is published in cooperation with The Center for Advanced Research in Phenomenology. More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/5811 Anders Odenstedt Gadamer on Tradition - Historical Context and the Limits of Reflection Anders Odenstedt Department of Business Administration, Technology and Social Sciences Luleå University of Technology Luleå, Sweden ISSN 0923-9545 ISSN 2215-1915 (electronic) Contributions To Phenomenology ISBN 978-3-319-59556-6 ISBN 978-3-319-59558-0 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-59558-0 Library of Congress Control Number: 2017943121 © Springer International Publishing AG 2017 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. Printed on acid-free paper This Springer imprint is published by Springer Nature The registered company is Springer International Publishing AG The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland Preface Since Hans-Georg Gadamer’s Wahrheit und Methode was first published in 1960, it has become something of a contemporary classic. Its appeal is perhaps at least partly the result of the wide range of topics that it covers. It contains interpretations of several figures in the history of philosophy, as well as discussions of truth, lan- guage, the human sciences, art, and aesthetic experience. But Gadamer in Wahrheit und Methode also proposes a theory of the way in which thought is influenced by its historical context and responds to this influence. I refer to this theory as Gadamer’s theory of context-dependence. Among the ques- tions that this theory tries to answer are the following: to what extent and in what way is thought influenced by and thus dependent on its historical context? To what extent is the individual able to become reflectively aware of and resist this influ- ence? And, conversely, how may the individual appropriate contextual influences and thereby contribute to the development of what Gadamer refers to as “tradition” (die Überlieferung)? This study offers an interpretation and assessment of Gadamer’s theory of context- dependence. It should be mentioned, however, that Gadamer does not him- self use the terms ‘context-dependence’ or ‘historical context.’ But he does refer to the “dependence” (Abhängigkeit) of thought on historical factors.1 Gadamer argues that these factors are formed by tradition, which involves and transmits a set of “presuppositions” or “prejudices” (Vorurteile): this is how thought is “dependent [angewiesen] on the given [historical] circumstances [Gegebenheiten] in which it operates.”2 I will have something to say about Gadamer’s discussions of other issues (pri- marily his discussions of the human sciences, art, and aesthetic experience) insofar as they contribute to an understanding of his theory of context-dependence. But this book is nevertheless largely thematic because it focuses on this theory. I do not attempt an examination of Gadamer’s philosophy as a whole even when he explic- itly draws conclusions in, for instance, the philosophy of language from his theory of context-dependence, or (conversely) when he infers elements of this theory in discussing other issues. Rather, I focus on the theory of context-dependence and attempt to place it in a somewhat larger thematic perspective. v vi Preface However, it might be argued that it is precisely through Gadamer’s theory of language that his theory of context-dependence is ultimately clarified, insofar as Gadamer holds that it is in language that the transmission of history and tradition occurs.3 This is undoubtedly true. But Gadamer often transfers certain key ideas and expressions from his theory of context-dependence to his theory of language and vice versa. For this reason it seems to me doubtful that either of these theories is fundamentally clarified by this transferal. Thus, Gadamer often argues that context- - dependence is in some sense unreflected. He says: “the consciousness of being affected by history [das wirkungsgeschichtliche Bewußtsein] is inescapably more [unreflective] being [Sein] than [reflective] consciousness [Bewußtsein] and being is never fully manifest.”4 And Gadamer makes similar claims on language: “No indi- vidual has a real consciousness of his speaking when he speaks. Only in exceptional circumstances does one become conscious of the language in which he is speak- ing.”5 Similarly, “The more language is a living operation [lebendiger Vollzug] the less we are aware of it. Thus it follows from the self-forgetfulness [Selbstvergessenheit] of language that its real being consists in what is said in it.”6 Instead of simply noting the passages where Gadamer asserts that language and context-dependence are both forms of unreflective “being” rather than reflective “consciousness” and so forth, I have tried to pose and, to some extent at least, answer the question what the very concepts of unreflective “being” and reflective “consciousness” might mean in cases of this kind. It seems to me that such ques- tions may be posed before one begins to trace Gadamer’s transferal of these con- cepts from one part of his philosophy to another. Gadamer’s theory of context-dependence is not, or so it seems to me, fundamentally clarified by his theory of language because both theories are expressed in the same general terms. Thus, Gadamer seems to use the concepts of unreflective “being” and reflective “consciousness” in largely the same way and in the same general and quite unspe- cific sense in all the three passages just quoted. Let me provide a few more examples of the close correspondence between the way in which Gadamer phrases his theory of language and the way in which he phrases his theory of context-dependence. According to Gadamer, “the most primordial [ursprüngliche] way in which the [historical] past is present is not remembering but forgetting.”7 This “forgetting” is an analogue of the “self- forgetfulness” that Gadamer sees as a feature of language. The question thus arises what the very concepts of “forgetting” and “self-forgetfulness” mean in both contexts. Similarly, Gadamer asserts that “the hermeneutic phenomenon proves to be a special case of the general relationship between thinking and speaking, whose enig- matic intimacy [rätselhafte Innigkeit] conceals the role of language in thought.”8 Gadamer also says: “When a person lives in a language, he is filled with the sense of the unsurpassable appropriateness [unübertrefflichen Angemessenheit] of the word he uses for the subject matter he is talking about.”9 And Gadamer argues that a similar “intimate” and “concealed” role is played by unreflected and context- - dependent “presuppositions” in thought in such a way that they seem self-evidently “appropriate” to their subject matter. Once again, the question arises what concepts Preface vii such as “intimacy,” “concealment,” and unreflected “appropriateness” might mean in cases of this kind. It is such questions as these that I pose in this book. I also discuss some of the historical sources of Gadamer’s theory of context- - dependence. Hegel is one of the most important of these sources. I thus discuss quite extensively Hegel’s account of the relationship between the individual’s think- ing, which Hegel calls “subjective Spirit,” and the surrounding historical context with its traditions, norms, and customs, which he calls “objective Spirit.” Gadamer often (but not quite consistently) stresses the epistemic cohesion of historical con- texts. This cohesion is, he thereby argues, formed by shared presuppositions which are not questioned by individuals situated in a historical context, and which to some extent are not reflectively or even consciously entertained by them (at least not in normal circumstances). Hegel makes somewhat similar claims in his account of objective Spirit, describing it as the unreflected basis of subjective Spirit. As we shall see, however, there are also crucial differences between Hegel’s and Gadamer’s views in this respect. Hegel is the most important representative of a tendency that began to emerge at the end of the eighteenth century to perceive cultural and historical factors as crucial to an understanding of thought. Previously such factors were traditionally described, insofar as the issue was discussed at all, as an external milieu in which thought more or less contingently happens to occur and which can only superficially enable or obstruct it. Hegel, by contrast, argues that objective Spirit plays a more fundamental role. Objective Spirit is not an external milieu of thought serving as an ancillary aid or obstacle to it. Objective Spirit forms part of the very constitution of thought. I try to spell out Hegel’s claim that contextual factors play a constitutive role in this regard in somewhat more detail in Chaps. 6 and 7, but we may note already at this stage that Gadamer describes these factors as constitutive in a similar way, and this is one of the reasons why Hegel is considered at some length in what follows. There was a stress on the context-dependence of thought and on the alleged mul- tiplicity of historical contexts in connection with the rise of the historical sciences as academic and institutionalized pursuits in the nineteenth century. The new sci- ence of history took pride in having abandoned what it saw as a previous naïve tendency to assume that all historical contexts are basically similar, that they exer- cise only a superficial influence on thought and conduct, and that, for this reason, they can be understood by the historian in a relatively simple fashion. Wilhelm Dilthey was one of the leading figures of the new historical sciences and nineteenth-- century hermeneutics, and he criticized previous history writing for having been insensitive to the influence of historical contexts. But Gadamer holds that Dilthey himself failed to understand the scope and strength of this influence. In what follows I also discuss this issue at some length. Now, there is an emphasis on context-dependence in several branches of contem- porary philosophy, such as poststructuralism (Foucault), deconstruction (Derrida), Marxism, certain forms of feminist philosophy, and the philosophy of science. Thomas Kuhn’s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions has been a seminal work in this regard, with its stress on the importance of the historical context (tradition and paradigm) even for research in the natural sciences. Kuhn refers to his “discovery of viii Preface hermeneutics.” This discovery, he says, “did more than make history seem conse- quential. Its most immediate and decisive effect was instead on my view of sci- ence.”10 And Gadamer refers to Kuhn’s views with approval and sees them as lending support to his own position.11 Accordingly, this book is not restricted to a discussion of the philosopher who is often seen as the most important contemporary representative of hermeneutics: it addresses an issue that has wider repercussions. To be sure, several of the schools of thought just mentioned are implicitly or even explicitly opposed to Gadamer’s view that context-dependence is ultimately formed by presuppositions. For instance, Marxists stress the role of forms of production as they occur in a historical context in determining the presuppositions and modes of thought of this context. And Jürgen Habermas has argued that the claim that context-dependent presuppositions are the ultimate ground of belief is superficial and even misleading insofar as communica- tion and thought may be distorted by forms of social and economic domination. Somewhat similarly, Foucault develops his account of “discursive practises” in opposition to what he sees as a misplaced stress in hermeneutics on mentalities and forms of thought. What Foucault tries to uncover is not a “structure of thought that the men of a particular period cannot escape” but “processes of a historical practice.”12 Of course, I do not pretend to have even sketched Foucault’s theory of discursive practices and its opposition to hermeneutics here, nor shall I address it in what fol- lows. This constraint also applies to Derrida’s “deconstructive” critique of herme- neutics.13 I mention Foucault and Derrida here to illustrate that there is a quite common stress on context-dependence in contemporary philosophy, although there are important differences between the accounts of this dependence in the respective cases. Derrida and feminist philosophers inspired by him see distinctions of the Western philosophical tradition such as those between the mental and the physical and between masculinity and femininity as permeating everyday language and thought. And Derrida tries to undermine distinctions of this kind. By contrast, Gadamer often questions both the possibility and desirability of such undermining of our context-dependence. However, Gadamer and Derrida share a stress on the allegedly fundamental role of theory and presuppositions in the formation of context- dependence and thereby differ from Foucault and Habermas. The question of context-dependence is not only of academic interest. For instance, in discussions of matters of principle between liberals and conservatives, the latter tend to stress the role of the historical context (custom, tradition, and prec- edent) in determining the preferences and beliefs of the individual, whereas the former conversely stress the individual’s autonomy in relation to such contextual factors. In what follows, some philosophical forms of this discussion are explored. I thus offer an analysis of Habermas’ critique of Gadamer and Gadamer’s response to it. I also discuss Gadamer’s critical remarks on Karl Popper and describe some of the differences between their respective views. Popper and Habermas represent, one might say, a liberal position in this regard. By contrast, Gadamer’s position often, but not consistently, involves a conservative stress on the inescapability of tradition and of the historical context. I say “not consistently” here to emphasize that Preface ix Gadamer’s position in this respect is quite complex and cannot straightforwardly be described as conservative, although there is certainly support in Gadamer’s writings for such a description. I devote large portions of this book to an exploration of this and related complexities in Gadamer’s thought. Several writers see a tension in Gadamer between a commitment to reflection on context-dependence, on the one hand, and his claim that this dependence is unre- flected, on the other hand. In what follows I examine possible reasons for and against ascribing such a tension to Gadamer’s thought. I also discuss if we are actu- ally involved with a tension and with incompatible views in this regard, or if Gadamer’s very stress on unreflected context-dependence follows quite naturally from a certain form of reflection on the contextual circumstances under which we live. Parts of this book have been published in earlier versions in the following forms. Chapter 2 is based on “Art and history in Gadamer’s hermeneutics” (Phänomenologische Forschungen 2007). Chapter 3 is based on “Tradition and truth. Dilthey and Gadamer on the history of philosophy” (Lychnos 2006), and on “History as conversation versus history as science. Gadamer and Dilthey” (in Hermeneutics and the Art of Conversation, ed. Andrzej Wiercinski. Berlin: LIT Verlag 2011). Chapters 4 and 5 incorporate “Gadamer on the limits of reflection” (The Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 36: 2005),14 and “Gadamer on context-dependence” (The Review of Metaphysics 57: 2003). Chapter 6 is based on “Hegel and Gadamer on Bildung” (The Southern Journal of Philosophy 46: 2008),15 and Chap. 7 is an extended version of “Being a child of one’s time: Hegel on thought and cultural context” (International Philosophical Quarterly 52: 2012). I wish to thank the publishers for their kind permission to use this material here. During the preparation of this book I have incurred many debts of gratitude. The late Professor Stanley Rosen promptly and perceptively read and commented on parts of the manuscript. I also thank Professors Sören Stenlund, Ingvar Johansson, Sharon Rider, and Jeff Malpas, who read earlier versions of parts of the manuscript and made many valuable and helpful remarks. Ingvar supervised the writing of my dissertation, on which this study largely builds. Parts of the text were presented and discussed at seminars at the universities of Uppsala and Umeå. I extend my thanks to all the participants concerned. I am also grateful for comments and questions by students over the years at Umeå University, Luleå University of Technology, and the Academy of Fine Arts in Umeå. I also thank an anonymous reviewer of the manu- script for many valuable remarks. Thanks also to my editors at Springer, Dr. Cristina dos Santos, Anita Rachmat, and Magesh Kaarthick for much good advice of a more practical nature. Last but not least, I thank my late parents Birgitta and Bengt, my sister Christina, my brother Fredrik, Mojgan Sanaei, and my son Oscar for their support and encouragement. Luleå, Sweden Anders Odenstedt