FREUD FOR HISTORIANS Books by Peter Gay The Bourgeois Experience: Victoria to Freud, volume I, Education of the Senses (1984) Freud, Jews and Other Germans: Masters and Victims in Modernist Culture (1978) Art and Act: On Causes in History—Manet, Gropius, Mondrian (1976) Style in History (1974) Modem Europe (1973), with R. K. Webb The Bridge of Criticism: Dialogues on the Enlightenment (1970) The Enlightenment: An Interpretation, volume II, The Science of Freedom (1969) Weimar Culture: The Outsider as Insider (1968) A Loss of Mastery: Puritan Historians in Colonial America (1966) The Enlightenment: An Interpretation, volume I, The Rise of Modern Paganism (1966) The Party of Humanity: Essays in the French Enlightenment (1964) Voltaire's Politics: The Poet as Realist (1959) The Dilemma of Democratic Socialism: Eduard Bernstein's Challenge to Marx (1952) F R E UD FOR HISTORIANS Peter Gay OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS New York Oxford Oxford University Press Oxford New York Toronto Delhi Bombay Calcutta Madras Karachi Petaling Jaya Singapore Hong Kong Tokyo Nairobi Dar es Salaam Cape Town Melbourne Auckland and associated companies in Beirut Berlin Ibadan Nicosia Copyright © 1985 by Peter Gay First published in 1985 by Oxford University Press, Inc., 200 Madison Avenue, New York, New York 10016 First issued as an Oxford University Press paperback, 1986 Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Oxford University Press, Inc. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Gay, Peter, 1923- Freud for historians. Includes index. 1. Psychohistory. I. Title. D16.16.G39 1985 901'.9 85-10665 ISBN 0-19-503586-0 ISBN 0-19-504228-X (pbk.) Printing (last digit): 987654 Printed in the United States of America To ERNST PRELINGER and to one other for talking, and for listening Acts and examples stay WILLIAM JAMES This page intentionally left blank Preface This book is the concluding volume of a trilogy I did not intend to write. When, in 1974,1 published Style in History, I thought I had paid my tribute to historiography. In that expedition of discovery among the stylistic devices of four master rhetoricians—Gibbon, Ranke, Macaulay, and Burck- hardt—I attempted to locate history among the human sci- ences. My conclusion, less banal, I trust, in the extended argument than in bald summary, was that, for history, the old sharp division between art and science is untenable: in ways I attempted to demonstrate in the book, it is both. Although there is at first glance nothing very startling about such a judgment, my particular formulation raised questions about the fundamental intentions of my craft that Style in History could not address, let alone resolve. The historian's art, I proposed, forms part of his science; his manner is neither decoration nor idiosyncrasy but is inextric- ably bound up with his matter. Style, in short, helps to bear the burden, and define the nature, of substance. This quite naturally propelled me from the way that the historian ex- presses himself to the issues he is bound to find most critical. "In the course of his work," I wrote two years later, "the historian does many things, but his most difficult and, I think most interesting, assignment is to explain the causes of historical events." I found that to think about cause is to viii Preface enter an uninterrupted professional debate in which his- torians engage with great gusto, and in which the stakes are the highest possible. And it is to encounter the insistent claims of psychology on the historian's attention. Like Style in History, its sequel about causation, Art and Act, was steeped in concrete experience: in the company of most historians, I have always been most comfortable among specific instances. While, in the earlier book, I con- structed my case by examining the work of four great his- torians, in its successor, I focused on three influential artists—Manet, Gropius, and Mondrian—to urge a pluralis- tic but confident stance toward historical causation. In an introductory chapter I spelled out the theory informing these exercises in cultural biography, and diagrammed the relations among three clusters of causes, those springing from the private domain, from craft, and from culture. It is in their subtle interplay, their jostling for supremacy, that psychology asserts its special rights. The intellectual kinship of these two books lies on the surface. Both are explorations in historical epistemology; both, while arguing for the overpowering variety of possible ways of expressing historical truths and of reaching them, are relatively optimistic about the historian's reach and grasp. It is curious: when historians settle down to reflect about their business—a self-conscious, not always felicitous venture into philosophical rumination they are often se- duced to undertake after they have reached the age of fifty— they are apt to profess themselves pronounced subjectivists. They will likely insist that every historian's personal demons or social aspirations dictate a severely limiting perspective on the past, and that no amount of self-awareness will ever let him escape these inescapable pressures for partisanship. The historian's style, on that view, is a repository of biases Preface ix and his perception of causes is bound to be compromised by the same crippling ideological burdens. In dissent, I argued that style can also be a privileged passage to historical knowledge and that the historian's particular vision of what made the past world move, however distorted that vision may be by his neuroses, professional deformations, or class prejudices, may yet assist him in securing insights into his material that he could not have gained without them. Gib- bon's stately irony, for one, a kind of magnificent nastiness that pervaded his character, was the perfect instrument for dissecting the dominant political motives of Imperial Rome, with its high professions and low motives; Burckhardt's re- pressed bachelor existence, for another, gave rise to luxu- riant fantasies of cruelty and power supremely adapted to appreciating the mentality of the outsize condottieri con- ducting the wars of the Italian Renaissance. I had no taste for joining the camp of historians who judge attainment of reliable knowledge about causes a chimera, or those who reduce the glittering, multicolored costume of historical ex- perience to the drab uniform of a single dominant set of impulsions. The two books were at once a warning against the facile pessimism of the skeptics and the equally facile simplifications of the dogmatists. My plea for history as an elegant, fairly rigorous aesthetic science was, as I have already hinted, powerfully assisted by my commitment to psychology, in particular to psycho- analysis.1 I saw it then, and see it even more now, as a re- I. I should emphatically make plain from the outset that by "psy- choanalysis" I mean more than the body of work done by Sigmund Freud and his immediate disciples alone. I include that of their suc- cessors who, though in some respects going their own way and at- tending to clinical experiences not available to Freud, securely belong into his camp. I stress this here because the title of my book, and the