ebook img

Foucault PDF

162 Pages·10.561 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Foucault

FOUCAULT Edited by ROBERT NOLA FRANK CASS LONDON • PORTLAND, OR First published in 1998 in Great Britain by FRANK CASS PUBLISHERS Newbury House, 900 Eastern Avenue, liford, Essex IG2 7HH, England and in the United States of America by FRANK CASS PUBLISHERS clo ISBS 5804 N.E. Hassalo Street Portland, Oregon 97213·3644 Website: http://www.frankcass.com Copyright © 1998 Frank Cass & Co. Ltd British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Foucault 1. Foucault, Michel, 1926-1984 I. Nola, Robert 194 ISBN 0 7146 4915 5 (cloth) ISBN 0 7146 4469 2 (paper) Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data ,, ' Foutault I edited by Robert Nola. p. cm. Iilduaes'tsibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-7146-4915-5 (hbk). - ISBN 0-7146-4469-2 (pbk.) 1. Foucault, Michel. I. Nola, Robert. B2430.F724F67 1998 98-21412 194-dc21 CIP This group of studies first appeared in a Special Issue on 'Foucault' of Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, (ISSN 1369-8230) 1/2 (Summer 1998) published by Frank Casso All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form, or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher of this book. Printed in Great Britain by Antony Rowe Ltd., Chippenham, Wilts. Contents Introduction Robert Nola 1 Foucault as Historian Keith Windschuttle 5 Foucault's Problematic Joseph Margolis 36 Knowledge and Political Reason Barry Hindess 63 Foucault and the Possibility of Historical Transcendence Robert Wicks 85 Knowledge, Discourse, Power and Genealogy in Foucault Robert Nola 109 Notes on Contributors 155 Index 157 Introduction The writings of Michel Foucault (1926-84) have influenced diverse fields such as literary and cultural studies, the history of ideas and science, and disciplines such as sociology, history, law, politics and philosophy. His areas of investigation have been equally diverse and include: our practices concerning sexuality and more generally 'technologies' of the self; our institutions, such as asylums or prisons; the history of these practices and institutions from ancient Greece to modern times; and lastly theoretical matters, such as the nature of the self, power, politics, discourse and knowledge. The secondary literature on Foucault has grown so fast that a recent author! entitled the Preface to his book 'Not Another Book on Foucault'! The same might be said of even a special issue of a journal. Foucault's writings have also excited commentary ranging from the hagiographical to the sternly dismissive. In the absence of a current consensus, it befits a journal with the word 'critical' in its title to engage in the task of critical evaluation. Such an evaluation raises a host of questions from the historical to the philosophical. How correct is Foucault as a historian of our culture? What is the alleged connection between power and knowledge? Is Foucault right about the connections between power and knowledge within liberal societies? Is there something inconsistent about Foucault's strongly historicist stance and the seemingly more objectivist transhistorical position he often seems to adopt? How might one begin to answer these questions given that Foucault holds that there are no fixed norms of truth, knowledge and objectivity, but merely 'regimes' or 'games' of 'truth'? Should we conclude that there are simply 'readings' of Foucault between which no consensus need be found or ought to be sought? Would a positive answer to the last question merely evade the hard problems that Foucault's work raises? These are urgent questions to raise and answer given the wide range, complexity and sometimes bewildering obscurity of Foucault's work. Lastly, even before the dust settles over the controversies raised by these questions, how do historians of ideas situate Foucault's work in the context of other twentieth- 2 FOUCAULT century writers, ranging from philosophers such as Heidegger or Kuhn to sociologists such as Goffman or historians of Greek culture such as Dover? The papers in this collection attempt to answer only aspects of the above questions. Though the papers range over all of Foucault's works, their main focus is on themes of objectivity, power and knowledge. Moreover, it has been left to each author to specify the extent, and kind, of critique their paper provides of Foucault's writings, whether they ultimately support, refine or reject his views. This is an important matter because the very possibility of a critical stance is a recurring theme in all of Foucault's works, turning as it does on his views about truth and reason in relation to power and government. Keith Windschuttle challenges Foucault the historian. In considering the 'reason-madness nexus', Foucault alleges that there was a change in our attitude toward the mad in the transition to the Enlightenment, during which 'the great confinement' of the mad first occurred. In contrast, Windschuttle argues that historians have shown that while the great confinement did occur, it was after the French Revolution, which marks the emergence of the modern era and the end of the Enlightenment. In the case of punishment, legislation directed against 'the body' rather than 'the soul' increased rather than declined at the end of the Enlightenment and the beginning of the modern era with an increase in the number of capital offences. Again, Windschuttle argues that there is a lack of fit between the development of sciences such as psychiatry and criminology and changes in the way we dealt with criminals and the insane. Lastly, Windschuttle criticises the account of homosexuality in ancient Greece that Foucault gives in his final works. He argues, following the research of the classicist Thornton, that Foucault has relied on too narrow a selection of source material concerning the extent of homosexuality in, and its endorsement by, ancient Greek society. Windschuttle presents a challenge to Foucault's endorsement of Nietzsche's 'effective history' with its 'affirmation of knowledge as perspective', by contrasting it with the practice of traditional objective history. Joseph Margolis' discussion also ranges over Foucault's entire span of writing. It emphasises how Foucault's efforts at the end of his INTRODUCTION 3 career to explore the 'technologies of the self' bear on the master themes of his entire work, particularly archaeology, genealogy, historicity, and problematic. Margolis finds Foucault's analysis of the human self or subject particularly elusive. He considers the use of Althusser's version of structuralism in this context, but notes the general sense in which Foucault has failed to formulate a rounded theory of the self. The relevance of this lacuna is examined, particularly with respect to Foucault's occasional explicitness on moral issues and, at the same time, his disinclination in the later works to restore any sort of essentialism. Barry Hindess argues that Foucault's earlier 'power/knowledge' perspective presents the social sciences as normalising technologies, while his later governmentality perspective offers a more differentiated account. This suggests that the development of a liberal rationality of government is responsible both for the discovery of society as a reality independent of government and for the emergence of the sciences which aim to study its workings. Hindess argues that Foucault's treatment of this issue presents too direct a set of connections between liberalism and this conception of society. In contrast, Hindess proposes an alternative account of relations between liberal government and knowledge of various domains of social interaction. Robert Wicks's essay explores the allegation, by Habermas among others, of an inherent self-referential inconsistency in Foucault's method of genealogical critique by considering the extent to which a transhistorical standpoint is implicit within Foucault's manifestly historically grounded outlook. He argues that Foucault's account of freedom implicitly recognises a transhistorical perspective, and shows that if Foucault's conception of 'power/knowledge' is understood as an expression of 'concrete thinking', which has its history in Berkeley and Hegel, then Foucault can maintain consistently that all knowledge, as it exists in a concrete social situation, must arise within the context of power, while assuming that there is a legitimate vision of how a less oppressive society ought to be. Robert Nola argues that Foucault links power to knowledge and discourse in such a way that he appears to challenge traditional theories of knowledge, either bypassing their concerns or proposing a rival genealogy of knowledge and discourse. Despite its radical 4 FOllCAll LT character, it is argued that Foucault's theory not only needs notions of traditional epistemology, but also, by its standards, is found wanting. Foucault's epistemic notions are linked to his theory of discourse. The main part of the paper examines Foucault's theory of discourse and its accompanying account of rules for the formation of objects, highlighting the anti-realist constructivism to which both are committed. It is shown that the theory bears many similarities to the views of Kuhn and Feyerabend concerning incommensurability. However, its account of the 'objects' of a discourse is bizarre and this, in turn, vitiates any prospects of its providing a rival to traditional epistemology in the form of a 'genealogy of knowledge'. ROBERT NOLA Editor 1. Rudi Visker, Michel Foucault: Genealogy as Critique (London: Verso, 1995). Foucault as Historian KEITH WINDSCHUTTLE In 1966, Michel Foucault attracted a great deal of academic attention by coining the phrase 'the death of man'. His obvious allusion to Nietzsche's well-known proclamation of the end of religion in the phrase 'the death of God' drew a considerable notoriety to himself and to the then burgeoning school of 'anti-humanism'. By 'the death of man', Foucault wrote in his book The Order of Things, he meant the end of the humanist concepts of mafias a creature ruled by reason and of history as a phenomenon governed by the decisions of powerful individuals. Instead,: history was a process without a: I subject. Not only did men not make their own history, but the concept of 'man' itself, he argued, was passe. Foucault shared this thesis with other anti-humanist thinkers of the time, including the Annales school of French historians, all of whom regarded history as being driven by forces far more powerful than those of any individual. i Anti-humanism's) main proposition was that the autonomy of the individual s~bject was an illusion. The humanist tradition had been wrong to assign the central roles of human affairs to the conscious mind and free will. Instead, some strands of anti humanism claimed that human behaviour and thought were dominated by the unconscious, and hence humanists should abandon their assumption that purposive behaviour was consciously directed. Others, like the Annales school, held that the impersonal forces of geography and demography\governed the destiny of mankind. At the same time, Foucault believed the historian could not avoid the role of political activist. All knowledge 'exuded power, he insisted, so the knowledge produced by the historian must serve political ends of one kind or another. Most historians, he claimed, were traditionalists who supported the established regime. However, he This paper is an adaptation of sections of the author's book The Killing of History, while other material is new. 6 FOUCAULT also identified 'the new historian', someone who could help foster an 'insurrection of subjugated knowledges' opposed to what he called 'the centralising powers which are linked to the institution and functioning of an organised scientific discourse within a society such as ours'.2 In the 1970s, Foucault claimed this insurrection was being led by outcast groups struggling against authority, especially psychiatric patients and prisoners. At the time he proclaimed these ideas, Foucault himself was engaged in the radical prison activist movement, attending meetings and offering advice. He argued that the 'local knowledges' of groups such as prisoners were crude responses to their immediate situation. They lacked any historical knowledge of predecessors who might have emulated their deeds. So their demands needed to be supplemented by the interpretations of a sympathetic academic like himself (a person he defined as 'the specific intellectual'), thereby uniting 'erudite, historical knowledges' with the 'disqualified knowledges' of the outcasts. This union would produce 'subjugated knowledge' or a 'historical knowledge of struggles' that was formidable enough to challenge the power of those sciences which sided with authority.3 In his 1971 article, 'Nietzsche, Genealogy and History', Foucault declared the need to distinguish between 'effective history' (a term of Nietzsche's) and traditional history.4 He said that the aim of traditional history) to discover(a pattern or a rational sequence of events in the past is impossible because there is nothing constant or universal in either human nature or human consciousness. Different historic eras cannot relate to one another and a new era is not born within and nurtured by its predecessor. A new era (or episteme or 'discursive formation', to use his earlier terminology) simply appears in a way that cannot be explained. History does not display any pattern of evolution, he says, because the past is nothing more than a series of discontinuities or unconnected developments: 'Effective history}idiffers from traditional history in being without constants ... Nothing in man - not even his body - is sufficiently stable to serve as the basis for self-recognition or for understanding other men. The traditional devices for constructing a comprehensive view of history and retracing the past as a patient and continuous development must be systematically dismantled. I

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.