ebook img

Forcing, Arithmetic, Division Rings PDF

256 Pages·1975·2.15 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Forcing, Arithmetic, Division Rings

Lecture Notes ni Mathematics detidE yb .A Dold dna .B nnamkcE 454 maroJ Hirschfeld William .H Wheeler Forcing, Arithmetic, noisiviD sgniR Springer-Verlag Berlin-Heidelberg • New York 1975 Authors .rD Joram Hirschfeld Department of Mathematics leT Aviv University Aviv Ramat leT Aviv learsI .rD William .H Wheeler Bedford College University of London London England Permanent address: Department of Mathematics Indiana University Bloomington, Indiana 47401 USA Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Hirschfeld, Joram. Forcing, arithmetic, and division rings. (Lecture notes in mathematics ; 454) Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1. Forcing (Model theory) 2. Model theory. 3. Division rings. .I Wheeler, William H., 1946- joint author. II. Title. III. Series: Lecture notes in mathematics (Berlin) ; 454. QA3.L28 no. 454 [QAg.7] 510'.8 [511'.8] 75-12981 AMS Subject Classifications (1970): 02 H 05, 02 H ,31 02 H ,51 02 H 20, 08A20, 10N10, 10N15, 16A40 ISBN 3-540-07157-1 Springer-Verlag Berlin- Heidelberg" New York ISBN 0-387-07157-1 Springer-Verlag New York • Heidelberg • Berlin This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically those of translation, reprinting, re-use of illustrations, broadcasting, reproduction by photo- copying machine or similar and means, storage ni data banks. Under § 54 of the German Copyright Law where copies are made for other than private use, a fee is payable to the publisher, the amount of the fee to be determined by agreement with the publisher. © by Springer-Verlag Berlin • Heidelberg 1975. Printed in Germany. Offsetdruck: Julius Beltz, Hemsbach/Bergstr. In memory of Abraham Robinson ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS We gratefully acknowledge the contributions of our colleagues and coworkers to this volume. Deserving of special mention are Mrs. S. Mandel for typing Part Two; L. Manevitz, D. Saracino, .P van Praag, and P. M. Cohn for their valuable comments and criticism of the manuscript; the members of the 1973-1974 Bedford College (University of London) logic seminar, to whom much of the material herein was presented, for their questions and comments; and the members of the Department of Mathematics of Yale University, 1969-1972, especially N. Jacobson, J. Barwise, G. Sacks, .E Fisher, M. Lerman, J. Schmerl, and S. Simpson, for their instruction and suggestions. We are indebted especially to Abraham Robinson, our adviser, for his guidance and encouragement and for the proposal of this volume. Finally, we thank our wives for their patience and moral support during the writing and preparation of this volume; the second author acknowledges in particular his gratitude to his wife for her labor of love in typing Parts One and Three. Joram Hirschfeld William H. Wheeler CONTENTS INTRODUCTION PART ONE ii FORCING CHAPTER 1 EXISTENTIALLY COMPLETE STRUCTURES AND 15 EXISTENTIALLY UNIVERSAL STRUCTURES § i Existentially Complete Structures 15 § 2 Existential Types and Existentially 28 Universal Structures CHAPTER 2 MODEL-COMPLETIONS AND MODEL-COMPANIONS 44 CHAPTER 3 INFINITE FORCING IN MODEL THEORY 55 § i Infinite Forcing 55 § 2 Model-companions and Infinitely Generic 69 Structures § 3 Subclasses of ~ 72 CHAPTER 4 APPROXIMATING CHAINS FOR ~ 76 CHAPTER 5 FINITE FORCING IN MODEL THEORY 86 § 1 Finite Forcing 86 § 2 Finite Forcing by Structures 93 § 3 Finitely Generic Structures and 98 the Finite Forcing Companion § 4 Model-companions and Finite Forcing iOO Companions § 5 Approximating Theories for 104 the Finite Forcing Companion CHAPTER 6 AXIOMATIZATIONS iii CHAPTER 7 FORCING AND RECURSION THEORY 117 § 1 Degree of Unsolvability of F T 119 § 2 Degree of Unsolvability of f T 124 § 3 Consequences ef the Joint Embedding Property 12S § 4 Non-elementarily Equivalent Existentially 129 Complete Structures S UMMARY 132 IV PART TWO 137 ARITHMETIC CHAPTER EXISTENTIALLY COMPLETE MODELS 141 § 1 Models of T 141 w2 § 2 Existentially Complete Models for Arithmetic 146 § 3 The Definition of N in Existentially 150 Complete Models CHAPTER 9 SIMPLE MODELS AND R. E. ULTRAPOWERS 155 CHAPTER iO REGULAR MODELS 160 Biregular Models 166 CHAPTER ii REGULAR MODELS AND SECOND ORDER MODELS 168 FOR ARITHMETIC Biregular Models and Models 172 of Arithmetical Comprehension CHAPTER 12 GENERIC MODELS AND THE ANALYTIC HIERARCHY 179 § 1 Generic and Existentially Universal Models 179 § 2 The Approximating Chains for ~ 182 § 3 The Analytic Hierarchy 184 CHAPTER 13 APPLICATIONS TO COMPLETE EXTENSIONS 187 OF PEANO'S ARITHMETIC PART THREE 191 DIVISION RINGS CHAPTER 14 EXISTENTIALLY COMPLETE DIVISION RINGS 198 § 1 Inner Automorphisms 199 § 2 Transcendental Elements and Subfields 202 § 3 Centralizers and Maximal Subfields 207 § 4 Embeddings and Extensions 215 § 5 The Number of Finitely Generated 219 Division Algebras CHAPTER 15 NULLSTELLENSATZ 223 CHAPTER 16 CLASSES OF EXISTENTIALLY COMPLETE 232 DIVISION ALGEBRAS § 1 Structures for Second Order Arithmetic 233 § 2 An Interpretation of the Language 236 of Second Order Arithmetic § 3 Second Order Arithmetic and Classes 241 of Existentially Complete Division Algebras IIV BIBLIOGRAPHY 253 SUBJECT INDEX 261 INTRODUCTION Forcing in model theory is a recent development in the metamathematics of algebra. The context of this development has three principal features: the importance of algebraically closed fields in commutative algebra and the existence of analogues of algebraically closed fields for other algebraic systems, earlier work on model-completeness and model-completions by Abraham Robinson and others, and Paul Cohen's forcing techniques in set theory. Algebraically closed fields serve a useful function in commutative algebra, algebraic number theory, and algebraic geometry. Certain arithmetical questions can be settled conclusively in an algebraically closed field. Examples are well-known. For instance, a system of polynomials has a common zero in some extension of their coefficient field if and only if they have a common zero in the algebraic closure of their coefficient field. In algebraic number theory, the study of the prolongations of a valuation from its base field to a finite dimen- sional extension field reduces to the consideration of the embeddings of the extension field into the algebraic closure of the completion of the base field. A third example is the use of universal domains in algebraic geometry as the proper setting for the study of algebraic varieties over fields. In these and other instances, the existence and use of algebraically closed fields simplify the treatment of many mathematical problems. The usefulness of algebraically closed fields has motivated the development of analogues for other algebraic systems. The best known analogue is the class of real closed ordered fields, introduced by Artin and Schreier for the solution of Hilbert's seventeenth problem on ordered fields. Another important analogue is the Henselization of a discrete, nonarchimedean valued field (see Ax & Kochen (4)). Analogues have been introduced also for other algebraic systems, including groups .W( R. Scott (iO1)), abelian groups .r( Szele (106)), modules .P( Eklof & .G Sabbagh (34)), commutative rings .G( Cherlin (17)), commutative rings without nilpotent elements .D( Saracino & .L Lipshitz (98), A. Carson (12)), and on a more abstract level, universal algebra .P( M. Cohn (20), B. Jonsson (49)). While some analogues have been quite productive, others have presented almost insuperable difficulties. Algebraically closed groups are an example of the latter. In 1951 W. R. Scott defined a group G to be algebraically closed if each finite system of equations and inequalities of the form I = w 2 e, = w e, ..., n = w I e, ~ v e, 2 ~ v e, ..., m ~ v e (where the i w and vj are words in indeterminates and elements of G) with a solution in some extension of G has a solution in G itself. During the next year, .B H. Neumann (70) showed that only equations need be considered in the above definition and that every algebraically closed group is simple. No more work was done on these groups until 1969, when Neumann (71) proved that each finitely generated, recursively absolutely presented group is a subgroup of every algebraically closed group. Since algebraically closed groups are simple, they have not been amenable to the usual methods of group theory. However, they can be investigated through forcing techniques. Algebraically closed fields have a special significance for mathematical logic also. The theory of algebraically closed fields is the canonical example of each of the following concepts: a complete theory, a model-complete theory, a totally transcendental theory, and an ~l-categorical but not ~O-categorical theory. Moreover, algebraically closed fields were the starting point for the metamathematics of algebra. Relationships between the theory of fields and the theory of algebraically closed fields led to the concepts of model-completeness and model-completion .A( Robinson). From the point of view of algebra, the concept of a model-completion has been the most useful metamathematical concept introduced by logicians. For example, algebraically closed fields are the model-completion of commutative fields; real closed ordered fields are the model-completion of ordered fields; Hensel fields are the model-completion of discrete, nonarchimedean valued fields; and Szele's algebraically closed abelian groups are the model-completion of abelian groups. Both the Nullstellen- satz and Hilbert's seventeenth problem are consequences of the model- completeness of algebraically closed fields and of real closed ordered fields, respectively. Furthermore, the notion of a model-completion led A. Robinson to the definition and proof of the existence of differentially closed fields. The notion of a model-completion was weakened in 1969 by Eli Bers to that of a model-companion. A theory T* is called the model-companion of a theory T if )i( T and T* are mutually model-consistent, i.e., each model of T is contained in a model of T* and vice versa, and (ii) T* is model-complete, i.e., whenever M and M' are models of T* and M' contains M, then any sentence defined in M is true in M if and only if it is true in M'. Any model- completion is also a model-companion. However, some theories, for example, formally real fields, have a model-companion but not a model-completion. This phenomenon occurs when the original theory does not have the amalgamation property. The concept of a model-companion encompasses all of the common, useful analogues in algebra of algebraically closed fields. The second requirement in the definition of a model-companion, that T* must be model-complete, is the essence of "being algebraically closed" and is also the more difficult of the two requirements to satisfy. Robinson's model-completeness test demonstrates the first assertion. A formula ~(Vo,... , Vn) in a first order logic is called primitive if it consists of a string of existential quantifiers

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.