ebook img

Food for Thought PDF

284 Pages·1989·14.731 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Food for Thought

Food for Thought Parallax• •R e-visions of Culture and Society Stephen G. Nichols, Gerald Prince, and Wendy Steiner, SERIES EDITORS Louis Marin Translated, with an Afterword, by Mette Hjort The Johns Hopkins University Press Baltimore and London This book has been brought to publication with the generous assistance of the French Ministry of Culture. Originally published as La parole mangee et autres ~ssais theologico politiques. © Librairie des Meridiens, Klincksieck & c1e, 1986. This Eng lish language edition © 1989 The Johns Hopkins University Press Chapter 10, "Recipes of Power ('Puss-in-Boots')" was previously published as "Puss-in-Boots: Power of Signs-Signs of Power" in Diacritics (June 1977): 54-63. All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America The Johns Hopkins University Press, 701 West 4oth Street, Baltimore, Maryland 21211 The Johns Hopkins Press Ltd., London The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of American National Standard for Information Sciences-Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI z39.48-1984. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Marin, Louis, 1931- [Parole mangee et autres essais theologico-politiques. English] Food for thought I Louis Marin; translated, with an afterword, by Mette Hjort. p. cm. - (Parallax : re-visions of culture and society) Translation of: La parole mangee et autres essais theologico- politiques. Bibliography: p. Includes index. ISBN 0-8018-3476-7 (alk. paper). 1. Body, Human, in literature. 2. Human figure in art. 3~ Body, Human (Philosophy) 4. Power (Philosophy) I. Title. II. Series: Parallax (Baltimore, Md.) PN56.B62M3713 1989 844:914-dc19 88-29342 CIP For fudith Contents List of Illustrations ix Introduction to the English-Language Edition xi Part I: Food for Thought The Body of the Divinity Captured by Signs 3 Part II: Eat, Speak, and Write 2 "Donkey-Skin," or Orality 29 3 Little Butterpot, or the Spell of the Voice 39 4 The Fabulous Animal 44 5 "The Reason of the Strongest Is Always the Best" 55 6 Utopic Rabelaisian Bodies 85 Part III: The Culinary Sign in the Land of Fairies and Ogres 7 Theoretical Aperitif II? 8 Roast Blood Sausage, or the Gush of Performatives 126 9 Robert Sauce 133 IO Recipes of Power 148 II Stew and Roast, or the Mastery of Discourse and the Illusions of Eros 162 12 Butcher's Meat and Game, or the Culinary Sign within Generalized Communication 175 viii Contents Part IV: The King's Body 13 The Portrait of the King's Glorious Body 14 The Pathetic Body and Its Doctor: The "Medical Diary of Louis x 1 v" 218 Afterword: Portrait of the Translator 243 Bibliography Index Illustrations Ilustration of La Fontaine's "The Lamb and the Wolf," by M. Oudry (Photograph courtesy of Giraudon/Art Resource, New York.) 62 Reconstruction of the Abbey of Theleme, by Charles Lenor mant (Photograph courtesy of Giraudon/Art Resource, New York.) 88 Illustration of Perrault's "Sleeping Beauty in the Forest," by G. Dore (Photograph courtesy of the Bibliotheque Nationale.) 138 Illustration of Perrault's "Puss-in-Boots," by G. Dore (Photograph courtesy of the Bibliotheque Nationale.) 157 Illustration of Perrault's "Ricky with the Tuft," by G. Dore (Photograph courtesy of the Bibliotheque Nationale.) 171 Illustration of Perrault's "Tom Thumb," by G. Dore (Photograph courtesy of Collection Viollet.) 182 Louis xiv by Hyacinthe Rigaud (Louvre) (Photograph courtesy of Giraudon/Art Resource, New York.) 201 Caricature by Thackeray of Rigaud's portrait of Louis x 1 v in The Paris Sketch by Titmarsh (In Works of Thackeray. Vol. XVI. London: Charter House Edition, 1901: 313bis.) 210 Introduction to the English-Language Edition In bringing the Augustinian tradition to its cul mination within the Cartesian episteme, the Logic of Port-Royal (1662-83) sums up a long chapter in the history of Western semi otics. In this crucial text, the logicians define the very structure of signification as representation. Following such a conception, ideas represent things to the mind, and signs are the representa tions of these ideas for other minds. This representation of a rep resentation is the meaning of a sign, and this meaning is true to the extent that it corresponds to the idea and, thereby, to the thing signified. The ideal of the sign, if not its ideality as well, involves a process of self-effacement that leaves it transparent before the thing, an effacement that is all the more easily achieved and justified by the conventional nature of the sign when no mimetic relation obtains between the sign and its signified. If, then, the whole structure of signification consists of a doub ling, we may note that this duplication is accompanied by a sub stitution of the thing for the sign or, alternately, by a reduction of the sign to the thing. Indeed, it is precisely this reduction that is, ipso facto, constitutive of objectivity: here is the object's true foundation. We may well question the coherence of this reduc tive process because it appears to annul the first moment (the doubling or duplication). It is the purpose or function of the sign and of representation to guarantee that individual minds may xii Introduction to the English-Language Edition communicate being and truth to one another. Indeed, the sign as representation is functional, and this characteristic of the sign defines its objective structure. The converse is true in the case of the object, which manifests its structure in the sign's representa tion, that is, in its function; this very function constitutes the pragmatic dimension of the sign. By the same token, a community of minds wholly transparent to one another and embodying a kind of rational sociability estab lishes itself within the reversibility that lies at the basis of their intercommunication. Such, then, would be the essential struc ture and function of the linguistic sign. Thus, we understand that this representational theory of the sign finds (thesei) its author ity and justification in the particular de jure or conventional rela tion that it bears to an absent entity or thing. If representation means the substitution of an x for an absent y, then it is the juri dical conformity of what is present to what is absent-in other words, the isomorphism-that justifies the substitution. Opti mally, the transparency of the representation affords the sign its transitive dimension. To represent is to represent something. The operative character of this formal relation between what is present and what is absent ensures that the former functions in the place of and assumes the function of the latter. Representa tion carries the effect of an object. Yet this substitution between things and signs, a substitution generally characteristic of all representations or signs, is itself an oriented process. Replacing the sign with the thing can achieve an effect of objectivity within the rational universality of a dis course of knowledge. The process may also be inverted. Then signs take the place of things, representation substitutes for being, and the world of signs achieves an autonomy that allows it to deploy itself as a screen displaying the entire universe of things. This world is all the more deceptive or seductive precisely because it betrays its imitative nature {phusei). In it, the universal objectivity of true knowledge, systematically elaborated and enhanced within a rational discourse, comes to be replaced by the subjective infinity of individual desires. These desires find a bond or connection in an ever-deferred and differing satisfaction realized in the various pleasures of the imagination and sensibility. A different society develops as a result, a society that no longer espouses the funda mental value of what Augustine calls uti. As opposed to valoriz ing the use of signs, this society prefers the frui or intense thrill

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.