ebook img

Ethics for Enemies - Terror, Torture, and War PDF

194 Pages·2011·21.973 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Ethics for Enemies - Terror, Torture, and War

ETHICFSO R ENEMIES TERROTRO,R TURE, ANDW AR F.M.KA MM OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS OXFORD UNIVJIJI.S!T'I' PILBSS Great Oarmdon Street. Oxford oxi 6DP Oxford Uoivcmty Press is a depanment of lhe UnM:nityo fO xford. It fortll= tht Univcuity's ob;ective of aa:llenc.e in research, sdlolanhip, alld educatioo by pubJisJ,ing worldwide in Oxfonl New York \vi •1...d Cape Town Dar cs Salaam Hoog Koog Karachi. Km1a Lumpnr Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi Kew Delhi Sbangbai Taipei "foronto Wrth offices in Argentina Aosaia Brazil Chile C1>ech Republic Fr.in« GIUOC ('JUataUala Hungary Italy Japan Po&and Portugal Singapore Solllh Korea Switterlaod Thailand Turk l;'\:raine Vaetaam ey Ou>rd is a ttgistaed trade mark ofOr. ford l:nivcnity Press in the UK and in certain other c:ounlries Pnblisl>ed in the United SWes by Oxford University Press loc., � Yon: OF. M. Kamm 2011 The moral rigbl!I of the author have bceo aucrtcd Daubase right Oxford l,'niYenity Pit$$ (mal<tt) first published 20U AD rights �d. No part of this pul,licatioo. may be reproduc.cd, stored in a retmval srstcm. or tnnsmitted. in any fonn or by any means. without the prior perrola&ion in writing ofO xford Uni�ity Press, oras e:ipre:5$1y pennitkd hy law, or under tmns agreed with th" appropriale reprograpbics rights (rrgani,aooo. Enquiries concerning rcpl'oduction outs.idc the llCOpe of the :ibove should be sent fD � Ri8frts Department, Oxford Univcmty Pres.,, at the a� above Yoo most oot circolarz this book in any other binding or rover and you most impo5" lhe same condition on any acquirer British .lib Cawoglling io Publication Data rary Data available Library of Congi-ess Cataloging in Publication Data. Data awilabk Typeset by SPI Publisher Services. Pondic.berry, India Printed in Gteat Britain OD acid·ff'Ce paper by MPG Books Group, Bodmin and King's Lynn ISBN 9']8--<>-19-96<>873-z 3S79l08612 The USeehriiirnPeo rs a cEttihciacls {n 2002 the Uehiro foundation on .Ethics and Education, chaired by Mr :Eiji Uehiro, established the Uehiro Chair in Practical Ethics at the University of Oxford. The following year the Oxford Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics was created within the Philosophy Faculty. Generous support by the Uehiro Foundation enabled the establishment of an annual lecture series, 'lbe Uehiro Lectures in Practical Ethics. These three lectures, given each year in Oxford, capture the ethos of the Oxford Uehiro Centre for Pn1ctic.al Elhics: to bring the best scholarship in ana­ lytic philosophy to bear on the most si ificant problems of our time. gn The aim is to make progress in the anal is and resolution of these issues ys to the highest academic standard in a manner that is accessible to the general public. Philosophy should not only create knowledge, it should make people's lives better. Books based upon the lectures are published by Oxford University Press in the Uehiro Series in Practical Ethics. Julian Savulescu Uehiro Chair in Pnlctical Ethics Director, Oxford Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics, University of Oxford .Editor, The Uehiro Series in Practical Ethics In memory ofmy uncle, Samuel Kamm, with thanks for his crucial help at crucial times CONTE NTS 1 INTRODUCTION 3 TORTURE: DURING AND AFTER ACTION 73T ERRORISM ANDI NTENDEIVN1IG. 119 REASONS FOR STARTING WAR: GOALS, CONDITIONS, AND PR.0.PORTION.ALITY 16B9IB UOGRAPHY 17IN3D liX INTRODUCTION This book is composed of revised versions of the three Uehiro Lectures that l gave at Oxford University in November-December 2oo8. I am very grateful to Professor Julian Savulescu, head of the Uehiro C..entre for Practical Ethics at Oxford University, for having invited me to give these lectures. For the most part, the book considers how certain distinctions that I have explored in my work on ethical theory bear on aspects of the practicalp roblems ofte rrorism, torture, and war. 1 (I empha.,;ize "aspects," as I do not attempt to provide complete discussion of these problems.) a In general, after working on certain issues in ethical theory, I often become aware of how these same issues arise in practical contexts. This is how, in the past, I came to write on several topics in bioethics, such as allocation of scarce resources and physician-assisted suicide. My interest in terrorism, torture, and war arose in the same way. By contra.,;t, others begin with a deep concern about the practical problems themselves. may However, considering the practical problems, I find, can also help uncover new considerations and distinctions and so lead to revisions in one's ethical theory. My method in dealing with both ethical theory and pra<..tical is.rues makes heavy use of hypothetical cases. Such cases can be varied at will. thus test whether a factor is morally significant by comparing the One can moral status of a with the factor and a without the factor, hold­ case case ing all other factors in the constant While the cases may cases sometimes unrealistic, they are somewhat artificial, controlled experiments seem like in science that eventually yield results for situations. real-life Chapter , ," Torture: During and After Action," considers whether those who are responsihle for creating lethal threats may be tortured during and after their threatening acts to stop those acts or harm from them. I consider different conceptions of torture and the different occasions when torture might occur in order to isolate factors relevant to the moral status of torturing a wrongdoer held captive. I have previously written on 2 lr-ITRODU(.TION the inviolability of nonthreatening persons. This chapter considers what may and may not be done to threatening persons and when. Chapter 2, "Terrorism and Intending Evil," is primarily concerned with whether intending to harm a civilian can account for the special wrongness of terrorism, and also whether such an intention is always an indication of the presence of terrorism. This chapter deals with a practi­ cal application of the theoretical question, whether the intention with which an act is done bears on the act's permissibility. Chapter 3, "Reasons for Starting War: Goals, C'.onditions, and Proportionality;' is also, in part, concerned with whether having a proper jntention is ne�y in order to make action pe�ible, in this case, starting war. It goes on lo consider how the theoretical distinction between acting in order to bring about a good efef ct and acting on condition that one will bring it about may bear on the permissibility of causing side-efef ct harm (sometimes called collater-.tl damage) to civilians in war. The aim is to determine whether and how bad side effects can be proportional to the good effects of war so that we may pursue a just cause by means of war. A recurring theme of these chapters is whether prohibitions that have been thought to be based on considerations that make an act wrong in itself may rather he based on consequcntialist considerations, if they are prohibitions at all. That is, we ask whether certain prohibitions arc justi­ fied on the grouncl that what they rule out is intrinsically wrong or rather on the ground that the consequences of acting in certain ways, and features of agents who would act, might rule out certain conduct. The chapters are self-contained and each may be read on it,; own. Each has its own conclusion and acknowledgments. However, I am especially grateful to those who have read all three chapters and also provided challenging philosophical discussion, including Ruth Chang, Johann Frick, Shelly Kagan, JeffMcMahan, Derek Parfit, Julian Savulescu, and Larry Temkin. Lynne Meyer Gay's skills were crucial to preparing the manuscript. I am most indebted to Derek Parfitand Thomas Scanlon for their intelligence, kindness, and support over the years. Note 1. For the theoretical discussion, sec, for example, my Intricate Ethics: Rights, Res­ ponsibilities, and Permissible Harm (New York: Oxford University Press, WO'J) . l TORTURDEU:R INAGN DA FTEARC TION Nowadays when we hear the word torture, we think of wrongful, brutal treatment of people in custody whose use in the "war on ter­ ror" has recently been a matter of great concern. But sometimes we seem to be tempted to apply the word torture to cases that are unlike this. We may wonder whether doing this is correct and begin to think about the characteristics in virtue of which we identify something as torture. We may also wonder what specific characteristics of wrong­ ful torture make it wrong. Is it just the fact that it is torture? Or is it possible that we need not be misidentifying behavior as torture if we think that the behavior is moraUy permissible? This chapter is about these issues. In Intricate Ethics,1 I wrote concerning universal human rights: There are at least two ways in which the claim that there are such human rights can be understood: (1) AU that is needed in order to come to have certain rights is that one be a human person. {2) All that is needed in order to come to have and continue to have certain rights is that one be a human person. While there may be some rights that satisfy (2), most rights that are now considered human rights do not satisfy iL They only satisfy (1). For example, the right to free movement, the right not to be killed, and the right to free speech may all be forfeited in virtue of one's conduct. I Ience, if there are human rights in sense (1), this docs not mean that every human person always has such rights just in virtue of being a human person. Consider some practical implications of this. Some argue against capital punishment on the ground that it violates a human right not to be killed. They favor incarceration instead. But in the same sense (1) in which there is a right not to be killed, there is a right not to be deprived of liberty. If one can forfeit a right to liberty by bad 4 TORTURE: DURING AND AFTER ACTION acts and so can be permissibly i�carcerated as punishment, then it is not dear why one could not forfeit the right not to be killed (even when one is not presently a threat). Some argue that there is a human right not to be tortured. Others argue that it would take the need to stop a ticking bomb that threatens an enormous number of people to justify torturing even those who set the bomb. But suppose that a villain is about to set a bomb that will shortly kill one child. Presumably, the villain has no right that we not kill him, if only this would stop his setting the bomb. Furthermore, tortur· ing someone for a short period seems less bad for him than death. Then why does the villain also have no right not to be tortured, if torturing him rather than killing him would also stop his setting the bomb? And if we arc unable to kill him, but only able to torture him in order to stop his setting the bomb, might he not also have no righl not to be tortured? This chapter reconsiders some issues in that short discussion by examining aspects of two prominent discussions of torture by Henry Shue2 and David Sussman.3 Their discussions raise conceptual issues-­ that i what torlur,e is--that might help us decide whether we could s, correctly apply the term to doing what stops the villain from killing the child. Their discussions also raise normative issues-that is, whether there is something morally distinctive about tortrne and whether tor· ture is impermissible on deontological rather than on consequentialist grounds. (That is, whether torture is wrong just in virtue of what we would do, independent of whether it would have further bad effects.) I shall critically examine Shue's and Sussman's discussions and try to present an alternative perspective. In this discussion, I shall focus primarily on cases in which (what might be) torture wouJd be used on people (a) when evidence arrived at inde­ pendently of torture conclusively shows them to be wrongdoers (e .g., ter· rorists) and (b) when their being tortured is the only way to get something we need (c) to certainly stop the imminent succcs.� of their own murder­ ous plot.4 This excludes cases where torture is most likely to be morally wrong because (i) it i� done to people not known to be wrongdoers in order to find evidence that they are wrongdoers, (ii) it is done to those whom one knows are innocent as a means of stopping someone else's TORl"URE: DURING AND AFT lR ACTION S murderous plots, (iii) it is done to acquire what is not necessary to stop a threat or may have only a small chance of stopping a threat, and (iv) it is done when there is no certain and imminent murderous threat to stop. There has been much philosophical discussion of why it would be wrong to deliberately kill one innocent person to stop other innocent people from being killed bya wrongdoer. My own preferred explanation of this is in terms of the moral status of every innocent person, which rules out the permissibility of violating them seriously. 5 I shall as.rume that the status of such persons would also prevent us from torturing them to save other innocents from being murdered. The question is whether this status is retained by a wrongdoer responsible for the immi­ nent murderous plot against those innocents. As I have said, the topic of torture has been raised for many by the treatment of prisoners byt he United States and some ofi ts allies follow­ ing the September u, 2001a ttack on the World Trade C'.cnter in New York City and the war in Afghanistan. My discussion does not attempt to deal with these actions in particular, as this would require detailed empirical information. However, it does bear on how these actions should be evaluated, given full knowledge of what theyin volved, and it bears on strategies some have used to deny that these actions involved torture. It is important to remember that even if a discussion of torture showed that it could be morally permissible in some cases, this need not imply that any torture that might have been carried out by the United States or its allies was permissible.6 I. Conceptual Issues First, let us consider the conceptual issues with only minimal altention to moral issues theyra ise. That is, let us consider what torture is, by con­ trast to other types of behavior, with only minimal attention to whether it ( or they) are permissible. A. SHUE Shue emphasi1,cs that his characterization of torture is based on torture as it is commonly practiced (at the time he wrote). He is not claiming to offer a conceptual analysis and he concedes that there are many types

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.