ebook img

Ethical Theory: A Concise Anthology PDF

399 Pages·2000·22.72 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Ethical Theory: A Concise Anthology

This electronic material is under copyright protection and is provided to a single recipient for review purposes only. ETHICAL THEORY Review Copy This page intentionally left blank Review Copy ETHICAL THEORY: A CONCISE ANTHOLOGY EDITED BY HEIMIR GEIRSSON MARGARET R. HOLMGREN broadview press Review Copy ©2000 Heimir Geirsson and Margaret R. Holmgren Reprinted, 2001 All rights reserved. The use of any part of this publication reproduced, transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or other- wise, or stored in a retrieval system, without prior written consent of the publisher — or in the case of photocopying, a licence from CANCOPY (Canadian Copyright Licens- ing Agency) One Yonge Street, Suite 1900, Toronto, Ontario M5E 1E5 — is an infringement of the copyright law. Canadian Cataloguing in Publication Data Main entry under title: Ethical theory: a concise anthology Includes bibliographical references. ISBN 1-55111-292-2 1. Ethics. I. Geirsson, Heimir. II. Holmgren, Margaret R. (Margaret Reed), 1951- BJ1012.E87 2000 170 COO-930904-7 Broadview Press Ltd. is an independent, international publishing house, incorporated in 1985. North America Post Office Box 1243, Peterborough, Ontario, Canada K9J 7H5 3576 California Road, Orchard Park, NY 14127 Tel: (705) 743-8990; Fax: (705) 743-8353; e-mail: [email protected] United Kingdom: Turpin Distribution Services, Ltd., Blackhorse Rd., Letchworth, Hertfordshire SG6 1HN Tel: (1462) 672555; Fax: (1462) 480947; e-mail: [email protected] Australia: St. Clair Press, P.O. Box 287, Rozelle, NSW 2039 Tel: (02) 818-1942; Fax: (02) 418-1923 www.broadviewpress.com Broadview Press gratefully acknowledges the financial support of the Book Publishing Industry Development Program, Ministry of Canadian Heritage, Government of Cana- da. Typesetting and assembly: True to Type Inc., Mississauga, Canada. PRINTED IN CANADA Review Copy CONTENTS CHAPTER ONE: ETHICAL RELATIVISM Introduction 1 1. Selections from Folkways, WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER 5 2. Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, WILLIAM H. SHAW 12 CHAPTER Two: DIVINE COMMAND THEORY Introduction 33 3. Euthyphro, PLATO 38 4. The Story of Abraham, THE BIBLE 54 CHAPTER THREE: EGOISM Introduction 57 5. The Myth of Gyges, PLATO 61 6. Egoism and Moral Scepticism, JAMES RACHELS 70 CHAPTER FOUR: CONSEQUENTIALISM Introduction 81 7. Selection from Utilitarianism, JOHN STUART MILL 86 8. An Outline of a System of Utilitarian Ethics, J.J.C. SMART 95 9. The Experience Machine, ROBERT NOZICK 106 CHAPTER FIVE: DEONTOLOGY Introduction 109 10. Selection from The Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, IMMANUEL KANT 113 11. A Simplified Version of Kant's Ethics: Perplexities of Famine and World Hunger, ONORA O'NEILL 131 12. What Makes Right Acts Right?, W.D. Ross 142 CHAPTER Six: JUSTICE Introduction 167 13. Selection from A Theory of Justice, JOHN RAWLS 170 14. The Entitlement Theory, ROBERT NOZICK 189 Review Copy vi Contents CHAPTER SEVEN: VIRTUE ETHICS Introduction 209 15. Selection from Nichomachean Ethics, ARISTOTLE 213 16. On Some Vices of Virtue Ethics, ROBERT B. LOUDEN 231 17. Virtue Theory and Abortion, ROSALIND HURSTHOUSE 247 CHAPTER EIGHT: FEMINIST ETHICS Introduction 269 18. Selection from In a Different Voice, CAROL GILLIGAN 273 19. Women and Caring, NEL NODDINGS 285 CHAPTER NINE: THEORIES IN PRACTICE Introduction 295 20. The Message of Affirmative Action, THOMAS E. HILL, JR. 296 21. Rich and Poor, PETER SINGER 320 22. Perspectives On World Hunger and The Extent Of Our Positive Duties, ROBERT N. VAN WYK 340 23. Why Abortion Is Immoral, DONALD MARQUIS 355 24. Abortion Through A Feminist Ethics Lens, SUSAN SHERWIN 374 SOURCES 391 Review Copy CHAPTER ONE ETHICAL RELATIVISM INTRODUCTION Some cultures approve of abortions while other cultures do not. Some cul- tures approve of capital punishment while other cultures do not. And some cultures approve of slavery while other cultures do not. There is a great diver- sity of social norms and rules, and there seem to be significant disagreements from one culture to the next about what is right and wrong. Further, ethicists often disagree among themselves about what is right and wrong, and ethical theories often give conflicting answers to the same moral problems. The evi- dence seems to suggest that there are no objective or universal moral values. But if there are no objective moral values, then there is no absolute right or wrong. And if there is no absolute right or wrong, we presumably have to embrace relativism of some sort. Relativism comes in various forms and not all of them are directly relevant to ethical theory. Anthropology informs us of a wide variety of social norms, and shows us that different cultures have different moral rules. But anthro- pology is descriptive in nature and it only presents to us a descriptive form of relativism. It tells us how people do behave and not how they should behave. A different kind of relativism is moral relativism. Moral relativism is the thesis that what is right or good is determined by the relevant party. If the rel- evant party is an individual, then we have individual moral relativism. Accord- ing to individual moral relativism, what is right or good is determined by each individual. If the relevant party is a culture, then we have cultural moral rel- ativism. According to cultural moral relativism, what is right or wrong is deter- mined by each culture. Each of these versions of moral relativism holds that there are no objective moral values, and no basic moral demands that are binding on all moral agents. (The next section of this book addresses the lat- ter claim more fully.) It is important to recognize that descriptive relativism does not entail moral relativism. In order to see why this is so, assume for the sake of argu- ment that there are objective moral values. Given this assumption, moral rel- ativism is clearly false. In this case there is a single truth of the matter about morality, and individuals or cultures cannot stipulate for themselves what is right and wrong. If an individual or culture decides on a moral standard that conflicts with objective moral values, then their standard is mistaken. If we assume that there are objective moral values, descriptive relativism may still be correct, however. It is quite possible, and even probable, that some indi- viduals and cultures will make mistakes in thinking about and determining Review Copy 2 Ethical Theory moral values. Mistakes may be quite diverse, as there are many different ways of getting things wrong. Therefore, we can hold that there are objective moral values and at the same time account for the wide variation in moral standards from culture to culture and from individual to individual. It is clearly possible, then, for descriptive relativism to be true and for moral rela- tivism to be false. By the same line of reasoning, we can see that descriptive relativism does not entail the thesis that there are no objective moral values. It is clearly possible that there are objective moral values, but that people dis- agree widely on the question of what these values are. Descriptive relativism provides us with many examples of how people actually behave, but by itself it tells us nothing about the truth of moral relativism or the truth of the thesis that there are no objective moral values. Is moral relativism tenable? Many people believe that individual moral rel- ativism is not. In order to function as a society we need to agree on some basic moral standards. We cannot simply allow each individual to make up his or her own moral code. If we were to proceed in this manner, life would be, as Hobbes put it, nasty, brutish, and short. The foregoing consideration does not show that individual moral relativism is false, but it does suggest a prag- matic reason for rejecting this position as tenable. Once we recognize that a common moral code is needed, cultural moral relativism may seem like a viable thesis even if we reject individual moral relativism. Can we defend cultural moral relativism? Before we answer this question, let us consider more carefully what this position entails. In order to function as a society, we need to agree on some basic moral standards. But this is not to say that all societies need to agree on the same moral standards. Further, subcultures within a society do not have to agree on all moral rules. They can differ significantly from one another and for the most part coexist peaceful- ly, although their differences may sometimes erupt in violence or even civil wars. A cultural moral relativist need only hold that the predominant moral standards accepted by a given society determine what is right and wrong for the members of that society. At first glance, however, this position may seem to lead to inconsistencies. Suppose that Amy and Grant are talking about abortion, and that Amy is a cultural moral relativist while Grant believes there are objective moral values. Amy starts by arguing that there is nothing morally wrong with abortion. By citing a few examples, Grant gets Amy to concede that some cultures regard abortion as morally wrong. He then accuses Amy of inconsistency, claiming that her position entails both the conclusion that abortion is not morally wrong (because in some cultures it is not) and the conclusion that it is moral- ly wrong. But Grant is on the wrong track here. Cultural moral relativism is not inconsistent. Suppose that culture X believes that abortion is morally wrong, and culture Y believes that abortion is not morally wrong. The cultur- al moral relativist will make the following two claims: (1) it is true that it is Review Copy 3 Ethical Relativism morally wrong for persons in culture X to have abortions, and (2) it is true that it is not morally wrong for persons in culture Y to have abortions. These two claims are fully compatible with one another. The cultural moral relativist holds that actions are not right or wrong per se—they are only right or wrong relative to a given moral framework. It is obviously possible for an action to be right relative to one moral framework and wrong relative to another. If Grant is smart, he will reframe his objection to Amy's position. Although cultural moral relativism is not inconsistent, it seems to conflict with some of our most basic intuitions about morality. Suppose that you meet an individ- ual from culture Z, a culture that practices a brutal form of slavery. This indi- vidual, Zack, informs you that the practice of slavery is considered morally legitimate in his society, and that it is morally legitimate for him to buy and sell certain individuals, to torture them at will, and to hold them as slaves. If cultural moral relativism is true, then it is true that it is morally permissible for Zack to engage in this practice, and it is also true that it would be moral- ly wrong for you to practice slavery, given that you are a member of a culture which abhors such a practice. In the context of this position, there is really no source of disagreement between you and Zack. You might be tempted to tell Zack that slavery is morally wrong, but if you are a cultural moral relativist, the only claim you can make is that slavery is wrong relative to the moral code that your society accepts. If you look at the situation objectively, you will rec- ognize that slavery is morally permissible relative to the moral code that Zack's society accepts. In order to respond to Zack in an appropriate and enlightened manner, you should say something like "How interesting that your society accepts such an extensive practice of slavery. My society does not accept this practice at all. Our societies are quite different, but there is no objective way to adjudicate between our competing moral codes." Intuitively, however, most of us would not consider this to be an adequate response. We would want to argue strenuously that it is morally abhorrent to enslave and torture human beings. We would want to offer many strong rea- sons why one ought not to torture people and hold them as slaves, and to assert that if they constitute good reasons for people in our culture not to behave in this manner, they also constitute good reasons for people in culture Z not to behave in this manner. We would want to ask Zack what arguments he could possibly make to justify such a practice. And we would probably want to condemn culture Z in the strongest possible terms. It is not clear, then, that cultural moral relativism provides an adequate account of moral disagree- ment, nor is it clear that we should accept the claim that there is nothing wrong with torture and slavery in a society in which these practices are accepted as legitimate. Similar points can be made with respect to disagreement within a society. Suppose that there is a single member of culture Z who firmly believes that their practice of slavery is morally abhorrent, and who does everything in her

Description:
This anthology is designed for use as a brief introduction to ethical theory. Included are sections on various forms of ethical theory: Ethical Relativism; Divine Command Theory; Egoism; Consequentialism; Deontology; Justice; Virtue Ethics; and Feminist Ethics. Each section includes two or three of
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.