ebook img

Establishing Geographies of Children and Young People PDF

113 Pages·1.918 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Establishing Geographies of Children and Young People

Spinoza (and) the Spider: Theorizing Childhood as Capacities of Affection and Affect Giorgio Hadi Curti Contents 1 Introduction................................................................................... 2 2 Spinoza(and)theSpider..................................................................... 3 3 OfChildren,Fools,andMadmen............................................................ 5 4 DeussiveNatura............................................................................. 6 5 WeWillSaythatItImagines...(or,ThePassion[of]BodilyThought)................... 9 6 AnAssemblage-WebofSpinoza’sMetaphysicsandBenjamin’sChild.................... 13 7 Conclusion.................................................................................... 17 References........................................................................................ 19 Abstract Thischaptertheorizeschildhoodascapacitiesofaffectionandaffectbyworking throughtheimmanentphilosophyofBenedictdeSpinozaandintersectingsome of its conceptual threads with Walter Benjamin’s understanding of children and revolutionaryactionthroughplay.Aspartofthismove,Spinozaisapproachedas both a complex weaver and intricate traverser of a web of immanence, and particular attention is paid to his characterization of the embodied imagination and its relationship to different forms of knowing and understanding. Spinoza’s ontological system of immanence in general – and his understanding of the embodied imagination in particular – provides promising metaphysical threads uponwhichtostepawayfromnotionsofchildhoodorchildrenasage-dependent representations or stages within identificational schemes of linear development to, instead, approach and understand them as immanent bodily capacities. The importofthismoveandtheuniversalimplicationsitholdsfornotionsofpolitical agencyofchildrenisalsodiscussed. G.H.Curti(*) DepartmentofGeography,SanDiegoStateUniversity,SanDiego,CA,USA e-mail:[email protected] #SpringerScience+BusinessMediaSingapore2016 1 T.Skelton,S.Aitken(eds.),EstablishingGeographiesofChildrenandYoungPeople, GeographiesofChildrenandYoungPeople1,DOI10.1007/978-981-4585-88-0_2-1 2 G.H.Curti Keywords Spinoza (cid:129) Immanence (cid:129) Affection and affect (cid:129) Imagination (cid:129) Walter Benjamin (cid:129) Embodiment 1 Introduction TheseventeenthcenturyDutchSephardicJewishphilosopherBaruch(Benedict)de Spinozaisafigure–orperhapsitwouldbemorefittingtosay,conceptualpersona– who has long effected intense feelings of hatred and love, despair and joy, utter disgustandutmostadmiration–sometimesinthesamepersonatthesametime(e.g., Nietzsche(seeYovel1986)andLeibniz(seeStewart2006)).Ononehistoricalhand, hehaszealouslybeenmalignedasthemostdeviantofheretics,anatheisticpurveyor ofthegreatest“abominableheresies”and“monstrousdeeds”(KasherandBiderman 2001, p. 86; see Stewart 2006); on another, he has been identified as a “God- intoxicated man” (Novalis, cited in Stewart 2006, p. 160) and lovingly revered as the“Christofphilosophers,”aredeemeroflifewhosethoughtembodiesa“vertigo ofimmanencefromwhichsomanyphilosopherstryinvaintoescape”(Deleuzeand Guattari1994,p.48).CommentingonthevanguardnatureofSpinoza’sphilosophy, DeleuzeandGuattari(1994,p.48)hintatthecauseofsuchantipodalreactionstothe metaphysicalchallengesSpinoza’sthoughtpresentswhentheynotethathewas“the philosopher who knew full well that immanence was only immanent to itself and therefore that it was a plane traversed by movements of the infinite, filled with intensiveordinates...Hediscoveredfreedomexistsonlywithinimmanence...”;and theyask“...WillweeverbematureenoughforSpinozistinspiration?” But,whatexactlyisittobecomematureenoughforSpinozistinspiration?Itisto understandandaccept–andthereforenecessarilyactontheknowledge–thatallthat isis,andthatanysubstantive,Cartesian-likeseparationsofmind(thought)andbody (extension)orthesacred(God)andprofane(Nature)arenothingmorethanconfused absurdities. This is because, as Spinoza tells us, “God is the immanent, not the transitive,causeofallthings”(Ethics,I,P.18).Criticaltograspfromthisproposition specifically,andwithinSpinoza’sontologyofimmanencemoregenerally,isthatitis absurdtoholddisbeliefinGod,becauseItcanjustaswellbecalledNature;anditis ludicroustonotattributemo(ve)mentsofloveorjoytoNature,becauseItmayjust aswellbecalledGod(Ethics,IV,P.4andD).AsSpinozacautionedlongago,itis imperativenottoconfuseimages,words,andideas(Ethics,II,P.49,S.II). In turn, becoming worthy of Spinozist inspiration and living an immanent life require an understanding that there is no hierarchical, vertical rule of power that is not ultimately dependent on the very horizontal forces that permit, construct, and continually uphold its very existence. Relatedly, it is imperative to recognize that identityandmeaning–whetherofspecies,classes,forms,orgenus–arenevermore thanmomentary,constructedfictionssecondarytoemergentspeeds,motions,inten- sities,andcapacities–thatis,whatthingsdoandareabletodo–beforeandbeyond anysupposedlysetnotionsofgroupingsorindividuality. Spinoza(and)theSpider:TheorizingChildhoodasCapacitiesofAffection... 3 Becoming immanent with Spinoza, then, necessitates continual contemplative commitmentandclearconsiderationthatonemustalwaysengagehorizontalmate- rialitiesforanyunderstandingoflife,whilewhollyembracinga“materialismwitha difference,becauseGodorNatureisasmuchanintelligiblesystemofthoughtasa system of material objects” (Curley 1996: xii). Adequately knowing this is to understand that whether we choose to engage life through ontological notions of “God” or “Nature,” such conceptual engagements can never hold any weight of explanatory recourse to transcendental or teleological indulgences, whether of purpose, direction, creation, or meaning; these rejoinders are merely inadequate fictions of the imagination, itself immanently real – insofar that it is continually affectedandhasveryrealbodilyeffects–thoughconfused. The immanence of Spinoza’s philosophy and the impulsion of his materialist inspiration were driven by both a search for perfection (i.e., away from confusion, towardatrueunderstandingofallofnature)andaquestforfreedom(fromsuperstition, from tyranny, from war, in all of their forms), and this parallel journey necessitated livingaparticularkindoflife:onewhich–notmuchdifferentthanhisambivalentand collectiveschizophrenicreceptions–haslongappearedtobe“likealivingoxymoron: hewasanasceticsensualist,aspiritualmaterialist,asociablehermit,asecularsaint” (Stewart2006,p.73).Perhapsitissuchapeculiarandostensiblyoxymoroniclifethat hasallowed“Spinoza[tobe]claimedformanyafold:JewishandChristian,pantheist and atheist, rationalist and mystic, realist and nominalist, analyst and continental, historicist and ahistorical metaphysician, ecologist, and, yes, Buddhist” (Goodman 2002,p.20).Throughwhateverenlightenedormisguidedsensibilitiesheandhislife havebeencharacterizedorhisimmanentthoughtreceivedintheannalsofthehistories ofreligion,philosophy,andpolitics,Spinoza’sinfluenceandlessonstoandformultiple andheterogeneousstrainsofcriticalthoughtaretodayundeniable(seeNorris1991). InspiredbySpinoza’simmanentontology,thischapterplayfullyexploresthreadsof hiscriticalinsightsandinfluencethroughthetropeofthespidertotheorizechildhoodas capacities of affection and affect. In this, Spinoza is approached as both a complex weaverandanintricatetraverserofawebofimmanence,andparticularattentionispaid to his characterization of the embodied imagination and its relationship to different forms of knowing and understanding. Spinoza’s ontological system of immanence in general–andhisunderstandingoftheembodiedimaginationinparticular–provides promisingmetaphysicalthreadsuponwhichtostepawayfromnotionsofchildhoodor childrenasage-dependentrepresentationsorstageswithinidentificationalschemesof linear development to, instead, approach and understand them as immanent bodily capacities.Theimportofthismoveandtheuniversalimplicationsitholdsfornotionsof politicalagency(ofchildrenorotherwise)isalsodiscussed. 2 Spinoza (and) the Spider In his exhaustive, in-depth study of Spinoza’s lineage and legacy, Wolfson (1969, pp. 331–332) explains Spinoza’s originality and the immanence of his thought thusly: “It was Spinoza who first dared to cross [the] boundaries [of God and the 4 G.H.Curti laws of nature], and by the skillful use of weapons accumulated in the arsenals of philosophy itself he succeeded in bringing both God and man under the universal ruleofnatureandthusestablishingunity.”NegrirecognizesinSpinoza’simmanent boundarytransgressionanevenmorecriticalandsubversiveoriginality: Inthehistoryofontologyandtheideaofbeingingeneral,Spinoza’spositionisunique.The theistandpantheistvisionsofbeingdissolveinthefaceofhisdeclarationofthemateriality of being. Spinoza’s thought is characterized by a continuity between physics and ethics, between phenomenology and genealogy, between ethics and politics: the indissoluble continuityofmanifestationsofbeing,thiscircularityofsurfaces,vigorouslyandirreducibly opposesSpinoza’ssystemtoeveryprecedingand(inlargepart)everysuccessiveversionof ontology(Negri2004,p.95). Paralleling these understandings of the immanent power and importance of Spinoza’s thought, Zweig (1939, p. 44) offers perhaps the simplest, most precise, and–forourplayfulpurposeshere–mosthelpfuldescriptionofSpinoza’ssystem- atic philosophy and the expansive promise it offers: “In the end the system of Spinoza may be paraphrased as follows – one of the most sparkling filigree webs inwhichoururgeforinsighthasevertriedtoencompasstheworld.” Zweig’srelianceonthelanguageof“filigreewebs”todescribeSpinoza’sproject is as much artful poetry as (possibly unintentional) epistemological allegory and ontological clarity. Spinoza’s biographer, Colerus (Pollock and Colerus 1899, p. 395), related that at times, when absorbed by fits of intellectual exhaustion or strain,Spinoza“look’dforsomeSpiders,andmade‘emfighttogether,orhethrew some Flies into the Cobweb, and was so pleased with that Battel, that he wou’d sometimesbreakintoLaughter.”Whilesuchmanipulationofanddisregardfor–and apparentderivationofpleasurefromtheviolenceof–animallifemaydisturbsome, asDeleuze(1988),DeleuzeandGuattari(1994),Sharp(2011),andBerman(1982) all underscore, in several ways these actions and activities all fit within Spinoza’s approachtoandunderstandingoftheuniverse.AsSpinozahimselfexplains: [I]t is clear that the law against killing animals is based more on empty superstition and unmanly compassion than sound reason...Not that I deny that the lower animals have sensations.ButIdodenythatwearethereforenotpermittedtoconsiderourownadvantage, usethematourpleasure,andtreatthemasismostconvenientforus.Fortheydonotagreein naturewithus,andtheiraffectsaredifferentinnaturefromhumanaffects(Spinoza,Ethics, IV,P.37,S.1). UnderstandingSpinoza’spropositionthatdifferentanimalshavedifferentaffects, eachcapacitationallydifferentthananother,isacrucialfirststeptowardunderstand- ingthediscussionofchildhoodandchildrenbeingpresentedherein. A pause at this juncture, however, may be helpful. It can be anticipated that perhaps a somewhat quizzical moment may have arisen: why waste time with superfluous discussion of this “Spinoza (and) the spider” nonsense when the wholepointhereistodiscussandtheorizechildhoodascapacitiesofaffectionand affect? For two inter-related reasons: First, because within the development and expression ofSpinoza’ssystematic (and, asNegri has argued,exceedingly unique) Spinoza(and)theSpider:TheorizingChildhoodasCapacitiesofAffection... 5 immanentphilosophy,childrenfindverylittleexplicitmentionortheorization(what mentionthereiswillsoonbediscussed).Second,andrelatedly,tofullyfleshoutand better understand the importance and implications of approaching childhood as capacities of affection and affect, a Spinozist encounter is necessary, but to reach itsfullpotentialforinsightitmustbeonethatplayfullyengagessomeofSpinoza’s interlocutorsastheysimultaneouslyconfrontquestionsofchildhoodwhiletravers- ingandweavingfilialthreadsincommunionwithSpinozaofanontologicalwebof immanence. To explain it another way, Spinoza’s fascination with spiders provides a doubly creative mo(ve)ment that can serve as a helpful and, indeed, enhanced safety line upon which to simultaneously traverse, approach, and better theorize childhood in the ways attempted here. By engaging Spinoza and the spider, we can begin to unpack elements of his philosophy as it relates to childhood/children as part of an immanent reproduction of “relationships of modes in the system of the Ethics as higherethology”(DeleuzeandGuattari1994,p.73),andbyapproachingSpinozaas aspider–or,toputitinawaymorefittingofSpinoza’simmanentontology,ofwhat affections and affects a spider is capable, or by what it is a spider does – we can productivelyexpandonhissystemastheproductionofanontologicalfiligreeweb searchingforfreedomandperfectionthatbothtraversesandweaveslinesofJewish thought– along with, for example, Walter Benjamin – and hasjoyfully ensnared a multitude of philosophers in its sticky “vertigo of immanence” – particularly such thinkersasNegriandDeleuze. 3 Of Children, Fools, and Madmen... Generallyreflectingthespiritofthetime,whatSpinozahadtosayaboutchildrenin bothhiscorrespondencelettersandformalphilosophicalworks,includinghismost famous Ethics, largely subsumes them to passivity as either malleable objects of learningandeducationorequatesthemtothepassiveimpulsivenessandsillinessof suicidevictims,chatterboxes,fools,andmadmen(Ethics,II,P.49,S.III.B;III,P.2, S.). In his clearest and most precise description of children, Spinoza (Ethics, III, P.32,S.)states: Forwefindfromexperiencethatchildren,becausetheirbodiesarecontinually,asitwere,in astateofequilibrium,laughorcrysimplybecausetheyseeotherslaughorcry.Moreover, whatevertheyseeothersdo,theyimmediatelydesiretoimitateit.Andfinally,theydesirefor themselvesallthosethingsbywhichtheyimagineothersarepleased–because,aswehave said,theimagesofthingsaretheveryaffectionsofthehumanbody,ormodesbywhichthe humanbodyisaffectedbyexternalcauses,anddisposedtodothisorthat. Bycouplingthisbrief(andrathercondescendinganddismissive)characterization of children and childhood with epistemological and ontological considerations of Spinoza(and)thespider,wecanbegintolocatetheimmanent“essence,”asitwere, ofSpinoza’smetaphysicsand,inturn,engagehisfellowtravelersonandweaversof 6 G.H.Curti an ontological web of immanence to help theorize childhood as capacities of affectionandaffect. Before we begin to intensively traverse the immanent threads of this web, however, it is important for a brief moment to highlight Spinoza’s (re)call to experience in his efforts to describe children. In the same passage where he capacitationally equates children with suicide victims, fools, and madmen, he makes clear – from both his experience and in his philosophical system (we must presume)–thathedoesnottrulyknowwhattomakeofthem:“I...donotknowhow highly we should esteem one who hangs himself, or children, fools, and madmen, and so on.” While this passage may quickly be dismissed as simply a rhetorical device,itechoessimilarsentimentsSpinoza(Ethics,III,P.2,S.)offersaboutbodies in general: “no one has yet determined what the [human] body can do...” and “...the body itself, simply from the laws of its own nature, can do many things whichitsmindwondersat.” In this latter statement, Spinoza is specifically speaking of somnambulists and makes reference to “the lower animals” (remember his experiments with spider battlesandspider-flyfights)toexplainhowbodiesoftenfunctioninwaysbeyond either human control or human understanding. He also calls on experience to recount the story of a Spanish poet who recovered from a devastating illness, explaining that, despite his apparent convalescence, the poet “was left oblivious tohispastlifethathedidnotbelievethetalesandtragedieshehadwrittenwerehis own.Hecouldsurelyhavebeentakenforagrown-upinfant[or,whatsomesources havetranslatedas“child”]ifhehadalsoforgottenhisnativelanguage”(Ethics,IV, P.39,S.). A quite interesting proposition is raised here in this recall to experience: within Spinoza’ssystemofimmanence,isitpossibleforanadultto,quiteliterally,become a child? And, if so, what does this tell us about the relationship of bodies and capacitiesforknowledge–andhowtheyrelatetogethertogiverisetoidentity–in Spinoza’s ontological system? Moreover, if the child/adult dichotomy is malleable basedonbodilycapacitiesandactivities,whatdoesthisimplyforchildhoodasboth anarenaofpoliticaldesireandagency?Tobegintoanswerthesequestions,itwillbe necessarytogivesomeattentiontotheontologyofSpinozaandtheco-constitutional role bodily passions and imagination play in the formation of different forms (orlevels)ofknowingandunderstanding. 4 Deus sive Natura... IndirectresponsetoDescartes’dualisticpositionthatthereexisttwofundamentally different types of substance – mental and physical – Spinoza offered a monistic alternative:thereisbutonlyonesubstance,GodorNature(DeussiveNatura),and theyarethesamething(Ethics,IV,P.4andD.).Importantly,‘or’(sive)heredoesnot refer toeitheraCartesian dualistic other asdistinct orHegelian other asantithesis. Rather,itrefersto‘or’as‘and’–thesamesubstancesimplyviewedandunderstood from an alternative register or perspective. All things in existence (regardless of Spinoza(and)theSpider:TheorizingChildhoodasCapacitiesofAffection... 7 identityorform)are“modes”ofGodorNature,or“theaffectionsofasubstance,or thatwhichisinanotherthroughwhichitisalsoconceived”(Ethics,I,D5).Spinoza explains: [W]e have conceived an individual which is composed only of bodies which are distin- guishedfrom oneanother onlybymotionandrest,speedandslowness, thatis,whichis composedofthesimplestbodies.Butifweshouldnowconceiveanother,composedofa numberofindividualsofadifferentnature,weshallfindthatitcanbeaffectedinagreat manyotherways,andstillpersevereitsnature.Forsinceeachpartofitiscomposedofa numberofbodies,eachpartwilltherefore...beable,withoutanychangeofitsnature,to movenowmoreslowly,nowmorequickly,andconsequentlycommunicateitsmotionmore quicklyormoreslowlytotheothers. But if we should further conceive a third kind of individual, composed [of many individuals]ofthissecondkind,weshallfindthatitcanbeaffectedinmanyotherways, withoutanychangeofitsform.Andifweproceedinthiswaytoinfinity,weshalleasily conceivethatthewholeofnatureisoneindividual,whoseparts,thatis,allbodies,varyin infiniteways,withoutanychangeofthewholeindividual(Ethics,II,L7,S.). InSpinoza’ssystem,humans,spiders,webs,andflies–asafewexamples–can each be understood as individual modes, or bodies, with their own conatus, or the strivingandendeavoring“toperseverein...being”(Spinoza,Ethics,III,P.6)present withinalllife.Aspart(s)ofthesinglesubstanceofGodorNature(i.e.,thedynamic butinfiniteindividual),eachmodenecessarilyaffectsandisaffectedbyoneanother in a nonhierarchical extensional relationship of dynamic speeds, forces, and flows. Nidditch(1964,p.191)explains: ForSpinoza,eachobject[orbody,ormode]thatappearsasanindividualintheworld–beit aman,ahouse,astone,orastar–isaffiliatedtoothersandbothaffectsandisaffectedbythe characteristicsofothers.Noneoftheseobjectscanleadanindependentexistence;intheir originstheyhavenotcomefromaprocessofself-creationbuthavebeengeneratedbyother objects,andthemanneroftheircontinuanceasobjectsispervasivelyconditionedextrinsi- callyaswellasintrinsically. Within this metaphysics of inter-related variation and forces of different modes andthealwaysdynamicyetunchangingsinglesubstanceofGodorNature,thereisa vital point that must be highlighted related to Spinoza’s experiments with and perspectives on animals presented above that has important implications for how childrenandchildhoodare–or,moreprecisely,canbe–characterizedinhissystem ofimmanence.Sharp(2011,pp.52–53)notesthat: Onacasualreading,[Spinoza]seemstoclaimthathumannatureissimplydifferentinkind frombestialnatureandthuswedonotregardourselvestobeboundtothem.Ouraffects, natures,andvitalinterestsdiffer,andthuswehavenomoralorprudentialreasonstopreserve and enhance the lives of animals. Unlike Descartes and the idealist tradition that he inaugurates,however,thislackofimperativetocareforanimalsdoesnotfollowfroman absolutedivisionbetweenhumansandanimals.ForSpinoza,thereisnounbridgeablechasm between the conscious animal and the unconscious thing. Descartes, Kant, and Hegel frequentlyappeal to theinfinite difference between humansand “things,”acategorythat includes nonhuman animals, by virtue of an exclusive mental power to think, will, and 8 G.H.Curti represent our sensations. Yet, for Spinoza, there are only differences of degree between humans,animals,machines,androcks. Withthisconsiderationinmind,what,then,makeshumansuniqueinSpinoza’s system?Indeed,thisisavitalquestionifwearetounderstandwhatqualities,ifany, distinguish an adult from a child. We can glean from the internal logic of his ontological system of immanence that, from at least one standpoint, the answer to both questions must certainly be: nothing at all. Even considering degrees of differencebetween humans andnonhumans,Spinoza states though “human bodies agree in many things, they still differ in very many” (Ethics, I, Appdx. III), and “[e]ach affect of each individual differs from the affect of another as much as the essence ofthe one from theessence of theother” (Ethics, III, P. 57). Moreover, he explains that “[d]ifferent [singularities] can be affected differently by one and the same object; and one and the same [singularity] can be affected differently at different times by one and the same object” (Ethics, III, P. 51). In the context of thesepropositions,anyuniversalizeddichotomybetweenhuman/nonhumanand,by logical extension, child and childhood/adult and adulthood, appears to be concep- tuallynonsensical,aseachmode–consideredfromthestandpointofsingularities– can have as many similarities or differences with another mode in any given place andatanygiventimeregardlessofanyrepresentationalgroupingoridentificational schemebasedongenus,species,age,orotherwise. Sharp(2011,p.62),however,highlightsavitalpointthatisnecessarytoconsider here: Spinoza’sphilosophicalnaturalismseekstoportraysingularbeings,especially“men,”ashe saysmanytimes,astheyare,andnotaswewouldlikethemtobe.Butwecannotavoid erectingexemplars,ormodels,thatgiveshapetoourprojectedfuturesandthelifewehope tobuild.Spinoza’ssuspiciontowarduniversalcategorieslikespeciesnotwithstanding,he maintainstheneedforprovisionalboundariestoourideaof“humanity.” Thus,asSharpsuggests,itisnecessaryforSpinozatoprovideconceptualspace for provisional boundaries and categorizations built through abstractions and even fictions, if for no other reason than to be able to productively work toward a capacitationally enriching future and (human) collective perseverance in being. Such abstractions and fictions of unification – or entia rationis – are vital for understandingandgraspingelementsoftheapparentchaosoftheinfinitesubstance GodorNature,butonlyifwedonotconfusetheirfictions[ficta]fortruths: Entia rationis are class concepts, formed by the intellect in order to bring actual things togetherforcomparisonoftheirsimilaritiesanddifferences.Examplesofentiarationisare genus,species,time,andmathematicalconcepts–figure,number,andmeasure.Weneedbe innofearofformingsuchconstructions,providedwefirsthaveatrueandadequateideaof thefirstprinciplesofscience.Theintellectmaythenfreelyandknowinglyconstructfictional entities and abstractions as aids, tools, or instruments to push its investigations further (Savan1986,p.120). Spinoza(and)theSpider:TheorizingChildhoodasCapacitiesofAffection... 9 Is the child/adult distinction simply this: a particular class of entia rationis, a fictional aid, tool, or instrument providing conceptual material to help analyze pathways and trajectories to freedom and perfection through better understanding of the infinite substance of God or Nature for Spinoza? Certainly, if measures, groupings,categories,andotheridentificationalschemessuchasgenusandspecies are fictional constructions, so, too, must be any arbitrary classificatory or identifi- cationalschemealongagelines.Whilethismay,indeed,beshowntobethecase,itis notsoinsuchasimple,straightforwardmanner. Thereisanother,universalboundarythroughwhichhumanscanbecharacterized in Spinoza’s system that he did not deem provisional and which is not based on fictions or abstractions: the ability to adequately perceive (only) two of an infinite array of attributes, or affections, of God or Nature. It is how these two attributes function in “parallel” and how they co-exist and inform Spinoza’s system of knowledge that provide him with the internal logic necessary for conceptually and metaphysically making (implicit) distinctions between human and nonhuman and adult and child, distinctions that offer a playful opportunity to engage some of his interlocutorsandfellowtravelersonawebofimmanencetohelpusmoveawayfrom notionsofchildrenorchildhoodasage-dependentrepresentations. 5 We Will Say that It Imagines... (or, The Passion [of] Bodily Thought) Using the logic ofDescartes’ dualism againstitself, Spinoza reasoned that thought (mind)andextension(body)arenottwosubstancesbuttwodistinctattributesofthe oneinfinitesubstanceofGodorNature.Becausetheyaredistinctattributes,thought andextensioncannotbethecauseoreffectofoneanother;“abodyisnotlimitedby thoughtnorathoughtbyabody”(Ethics,I,D2;seealsoIII,P.2andDem.).Instead, bothexistsimultaneously,inparallel,astwoperspectivesofthesamephenomenon orevent;“theorderofactionsandpassionsofourbodyis,bynature,atonewiththe orderofactionsandpassionsofthemind”(Ethics,III,P2,S.).Deleuze(1988,p.18) explainsinmoredetail: [O]neofthemostfamoustheoreticalthesesofSpinozaisknownbythenameofparallelism; itdoesnotconsistmerelyindenyinganyrealcausalitybetweenthemindandthebody,it disallowsanyprimacyoftheoneovertheother.IfSpinozarejectsanysuperiorityofthe mindoverthebody,thisisnotinordertoestablishasuperiorityofthebodyoverthemind, which would be no more intelligible than the converse. The practical significance of parallelismismanifestedinthereversalofthetraditionalprincipleonwhichMoralitywas foundedasanenterpriseofdominationofthepassionsbyconsciousness.Itwassaidthat whenthebodyacted,themindwasactedupon,andtheminddidnotactwithoutthebody beingacteduponinturn...AccordingtotheEthics,onthecontrary,whatisanactioninthe mind is necessarily an action in the body as well, and what is a passion in the body is necessarilyapassioninthemind.Thereisnoprimacyofoneseriesovertheother. 10 G.H.Curti Thus,thoughphenomenamayregisterdifferentlyforhumansinmind(thought) and body (extension), these different registering effectsare just two expressions of thesamething:“Theobjectoftheideaconstitutingthehumanmindisthebody,ora certainmodeofextensionwhichactuallyexists,andnothingelse”(Spinoza,Ethics, II,P.13).Becausebodyandmindarethesamethingsimplyinadifferentregisteror fromadifferentperspective,thinking always parallels acorrespondingtransforma- tionin,of,andthroughthebody,andactionsandmaterialeffectsonandofthebody necessarily are paralleled by thought and ideas in the mind – each interaction informed through the body as affection and affect. Like the spider, Spinoza works throughthecapacitiesofthebodytomeasure,weave,andtraversethefiligreeweb: “theaffectionsofthehumanbodywhoseideaspresentexternalbodiesaspresentto us,weshallcallimagesofthings,thoughtheydonotreproducetheexternalfigures of things. And when the mind regards bodies in this way, we shall say that it imagines” (Spinoza, Ethics, II, P. 17, S.), and “[t]he human mind does not know the human body itself, nor does it know that it exists, except through ideas of affectionsbywhichthebodyisaffected”(Spinoza,Ethics,II,P.19). Here, there is an important distinction to make between affection (affectio) and affect(affectus)inSpinoza’ssystem.Hedefines“affect”as“affectionsofthebody bywhichthebody’spowerofactingisincreasedordiminished,aidedorrestrained, andatthesametime,theideasoftheseaffections”(Ethics,III,D3).Affection,then, is the immediate impression of one body upon another, while an affect is that impressiontakenupbyaparticularbodyasachangingstateinactivityandthought (e.g.,fromjoytosadness,orfromsadnesstomoresadness,orfromjoytomorejoy, etc.). But Spinoza also states that it is through the ideas of affection (that is, the impression between different modes, or bodies, and their register in the mind) that we,ashumans–asrationalanimals–(areableto)developmoreadvancedformsof knowledge. In other words, this understanding of affection and affect has a direct roleinhowwebothrelatetoand(can)understandandknowtheworld.Presenting an example comparing a (“rational”) human animal and a(n) (“irrational”) horse animal,Spinoza(Ethics,III,P.57,S.)explains: [T]heaffectsoftheanimalswhicharecalledirrational(forafterweknowtheoriginofthe mind, we cannot in any way doubt that the lower animals feel things) differfrom men’s affectsasmuchastheirnaturediffersfromhumannature.Boththehorseandthemanare drivenbylusttoprocreate,buttheoneisdrivenbyanequinelust,theotherbyahumanlust. Soalsothelustsandappetitesofinsects,fish,andbirdsmustvary.Therefore,thougheach individuallivescontentwithhisownnature,bywhichheisconstituted,andisgladofit, neverthelessthatlifewithwhicheachoneiscontent,andthatgladness,arenothingbutthe idea,orsoul,oftheindividual.Andsothegladnessoftheonediffersinnaturefromthe gladnessoftheotherasmuchastheessenceoftheonediffersfromtheessenceoftheother. Finally,...itfollowsthatthereisnosmalldifferencebetweenthegladnessbywhicha drunkisledandthegladnessaphilosopherpossesses. Thiswillbeenoughconcerningtheaffectswhicharerelatedtomaninsofarasheisacted on.... To Spinoza, bodily passion such as lust is both an affection of the body and a mode of thinking (Ethics, II, A3), and thus an idea, but a confused idea; that is, it

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.