History of Mechanism and Machine Science 39 Danilo Capecchi Epistemology and Natural Philosophy in the 18th Century The Roots of Modern Physics History of Mechanism and Machine Science Volume 39 Series Editor Marco Ceccarelli, Department of Industrial Engineering, University of Rome Tor Vergata, Rome, Italy Thisbookseries establishes awell-defined forum for Monographs andProceedings on the History of Mechanism and Machine Science (MMS). The series publishes worksthatgiveanoverviewofthehistoricaldevelopments,fromtheearliesttimes up to and including the recent past, of MMS in all its technical aspects. Thistechnicalapproachisanessentialcharacteristicoftheseries.Bydiscussing technicaldetailsandformulationsandevenreformulatingthoseintermsofmodern formalisms the possibility is created not only to track the historical technical developments but also to use past experiences in technical teaching and research today. In order to do so, the emphasis must be on technical aspects rather than a purely historical focus, although the latter has its place too. Furthermore,theserieswillconsidertherepublicationofout-of-printolderworks with English translation and comments. Thebookseriesisintendedtocollecttechnicalviewsonhistoricaldevelopments of the broad field of MMS in a unique frame that can be seen in its totality as an EncyclopaediaoftheHistoryofMMSbutwiththeadditionalpurposeofarchiving and teaching the History of MMS. Therefore. the book series is intended not only forresearchersoftheHistoryofEngineeringbutalsoforprofessionalsandstudents who are interested in obtaining a clear perspective of the past for their future technicalworks.Thebookswillbewritteningeneralbyengineersbutnotonlyfor engineers.TheseriesispromotedundertheauspicesofInternationalFederationfor the Promotion of Mechanism and Machine Science (IFToMM). Prospective authors and editors can contact Mr. Pierpaolo Riva (publishing editor, Springer) at: [email protected] Indexed by SCOPUS and Google Scholar. More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/7481 Danilo Capecchi Epistemology and Natural Philosophy in the 18th Century The Roots of Modern Physics 123 DaniloCapecchi IngegneriaStrutturale eGeotecnica Sapienza Universitàdi Roma Roma, Italy ISSN 1875-3442 ISSN 1875-3426 (electronic) History of Mechanism andMachineScience ISBN978-3-030-52851-5 ISBN978-3-030-52852-2 (eBook) https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-52852-2 ©SpringerNatureSwitzerlandAG2021 Thisworkissubjecttocopyright.AllrightsarereservedbythePublisher,whetherthewholeorpart of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission orinformationstorageandretrieval,electronicadaptation,computersoftware,orbysimilarordissimilar methodologynowknownorhereafterdeveloped. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publicationdoesnotimply,evenintheabsenceofaspecificstatement,thatsuchnamesareexemptfrom therelevantprotectivelawsandregulationsandthereforefreeforgeneraluse. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, expressed or implied, with respect to the material contained hereinorforanyerrorsoromissionsthatmayhavebeenmade.Thepublisherremainsneutralwithregard tojurisdictionalclaimsinpublishedmapsandinstitutionalaffiliations. ThisSpringerimprintispublishedbytheregisteredcompanySpringerNatureSwitzerlandAG Theregisteredcompanyaddressis:Gewerbestrasse11,6330Cham,Switzerland To my wife Preface At the beginning of the modern era, what is now called science was spread out among various disciplines: theology, handcrafts, magic, alchemy, astrology, med- icine, natural philosophy, and mixed mathematics (that is optics, astronomy, mechanics,music,etc).Inthe18thcentury,thesedisciplineshadalreadybrokenup and became recomposed into an organization of science of the natural world that was similar to the modern one. The most important transformation was that affectingnaturalphilosophy,whichwasconsidered,atleastintheacademicworld, themostnobleandbyfarthemostimportantformofknowledge.Itceasedtobea philosophy in the canonical sense, merging with other forms of knowledge and givingraisetodisciplinessuchasphysics,naturalhistory,chemistry,medicine,and engineering, names which, while not initially fully shared, were established in the 19th century and are still used today. The new philosophers of nature were no longer canonical philosophers, although they continued to think about philosophy. They were rather mathematicians in the broad sense, namely, scholars who were interestedinmorethanjustpuremathematics.Insomecases,thisisparticularlytrue for the new branches of physics such as electricity and magnetism, and they were also simply educated gentlemen, gifted with intelligence and curiosity. Thepresentbookaimstodocumentthisprocessoftransformation,concentrating onthe18thcentury,acenturythatinthepasthadbeenconsidereduninterestingfor the history of science. It would represent the transition from the age of genius and the birth of modern science, in the 17th century, to the age of prodigious devel- opment,inthe19thcentury.Thisviewdoesnotstanduptothoroughanalysis.The 18th century, the century of Enlightenment and reason, as will be clear from the present book, was rather a century of great ferment and novelty. Tomake thenarrativepracticable forasingleindividual,nogreat emphasishas beenplaced ontheprecisegenesisofthevariousconceptsand methods developed inscientificenterprises,exceptwhenthiswasnecessarytomakethemclear.Ihave beencontenttotakesnapshotsofsituationsbytakingalookatdiscreteintervalsof time. In several situations, reference ismade to the authors who are famous today, such asNewton,the Bernoullis, Euler, d’Alembert, Lagrange, Lambert, Volta, etc. Not so much because they were the most creative and original minds, but mainly vii viii Preface because their writings represent a synthesis of contemporary and previous studies. The above names should, therefore, be considered more labels of a period than references to real historical characters. The history of science was not made up of isolatedheroes,butbyanentirecommunityanditslegacy,byteachers,anonymous collaborators of celebrities, playing this role often only as a result of their social status. It is true that in the 18th century scientific research was carried out by a handfulofscholars;thoughsmall,itwasstillanarmy,however,whosegeneralsare onlyrepresentativeofthevictoriescarriedoutbythesoldiers.Referringonlytothe great characters of science has in any case an advantage that there is no need entering the merits of their acquisitions because well documented by historians, thus leaving room for other aspects. This book intends to answer these three fundamental questions: 1. Wasthetransformationofancientnaturalphilosophyinto(modern)sciencedue to an internal evolution or an external appropriation? 2. What was the role of mechanical and experimental philosophies in this transformation? 3. What was the role of the newly born infinitesimal mathematics (Calculus)? The answers come as follows: 1. It was a conquest from the outside by mathematicians (broader sense). They were able to extend the approach of mixed mathematics to the study of most phenomena. 2. Mechanical philosophy was crucial. It aroused interest in natural philosophy in many not canonical philosophers—including mathematicians—because its argumentationsweremuch simplerthanthose offered bycanonicalphilosophy, imbued with metaphysics. A similar argument holds good for experimental philosophy. 3. The role of Calculus was twofold. On the one hand, its great fecundity made it possibletosolveverycomplexproblems,thusgivingmathematicsmoreappeal intheapproachofphilosophyofnature.Asregardstoapplications,ontheother hand,theneedtorefertoregularfunctionsdefinedoncontinuameantthatnature was seen through glasses with thick lenses, which influenced its interpretation. Beforegoingfurther,anomenclatureshouldbeestablishedbecausemanyofthe termsinuseinthepastandstillinusetodayhavechangedtheirmeaning,andthusa stipulation is necessary: (cid:129) Canonical natural philosophy. Study of nature under the concepts of matter, cosmos, and causation. Examples of canonical natural philosophies are the Aristotelean,thePlatonic,themechanicistic;butnotNewton’sandtheapproach to nature after him, even though the term natural philosophy is retained also in such cases. (cid:129) Mixed mathematics. Mathematics related to physical problems—that somehow joinsqualitytoquantity—astheywereestablishedintheearlymodernera,such as astronomy (physical or positional), surveying, fortification, ballistic, Preface ix mechanics, hydrodynamics, pneumatics, and so on. A category quite distinct from that of subalternate sciences of Aristotelian mould that sometimes are considered as the canon of mixed mathematics. (cid:129) Canonical philosophers (or simply philosophers). Scholars that besides natural philosophy considered also and in a systematic way metaphysics and either logic, or ethic, or theology. (cid:129) Mathematical practitioners (or mathematicians broad meaning or more simply mathematicians). People with a more or less important training in theoretical mathematicswhowerealsoinvolvedinpracticalactivities(notethattheideaof pure mathematicians is quite modern; until at least the end of the 18th century more or less all mathematicians were involved in practical activity or at least wroteaboutpracticaluseofmathematics).ThetermMathematicalpractitioners was introduces as a historical category in 1954 by the English geographer and historianofscienceEvaGermaineRimingtonTaylor(1879–1966),butitisused here quite freely. Of course one can envision a spectrum between canonical philosophers and mathematical practitioners. The columns of the following table show the possible main combinations, ranging from canonical philosophers with a very limited interest in mathematics (first column) to skilled artisans who knew little of phi- losophy and mathematics (last columns). H means high involvement and L means low or medium involvement. Philosophy H H L L Mathematics L H H L 16thCentury.ThebirthofGreekrationalityrepresentedafundamentalstepfor the change in the form of the western knowledge of the natural world. But in the 16th century the change was possibly more radical when mathematicians began to widen the fields of classical mixed mathematics—which had flourished in Hellenistic Greece and remained vital in the Middle Ages—certainly pressed by demandsoftechnologyfromarapidlyexpandingsociety,byappropriatingofparts of the canonical natural philosophy. 17thCentury.Theprocessofappropriationbecamemoreevidentasthecentury progressed. Traditional mixed mathematics, optics, astronomy, music, mechanics, flanked by many other disciplines that in previous centuries had been studied only in natural philosophy, such as acoustics, meteorology, and hydrodynamics, were given a new and fundamental acquisition: dynamics (term introduced by Leibniz). Successobtainedinthisfieldbythemathematical(andexperimental)approachdue to the contribution of many scholars, including Galileo, Torricelli, Cavalieri, Huygens, Mariotte, Roberval, Descartes, Borelli, Leibniz, and eventually Newton, hadafundamentalroleintheprocessoferosionoftheoldphilosophyofnatureby (mixed) mathematicians. Because of this success, with the greater interest in experimentationtoclarifyanddiscovernew“facts”,andtheinterestinapplications, naturalphilosophy wasseendifferently than inthepast. Lessattentionwas paidto traditional issues concerning nature, essence, and properties appropriate to all x Preface bodies—the so-called physica generalis—and more attention was paid to the examination and discussion of the particular bodies—the so-called physica par- ticularis. Traditional explanations, both Aristotelian and Cartesian, appeared in some way sterile. Indeed the theories put forward did not have any element of objectivity;thesamephenomenoncouldbeexplainedinonewaybyonescholar,in another way by another, without an agreement being reached. New approaches to the study of nature became so appealing because, despite providing answers in a morerestricted range,they hadsomekindofobjectivityandwereable tolead toa consensus of opinion. Furthermore, together with the explanations, the new approaches also provided for the prediction of phenomena, which had great utili- tarian value, leading to technological applications. Skepticismtowardcanonicalnaturalphilosophyledtothebirthofexperimental philosophy.ItdevelopedindifferentwaysontheContinentandinEngland,sothat itisstipulatedbysomehistoriansthatthelabelexperimentalphilosophybeapplied to English experimentations only, sponsored by the Royal society. The way of relatingtoexperimentationisattributedbythesehistorianstotheconceptionofthe roleofthedemiurgeandmagicintheCreationand,therefore,inwhatiscalledthe ordinary course of nature. In England, more freedom would have been granted to the demiurge than on the Continent, and this would have given greater freedom to theEnglish,whowerenotobligedtosubsumeexperimentsundergeneralnecessary laws. As a result, English scholars would have developed a science that favored phenomenological aspects while continental academics would have paid more attention to causation. 18th Century. The appropriation of natural philosophy by mathematicians became substantially complete. This process was aided by the spreading of Calculus, which made it possible to address many of yet unsolved problems. The receivedviewpointconsidersthechangeintheapproachtophilosophyofnatureto be largely a consequence of the technical results Newton achieved in the Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica and Opticks and his empirical view. Since the 19th century, Newton has generally been seen as the founder of modern science,inparticularofclassical mechanics,intheformithastoday. Thispointof view was also prevalent among modern science historians, at least until the mid-20th century. The assessment of Newton by contemporaries was more bal- anced. He was recognized as a great mathematician; his results in astronomy were consideredextraordinary,butfewsawhimasabringerofrevolutionaryresults,not even in the fundaments of mechanics. In fact, he was considered just one of the many. Before him, Huygens, Wallis, and Hooke had obtained results of no less importance than his. Modern historiography introduces great variations in the received point of view, giving to Newton only what is Newton’s. In mechanics, the old mixed mathematics of Hellenistic origin, together with statics and Galilean dynamics, changed into a theory that had the same ambitions ofthecanonicalnaturalphilosophy,namely,togiveaglobalresponsetothenature of motion based, however, only on a mathematical approach. The Bernoullis, Varignon, Euler, and a few others, explicitly introduced algebra and differential calculus, operating a non-trivial transformation that invested the very role of