ebook img

Epistemology after Protagoras: Responses to Relativism in Plato, Aristotle, and Democritus PDF

351 Pages·2005·2.49 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Epistemology after Protagoras: Responses to Relativism in Plato, Aristotle, and Democritus

Title Pages University Press Scholarship Online Oxford Scholarship Online Epistemology after Protagoras: Responses to Relativism in Plato, Aristotle, and Democritus Mi-Kyoung Lee Print publication date: 2005 Print ISBN-13: 9780199262229 Published to Oxford Scholarship Online: October 2005 DOI: 10.1093/0199262225.001.0001 Title Pages Epistemology after Protagoras Epistemology after Protagoras CLARENDON PRESS • OXFORD (p.iv) Great Clarendon Street, Oxford OX2 6DP Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide in Oxford New York Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto With offices in Page 1 of 3 Title Pages Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan South Korea Poland Portugal Singapore Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries Published in the United States by Oxford University Press Inc., New York © Mi‐Kyoung Lee, 2005 The moral rights of the author have been asserted Database right Oxford University Press (maker) First published 2005 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover And you must impose this same condition on any acquirer ISBN 978-0-19-926222-9 Dedication University Press Scholarship Online Oxford Scholarship Online Epistemology after Protagoras: Responses to Relativism in Plato, Aristotle, and Democritus Mi-Kyoung Lee Print publication date: 2005 Print ISBN-13: 9780199262229 Published to Oxford Scholarship Online: October 2005 DOI: 10.1093/0199262225.001.0001 Dedication (p.v) For PETER (p.vi) Preface and Acknowledgements University Press Scholarship Online Oxford Scholarship Online Epistemology after Protagoras: Responses to Relativism in Plato, Aristotle, and Democritus Mi-Kyoung Lee Print publication date: 2005 Print ISBN-13: 9780199262229 Published to Oxford Scholarship Online: October 2005 DOI: 10.1093/0199262225.001.0001 (p.vii) Preface and Acknowledgements This book was originally inspired by a question: did philosophical scepticism arise de novo in the Hellenistic period with the Academics and the Pyrrhonists, as is commonly thought, or could elements of scepticism be found earlier in the classical period? Were Plato and Aristotle simply unaware (or dismissive) of scepticism as a serious challenge to their own more optimistic views of the possibility of acquiring knowledge? I found that Protagoras' arguments, as presented and developed in Plato's Theaetetus, and Aristotle's related discussion of Protagoras in Metaphysics Γ, anticipate in striking ways some of the attacks which Hellenistic sceptics used. Furthermore, Plato's and Aristotle's cases against Protagoras constitute a powerful defence against the sorts of arguments that the Hellenistic sceptics would eventually deploy. My goal in this book, therefore, has been to explore and arrive at a better understanding of the impact of Protagoras' relativist arguments, together with Plato's, Aristotle's, and Democritus' responses to those arguments, on the development of classical Greek epistemology. Much of the material for this book grew out of work I did in graduate seminars given by Gisela Striker, who also taught me as an undergraduate at Columbia University and supervised my Ph.D. dissertation at Harvard University. In addition, her published work on Hellenistic scepticism and on the sophists inspired many of the leading questions and Page 1 of 3 Preface and Acknowledgements ideas in this book. It is through countless discussions, and many invaluable criticisms and suggestions, that she helped me shape this material into a book. I could not have hoped for a better teacher and adviser. I am also grateful to the following people for their generous and helpful comments on drafts of various chapters: Chloe Balla, Patricia Curd, Gail Fine, W. D. Hart, Rachana Kamtekar, Kathrin Koslicki, Connie Meinwald, Dana Miller, Stephen Menn, Susan Sauvé Meyer, Lije Millgram, Ian Mueller, Hilary Putnam, David Sedley, and Angela Smith. Although I sometimes end up disagreeing with him, I—and all scholars—am greatly indebted to Myles Burnyeat for his work on the Theaetetus. I have also benefited from conversations with him and his seminar on the De Anima at Harvard in the autumn of 1991. I thank Pat Curd for showing me part of her forthcoming commentary on Anaxagoras. I also thank Jørgen Mejer for helpful discussions of Democritus and Diogenes Laertius. Three anonymous readers for Oxford University Press carefully read and commented on successive drafts of this book; their meticulous comments and tough criticisms helped me enormously to get this book into shape. I would (p.viii) like to thank my editor, Peter Momtchiloff, for his advice and encouragement, Jacqueline Baker and Rebecca Bryant of OUP, and my copy‐editor, Nigel Hope, for all their help with the book. I also thank Itır Günes̜ for help with the proofs. None of these people should be blamed for the errors and lapses of judgement which still remain. I thank the Senior Fellows of the Center for Hellenic Studies in Washington DC and its former directors, Deborah Boedeker and Kurt Raaflaub, for giving me the opportunity to work on this book in the splendid library and environment of the Center for a year. I also acknowledge the support of the National Endowment for the Humanities Summer Stipend for the writing of this book. My colleagues at the Department of Philosophy at the University of Illinois at Chicago, especially Connie Meinwald and Bill Hart, have been incredibly supportive, both by reading my work and by shielding me from the more time‐ consuming duties in the department. I am grateful to my parents, Hye‐Sook and Joon Chang Lee, and to my sister, Sue Lee, for their unwavering support throughout all the years I have worked on this project. And finally, for all of his advice, comments on drafts, and encouragement, I thank my husband Peter Hunt, to whom I dedicate this book. Chapter 3 is a revised and expanded version of ‘The Secret Doctrine: Plato's Defense of Protagoras in the Theaetetus’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy (ed. David Sedley), 19 (Winter 2000), 47–86. Reprinted, with revisions, by permission of Oxford University Press. Chapter 5 is a revised and expanded version of ‘Thinking and Perception in Plato's Theaetetus’, in Mark McPherran (ed.), Recognition, Remembrance, and Reality: New Essays on Plato's Epistemology and Metaphysics, Apeiron 32/4 (Dec. 1999), 37–54. Reprinted, with revisions, by permission of Academic Publishing and Printing. Page 2 of 3 List Of Abbreviations University Press Scholarship Online Oxford Scholarship Online Epistemology after Protagoras: Responses to Relativism in Plato, Aristotle, and Democritus Mi-Kyoung Lee Print publication date: 2005 Print ISBN-13: 9780199262229 Published to Oxford Scholarship Online: October 2005 DOI: 10.1093/0199262225.001.0001 (p.xi) List Of Abbreviations A Testimonium in Diels–Kranz B Fragment in Diels–Kranz DA Aristotle, De Anima DK Diels–Kranz, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker DL Diogenes Laertius, Lives of the Philosophers DS Theophrastus, De Sensibus EN Aristotle, Ethica Nicomachea GC Aristotle, De Generatione et Corruptione KRS Page 1 of 3 List Of Abbreviations Kirk, Raven, and Schofield LS Long and Sedley, The Hellenistic philosophers M Sextus Empiricus, Against the Professors [Adversus Mathematicos] Met. Aristotle, Metaphysics OT Aristotle, Oxford Translation, ed. W. D. Ross PH Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism [Pyrrhoneae hypotyposes] Prot. Plato, Protagoras Rep. Plato, Republic ROT Aristotle, Revised Oxford Translation, ed. Jonathan Barnes SE Sextus Empiricus Soph. Plato, Sophist Tht. Plato, Theaetetus T Fragments and Testimonia in Taylor 1999a Unless otherwise indicated, translations of Plato's Theaetetus come from the Levett/ Burnyeat translation (Hackett, 1990), except in §§5.4–8, where J. McDowell's translation (Oxford, 1973) has been used. For passages from the other Platonic dialogues, the translations in Plato: Complete Works, ed. J. M. Cooper (Hackett, 1997) have been used. For Aristotle's Metaphysics, Ross' 1928 Oxford translation of the Metaphysics has been used. For the Democritean fragments and testimonia I have used C. C. W. Taylor's translation (Toronto, 1999). (p.xii) Introduction University Press Scholarship Online Oxford Scholarship Online Epistemology after Protagoras: Responses to Relativism in Plato, Aristotle, and Democritus Mi-Kyoung Lee Print publication date: 2005 Print ISBN-13: 9780199262229 Published to Oxford Scholarship Online: October 2005 DOI: 10.1093/0199262225.001.0001 Introduction Mi-Kyoung Lee (Contributor Webpage) DOI:10.1093/0199262225.003.0001 Abstract and Keywords This book starts from the question: did skepticism only arise in the Hellenistic era? It is argued that skepticism was in the air even earlier in the classical period — not in the form of a well-defined school of thought or position, but in the form of certain loosely-related ideas and arguments. Some of these were articulated by Protagoras in his book Alêtheia ‘Truth’, which began with the striking claim that ‘Man is the measure of all things, of what is that it is, of what is not that it is not.’ Protagoras’ claim posed a challenge to the ideals of expert knowledge, truth, and to the privileged role of reason in discovering the truth. Plato, Aristotle, and Democritus responded to this challenge in their work. Keywords: skepticism, truth, measure, expert knowledge, reason In the Hellenistic period of Greek philosophy, the lines between philosophical camps on the question of whether and how knowledge can be acquired are clearly drawn. We find Page 1 of 8 Introduction self‐proclaimed sceptics, such as the Academics and Pyrrhonists, posing a forceful challenge to their ‘dogmatic’ opponents, compelling them to justify their confidence in the very possibility of knowledge. Their opponents counter this in turn by formulating their theories of knowledge as proposals concerning a criterion of truth, that is, a self‐evident, infallible measure of the truth that can be used to distinguish with certainty between true and false assertions and thus secure the foundations of knowledge. However, before the Hellenistic era, worries about whether knowledge is really possible seem curiously absent. Certainly expressions of the difficulty of attaining knowledge go back to the earliest Greek thinkers. And in the classical period, Plato addresses the question of what knowledge must be like and how one should go about looking for it in his principal epistemological doctrines, such as his theory of recollection, and in his educational programme predicated on the existence of Forms as the proper object of knowledge. He thinks that acquiring knowledge is extremely difficult, and that most people do not have real knowledge; Socrates in the Republic denies that he has any such knowledge himself. But Plato, like his predecessors, seems to assume that it is possible, at least in principle, to acquire knowledge and discover the truth. This then raises the question: did scepticism only first arise in the Hellenistic period? Or was it already around, in the air, in the classical period? Were Plato, Aristotle, and other philosophers of the classical period simply unaware of scepticism as a problem, confident that philosophical knowledge can be reached, though no doubt with difficulty? Or did they recognize and grapple with some of the ideas and arguments that would later be marshalled for the sceptical position? The aim of this book is to describe and investigate the development of epistemology in the classical period of ancient Greece, focusing on the figures of Protagoras, Plato, Aristotle, and Democritus. My thesis is that scepticism was in the air—not in the form of a well‐ defined school of thought or position, but in the form of certain loosely related ideas and arguments. Some of these were articulated by Protagoras in his book Alētheia (‘Truth’), which began with the striking claim that ‘Man is the measure of all things, of what is that it is, (p.2) of what is not that it is not.’ One might wonder whether this is really ‘sceptical’, since it implies that knowledge is much easier to attain than one might have thought: we are all ‘measures’, that is, knowers of what is true and what is false.1 But in fact the measure doctrine—Protagoras' claim that things are for each as they appear to each— poses a challenge to the concept of expert knowledge and understanding, for it implies that no one can ever be wrong about anything. It poses a challenge to the concept of truth as the deeper reality behind appearances, for it implies that there is no such deeper reality to discover and explain. And it poses a challenge to the idea that reason alone has privileged access to the truth, for it implies that, in virtue of the sensory faculties and ordinary capacity for judgement that we all possess, we are each of us equally sufficient ‘measures’ of what is true and what is false. It is not surprising, then, that many of the arguments Protagoras used in support of the measure doctrine—his argument from conflicting appearances, his argument that there are no authoritative grounds for deciding that one belief is true rather than another, his particular focus on conflicts and relativity in perceptual and value judgements—later resurface in the sceptical repertoire. Page 2 of 8

Description:
Relativism, the position that things are for each as they seem to each, was first formulated in Western philosophy by Protagoras, the 5th century BC Greek orator and teacher. Mi-Kyoung Lee focuses on the challenge to the possibility of expert knowledge posed by Protagoras, together with responses by
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.