Title Pages Epicurean Ethics in Horace: The Psychology of Satire Sergio Yona Print publication date: 2018 Print ISBN-13: 9780198786559 Published to Oxford Scholarship Online: March 2018 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198786559.001.0001 Title Pages Sergio Yona (p.i) Epicurean Ethics in Horace (p.ii) (p.iii) Epicurean Ethics in Horace (p.iv) Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © Sergio Yona 2018 The moral rights of the author have been asserted First Edition published in 2018 Impression: 1 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in Page 1 of 2 Title Pages a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: 2017944153 ISBN 978–0–19–878655–9 Printed and bound by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon, CR0 4YY Page 2 of 2 Acknowledgements Epicurean Ethics in Horace: The Psychology of Satire Sergio Yona Print publication date: 2018 Print ISBN-13: 9780198786559 Published to Oxford Scholarship Online: March 2018 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198786559.001.0001 (p.v) Acknowledgements Sergio Yona This book, which is an expanded and revised version of my Ph.D. dissertation (University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign 2014), would not have been possible without the help and generosity of a number of scholars and friends. First and foremost I owe many thanks to my committee members Ariana Traill, Kirk Sanders, and Kirk Freudenburg, who were a constant source of support throughout the writing process and whose guidance is greatly appreciated. I owe special thanks to my dissertation director, mentor, and friend Antony Augoustakis, whose patience and advice over the years has made all the difference. To David Armstrong, whose generosity, insight, and support every step of the way have contributed enormously to the improvement of the project, I am profoundly grateful. I also wish to thank Elizabeth Asmis, who was kind enough to look at a portion of the manuscript. My interest in Horace began at Queen’s University at Kingston, where I had the great pleasure of learning from the late Professor Ross S. Kilpatrick. To him I will always be thankful, not only for having introduced me to the joys of Horace (as well as Lucretius) but also for his genuine interest in my progress and kind support early on. I also wish to thank the editorial staff at Oxford University Press, Charlotte Loveridge, Catherine Owen, and Georgina Leighton, whose assistance has made the publication process a truly pleasant one. Many thanks are also due to the Press readers, whose feedback and recommendations have been invaluable. Finally, to my wonderful family: to Angela, my loving wife, to our children, and to my parents, whose unconditional support and encouragement over the years has Page 1 of 2 Acknowledgements been a greater source of inspiration to me than they will ever know. To all of them I dedicate this book. (p.vi) Page 2 of 2 List of Abbreviations Epicurean Ethics in Horace: The Psychology of Satire Sergio Yona Print publication date: 2018 Print ISBN-13: 9780198786559 Published to Oxford Scholarship Online: March 2018 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198786559.001.0001 (p.ix) List of Abbreviations Sergio Yona ANRW Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt. 1972– . Berlin Arr. Arrighetti, G., ed. and trans. 1962. Epicuro: Opere. 2nd edn. Turin: Einaudi CIL 1863– . Corpus Inscriptionum Latinarum. Berlin DK Diels, H. and Kranz, W., eds. 1951–2. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. 3 vols. Berlin: Weidmann DL Diogenes Laertius Hdt. Epicurus, Letter to Herodotus KD Epicurus, Principal Doctrines (Κύριαι Δόξαι) LSJ Liddell, H. G. and Scott, R., rev. H. S. Jones 1925–40. Greek–English Lexicon. Oxford: Oxford University Press M Marx (Lucilius) Men. Epicurus, Letter to Menoeceus OCD Hornblower, S., Spawforth, A., and Eidinow, E. 2012. Oxford Classical Dictionary. Oxford: Oxford University Press OLD Page 1 of 2 List of Abbreviations Glare, P. G. W., ed. 2012. Oxford Latin Dictionary. Oxford: Oxford University Press PCG Poetae Comici Graeci PHerc. Papyrus Herculanensis Pyth. Epicurus, Letter to Pythocles RE Wissowa, G. et al. eds. 1893–1980. Paulys Realencyclopädie der classischen Altertumswissenschaft. Munich–Stuttgart SV Epicurus, Vatican Sayings (Sententiae Vaticanae) SVF Von Arnim, H., ed. 1905 (vols. 1–3), 1924 (vol. 4). Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta. Leipzig: Teubner TrGF Snell, B., Kannicht, R., and Radt, S., eds. 1977–2004. Tragicorum Graecorum Fragmenta. 5 vols. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht U Usener, H., ed. 1887. Epicurea. Leipzig: Teubner (p.x) Page 2 of 2 Introduction Epicurean Ethics in Horace: The Psychology of Satire Sergio Yona Print publication date: 2018 Print ISBN-13: 9780198786559 Published to Oxford Scholarship Online: March 2018 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198786559.001.0001 Introduction Sergio Yona DOI:10.1093/oso/9780198786559.003.0001 Abstract and Keywords The introduction serves to explain the general thesis of the book and its place in the scholarship tradition by providing a brief review of literature in connection with Horace’s Satires. Of particular importance are the contributions of scholars who regard persona theory as a useful tool for understanding and better appreciating these poems, as well as the views of those who consider the question of Horace’s audience. The introduction also defines the present study’s position with regard to both of these issues, which is then followed by a rationale behind the order in which individual poems are examined and an outline of the content of the chapters to follow. Keywords: Horace, Roman satire, Philodemus of Gadara, Epicurus, Herculaneum Horace, in describing the unreservedness of his predecessor Lucilius, notes that he “entrusted his secrets to his books as if they were faithful companions” (S. 2.1.30–1: ille velut fidis arcana sodalibus olim | credebat libris), with the result that the poet’s whole life “is open to view, as if painted on a votive tablet” (33: votiva pateat veluti descripta tabella).1 The self-revelatory expression of what appear to be one’s inner thoughts and convictions, which is at the heart of Roman satire,2 continues in Horace’s Satires but with one important shift regarding intention: whereas the revelation of Lucilius’ character and disposition is a by-product (cf. 32: quo fit, ut omnis…) of his criticism of contemporary society, Horatian satire is consciously introspective and, as such, revolves almost entirely around the poet’s reflections—whether explicit or made through implied contrast—concerning his own development and presentation in the context of satiric observations of Roman society. One would be justified in Page 1 of 13 Introduction assuming that such intimacy should ultimately reveal substantial information about the author’s own life, but the fact that both Horace, his predecessor, and all Roman satirists chose to disclose autobiographical details through poetry rather than prose suggests otherwise.3 Many have referred to Horace’s self- presentation as (p.2) a persona, which is informed by and responds to various literary traditions,4 often without staking any real claims or expressing the serious convictions of the man behind the mask. Kirk Freudenburg, for instance, who is part of a tradition beginning with Alvin Kernan’s 1959 The Cankered Muse and continuing with W. S. Anderson, regards any autobiographical information “not as documentary evidence for who [Horace] was, but as the first moves of a back-and-forth game played between reader and writer.”5 As the carefully crafted expression of poets, Roman satire first and foremost incorporates and often plays with the elements of many other traditions: there are comic situations and characters, parodies of epic poetry, literary criticism, and frequent engagement with philosophical teachings at every turn. Of course, the fact that not everything Horace says about himself is true—take, for example, his dubious claim in Epistles 2.2.51 to have been forced by paupertas audax to compose verses for survival, or his insistence that virtue rather than poetry was the cause of his successful encounter with Maecenas in Satires 1.6— further confirms that there is indeed an important theatrical or artistic component to his works. On the other hand, while persona theory has undoubtedly contributed to a more sophisticated or at least less naive understanding of Horace as poet, its over-application has often contributed to the view that satire is little more than an author’s entertaining but learned and intergeneric jeu d’esprit. According to this view, Horatian satire is disjointed, inept, and even schizophrenic at times, with the author employing different “masks” for different purposes without any real underlying connection.6 In order to restore balance by tipping the scales toward a more serious reading of the Satires but without denying the presence of fictional autobiography and humor, this study argues that Horace (p.3) portrays this poetic persona as consistently and competently engaged with Epicurean ethics throughout the entire collection. Its purpose is not to reveal definitively who the “real” Horace was or to uncover exactly what his convictions, philosophical or otherwise, were in life, which admittedly would be a fruitless attempt and one that any prudent scholar would consider misguided.7 Nor does it go to the extreme of claiming that Epicureanism is the only element in the Satires. Rather, it aims to show that in his earliest works Horace creates a coherent persona whose observations, criticisms, and views are perfectly consistent with Epicurean teachings regarding ethics, and that this engagement reveals a profound understanding of and interest in the intricacies of ethical doctrines that were a topic of polemical debate at the time. The notion that Horace’s persona is unified and communicates a coherent message is similar to the interpretation of Suzanne Sharland, who posits the predominant role of a “second self,” which is the Page 2 of 13 Introduction “overriding persona who is there in a sense throughout the Satires.”8 More specifically, this examination will suggest that it is possible to identify in these poems certain themes that, as will be shown in the following chapters, pervade most of the Satires and therefore provide overall unity,9 such as the poet’s self- proclaimed disposition as purus et insons (S. 1.6.69), his relationship with Maecenas, his attitude regarding wealth and his place in society, and the correct approach to applying criticism.10 These themes also determine the manner in which individual poems will be examined in this study and how this (p.4) organization contributes overall to Horace’s self-portrayal as an Epicurean moralizer: the strong views in Satires 1.1–3 regarding money, sex, and friendship, all of which rely heavily on the Epicurean calculus of pleasure and pain, are justified by the portrayal of his quasi-philosophical upbringing in Satires 1.4. This poem, which is at the heart of the first collection, also looks ahead to Satires 1.6 and explains, from a philosophical and moral point of view, how the poet’s persona made a positive impression on Maecenas, which is appropriately followed by the negative portrait of the pest in Satires 1.9 and the revelation of the members of Maecenas’ circle of friends in the last satire.11 In Book 2, Satires 2.1 and 2.5 revisit the topic of friendship in connection with frankness and flattery before turning once again to a positive description of Horace’s healthy relationship with Maecenas in Satires 2.6. Following this description of idealized friendship and philosophical discussion in the country, which is facilitated by the gift of the Sabine estate, is that of Ofellus in Satires 2.2, a rustic who resembles Horace’s persona but has recently experienced financial misfortune. Finally, in contrast to Ofellus’ Epicurean equanimity in the face of a crisis and his useful moral advice concerning how to live happily, Horace introduces Satires 2.3 and 2.7, which parody two Stoic novices’ misguided approach to what Horace’s persona does so well, namely, the offering of frank criticism that is generally cheerful and useful.12 One will immediately recognize that all of these topics and descriptions easily fall within the realm of ethics, which is not surprising given that Horace is often distinguished from other satirists by his significant concern with moral correction.13 Insofar as the Satires are largely introspective and deal with ethical issues, moreover, one may be justified in speaking of the “psychology of satire” with respect to Horace’s critical examinations, which are largely about his persona’s mental health (ψυχή; cf. S. 1.4.128–9: teneros animos…ego sanus) as (p.5) considered through prolonged and repeated conversations (λόγοι; cf. S. 2.6.71: sermo oritur) that function as a kind of therapeutic antidote to contemporary vices. Although his informal, and, especially in Book 2, dialectical style has been linked to that of Plato,14 most commentators recognize the predominant role of Hellenistic ethics in Horatian satire.15 By highlighting the role of Epicurean ethics in particular in the Satires, this study also attempts to demonstrate how Horace shows consistency in developing a persona throughout the collection that is not only concerned with “saving face,” as Ellen Oliensis argues,16 but with actively justifying his virtus and defending his place in society. The poet accomplishes Page 3 of 13 Introduction this goal not only by engaging closely with the works of Lucretius and Cicero, but by working largely within the framework of Epicurus’ moral doctrines as Philodemus of Gadara presents them in his treatises. The idea that in the Satires Horace constructs a coherent persona whose observations and criticisms are constantly engaged with Epicurean doctrine begs the question: to what end, or, on a related note, for whom did the poet intend such a persona? This leads to the question of audience, with which many scholars have grappled over the years and which has led to a variety of interesting theories. In reading Satires 1.1, Barbara Gold posits four layers of audience, including an internal one consisting of Maecenas and the addressee within the satire, and an external one consisting of upper class Romans and anyone else who might have had access to the poems.17 Frances Muecke similarly identifies two main groups, one fictitious (i.e. the nameless interlocutors) and the other actual (i.e. those actually hearing or reading the poems).18 Randall McNeill, on the other hand, suggests that there are five “rings” of possible audiences, with Maecenas in the middle (first ring), then Horace’s close friends and fellow poets (second ring), followed by the social elite (third ring), outsiders in general (fourth ring), and finally, those who “have no contact with the poet (p.6) and no hopes of advancing in his society but who read and respond to his poetry all the same” (fifth ring).19 Denis Feeney regards Horace as making a distinction between “aristocratic Romans who are his ideal readers,” such as those named at the end of Satires 1.10 (81–6), and “the babel of hybrid lowlife professionals who are also his readers, but his ‘unideal’ readers,” although he cautions against regarding this division as a “real state of affairs.”20 Although all of these theories contribute something to the understanding of audience in Horace’s earliest works, the following study adopts the view of Benjamin Hicks, who identifies the list of names in Satires 1.10 as the inner reading circle of his friends, who would have appreciated the convictions of an Epicurean persona (as opposed to outsiders, who may “fail to grasp the subtleties of satire”21). He states the following: Satire is characterized by its moral critique of human behaviors, not merely by the jokes and parodies. Some behaviors are inappropriate or inconsistent, but the implication of critiquing behavior is that a recognizably appropriate behavior does exist. This appropriate behavior stems from one’s culturally derived worldview, of which philosophical preferences are a part. Horace’s reading circle shows strong connections to Epicurean philosophy: Many of Horace’s friends were trained by Philodemus, and many other upper-class Roman males studied Greek philosophy extensively enough to engage in sophisticated arguments over the correct moral actions of their lives. Thus, philosophy and the debates between schools become focal points of intellectual sparring.22 Page 4 of 13