ebook img

Einstein and Aquinas: A Rapprochement PDF

160 Pages·1970·4.1 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Einstein and Aquinas: A Rapprochement

EINSTEIN AND AQUINAS: A RAPPROCHEMENT EINSTEIN AND AQUINAS: A RAPPROCHEMENT by JOHN F. KILEY Foreword by W. E. CARLO at University Ottawa MARTINUS NIJHOFF / THE HAGUE / 1969 LIBRARY OF CONGRESS CATALOG CARD NUMBER: 79-95)89 © I969 by Martinus Nijhotl. The Hague. Netherlands All rights reserved. including the right to translate or to reproduce this book or parts thereof in any form ISBN-B: 978-90-24H1081-3 e-ISBN-B: 978-94-{)IO-3172-1 001: IO.I007/978-94-{)IO-3172-1 To my Father and to my Mother, who began me on my search T ABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE IX INTRODUCTION XI FOREWORD XVII CHAPTER 1. THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF ALBERT EINSTEIN I Section A. The Inductive Beginnings of Scientific Investi- gation I Section B. The Formation of Primary Concepts according to Einstein. Their Invention 15 Section C. The Deductive Process. The Rules of Naturalness and Simplicity 25 Section D. The Epistemological Elements of the SPecial Theory of Relativity. Confirmation of the Theory 35 CHAPTER II. A METAPHYSICAL ANALYSIS OF EINSTEIN'S VIEW OF REALITY 46 Section A. The Notion of Reality in Albert Einstein 46 Section B. The Problem of the Reality of Relations 56 Section C. The Grasp of Reality in Mathematico-physicat Investigation 70 CHAPTER III. THE METAPHYSICAL FOUNDATIONS OF EINSTEIN'S EPISTEMOLOGY 78 Section A. The Foundations of Inductive Beginnings 78 Section B. The Roots of the Formation of the Primary Con- cepts 89 Section C. Judgment and Reasoning as Related to Scientific Postulation 98 Section D. The Confirmation of the Theorems and the Nature of Scientific Proof !O3 CONCLUSIONS 107 ApPENDIX. A NOTE ON THE DISCOVERY OF BEING IIO BIBLIOGRAPHY II4 INDEX 121 PREFACE Now how would things be intelligible if they did not proceed from an intelligence? In the last analy sis a Primal Intelligence must exist, which is itself Intellection and Intelligibility in pure act, and which is the first principle of intelligibility and essences of things, and causes order to exist in them, as well as an infinitely complex network of regular relationships, whose fundamental mysterious unity our reason dreams of rediscovering in its own way. Such an approach to God's existence is a variant of Thomas Aquinas' fifth way. Its impact was secretly present in Einstein's famous saying: "God does not play dice," which, no doubt, used the word God in a merely figurative sense, and meant only: "nature does not result from a throw of the dice," yet the very fact implicitly postulated the existence of the divine Intellect. Jacques Maritain God's creation is the insistence on the dependence of "epistemology" on ontology; man's acknow ledgement of creation is an insistence on the episte mological recovery of ontology. Paul Weiss My intellectual debts are many and if fully listed would run on in terminably. Passing over all the masters of philosophical thought who first awed and overpowered me and then led me on with gentle and great promises, more than fully kept, I would mention only those who, still among us, cannot know my gratitude unless I tell it. First to Professor Jacques Maritain for kindly tutelage and encouragement on this study first conceived at Princeton; then to Professor Joseph Owens C.SS.R., for taking me "inside" the metaphysics of St. Thomas; and to Professor Jacques Croteau, O.M.l., for sensitizing me in depth to epistemology and for other important philosophical and editorial help; finally, and most importantly, to Professor William E. Carlo, former x PREFACE professor and colleague at Ottawa, for my first real encounter with philosophic wisdom and the harmony of all knowledges, and for the example of a personal life nobly lived. Such errors as my book contains can only be because, exposed as I have been to greatness, I often blinked at the light. INTRODUCTION . .. we should admire the intellectual honesty of modem teachers who are not afraid to "Follow whithersoever the argument leads." It leads not only to an intellectual error, unfortunately. It leads to despair in the conviction that there is nothing in the objective world to satisfy the appetite for in telligibility. And thus, significantly, the modem philosopher who is responsible as much as any other for the popularity of a logic which presupposes human thought as ultimate, Bertrand Russell, pro claims a doctrine of despair as unmitigated as the human heart could entertain. Herbert Schwartz In the world of those who, in modern times, engage in scientific in vestigations involving the formulation of theories, there are two poles about which all these thinkers are arranged. That is to say, there are fundamentally two great schools to which all scientific theoreticians belong and in which they function either as teacher or pupil. There is on the one hand, the school of Albert Einstein relatively unpopulated yet immensely influential and, on the other, that of Bertrand Russell, heavily subscribed, powerfully amoebic and, therefore, just as im mensely influential. Let us now proceed to characterize these two schools. The school of Einstein is, in the first place, metaphysically involved in a considerable number of what have been called, "extra scientific problems" and which, for convenience, can be bracketed under the heading, "Realist Justifications." Striving for simplicity and unity it has not been able to find them and although it looks upon final unification as real goal, it considers it an immense task and, perhaps for this reason has an excellent record for making no prematurely foolish announcements of its achievement. That is to say, the failure to find it actually has not been the cause of generating illusions about it much in the manner of those for whom wishing makes it so. Now, the reason why this school does not find simplicity is because it does not deliber- XII INTRODUCTION ately abstract from philosophical controversy in order to achieve it, realizing, perhaps for the most part instinctively, that the rules for scientific investigation are so completely bound up with the real world as to be unintelligible without reference to it. Thus it will not, indeed cannot, restrict itself to questions of formal logic and in this respect like Aristotle will insist on having its Posterior Analytics as well. For it cannot be satisfied with a greater communication and consensus which is purchased at the price of an impoverishment of understanding and justification. Thus, it will cry out against the "fateful fear of Meta physics" of the Bertrand Russells who, by avoiding philosophical con siderations, would turn physics into logic. In contrast, the school of Russell will argue that metaphysical considerations are unnecessary, for it is the rules that must be adhered to as all important and this can be done amidst diversity of interpretation for their validity, just as many different people lead decent lives from motives ranging all the way from the love of God to fear of the policeman. So, too, the Rus selites would contend a unanimity of view can be achieved on the level of pragmatic understanding and by the test of consistency. This would save much time from controversy, which, at best, cannot raise itself above mere opinion and may become an end in itself like the futile hair-splitting of the scholastics. But this argument does not satisfy Einstein and perceiving this, the attempt is made to convince him" out of his own mouth." For does not the combining of Space and Time into a four-dimensional continuum in which only the event has meaning, thus eliminating the concept of the material thing, show that matter is mind and mind is matter and formal consistency is the only "real" problem confronting the mathematical physicist? The quick and firm Einsteinian answer is that the concept of thing should be retained. For Einstein is just as sure that physics is not logic or mathematics as he is that concepts are not things. He is as sure that there is an enduring real behind sense appearances as he is unsure of the final structure of this reality which he had dedicated himself to reach. Thus it is that one perceives in Einstein a positive yearning to reach and to know the real, that has, as a result, already disposed his epistemology to an inquiry into a deeper justification than it actually has. For in the last analysis Einstein cannot defend himself against the logicians of the type of Russell and Whitehead on this question of a real distinction between mind and matter nor can his epistemology have any other defense than the test of success, if the logicians prevail. For in such a logical reduction is removed the very ground for justifying such INTRODUCTION XIII an epistemology in terms of an explanation which does not do violence to the strongly realist instincts of Einstein. This study will attempt to supply the means of an Einsteinian de fense by giving his epistemology a stable and scientific ground within the real order by recourse to the metaphysical doctrines of St. Thomas Aquinas.l It will attempt to explain the necessity for certain epistemo logical procedures uniquely proper to Einstein by referring them to the dynamical activities and relationships of the most fundamental com ponents of the real world for Thomistic metaphysics viz., matter and form, predicamental accidents, essence and existence.2 It will for ex ample, try to show the root of the rule requiring sensible beginnings for all scientific theorising in the priority of existence over essence with especial attention to what is peculiar to Einstein's methodological procedure in the observance of this rule. Einstein insists on sensible beginnings for scientific investigations. There is no logical path, he contends, from sensible things to the first concepts and axioms of a system of scientific deductive thought and experiences can do no more than suggest, but the origins are firmly rooted to the real world of sensible realities. There is no stronger credo in the whole Einsteinian epistemology. At the same time there is lacking in Einstein's work any foundation for this methodological law other than an historico-pragmatic one. ~ ow this cannot be spoken of as a foundation even in the loosest terminology but only as a common sense "rule of thumb" arrived at by inductions from the history of natural philosophy or "science" as it has come to be called. Einstein speaks of Greek, Mediaeval, "classical" i.e. Renaissance, 1 On this point G. Klubertanz, S.J., writes about "those who assert that all the special sciences are based on metaphysics. On the ground that metaphysics alone can formally treat of the most universal principles of knowledge, they maintain that all the sciences which use those principles are thereby based on metaphysics. This, however, is an overstatement. It is true that only metaphysics can discuss certain universal principles correctly. But iliat does not make the other sciences formally depend on metaphysics. Any particular science starts with a certain number of assumptions, and, as far as the internal necessities of that science are concerned, these assumptions can remain unproved assumptions. As long as a thinker works within that particular science, he need never go back beyond these assumptions. True enough, if the thinker wants to find ilie foundation of his science outside that science and continues his search far enough, he will ultimately come to metaphysics. But this search is precisely no longer within science." Introduction to Being, Appleton-Century-Crofts, Inc., N. Y., 1952, p. 278. 2 I am not attempting to do what Father Louis Marie Regis warns against: " ... to wish to construct a discourse on Thomistic method by taking science as a point of departure is to try to justify intellect by reason, the end by the means, the cause by the effect which amounts to seeking an absurd criterion by absurd means." L. M. REGIS, O.P., Epistemology, New York, Macmillan 1959, p. 465. See also "L'Mre dans Ie lit de Procuste," by Jacques CROTEAU, O.M.I., in Revue de l'Universitif d'Ottawa, 29 (1959), p. 181.

Description:
Now how would things be intelligible if they did not proceed from an intelligence? In the last analy­ sis a Primal Intelligence must exist, which is itself Intellection and Intelligibility in pure act, and which is the first principle of intelligibility and essences of things, and causes order to e
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.