ebook img

Diplomatic Calculus in Anarchy: How Communication Matters PDF

22 Pages·2010·0.42 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Diplomatic Calculus in Anarchy: How Communication Matters

AmericanPoliticalScienceReview Vol.104,No.2 May2010 doi:10.1017/S0003055410000158 Diplomatic Calculus in Anarchy: How Communication Matters ROBERT F. TRAGER UniversityofCaliforniaatLosAngeles Whenstatescometobelievethatotherstatesarehostiletotheirinterests,theyoftenreorienttheir foreign policies by realigning alliance commitments, building arms, striking first, mobilizing troops, or adopting policies to drain the resources of states that menace them. This article presentsacrisisbargainingmodelthatallowsthreatenedstatesawiderarrayofresponsesthanthechoice tobackdownornot.Twoimplicationsarethat(1)“cheaptalk”diplomaticstatementsbyadversariescan affectperceptions of intentions,and (2) war can occur because resolved states decline tocommunicate theirintentions,eventhoughtheycould,andeventhoughdoingsowouldavoidawar.Themodelrelates thecontentandqualityofdiplomaticsignalstothecontextofpriorbeliefsaboutintentionsandstrategic options.Insimulations,thisformofdiplomaticcommunicationreducesthelikelihoodofconflict. In the fall of 1876, Russia queried Germany as to therefore,alsofailtoexplainthecase.4YetBismarck’s what its position would be if Russia were to go appraisal was correct: thereafter, Russia reckoned on towarwithAustria-Hungary.Germanyreplied,as GermansupportforAustria-Hungary.5 delicately as it possibly could, that it could not guar- Inthisarticle,Idescribeabargainingmodelinwhich antee its neutrality in such an eventuality, and that stateshavearicherarrayofoptionsthantheprevious “a lasting weakening of Austria would be contrary to literature has allowed. This results in a mechanism of [German] interests.”1 The German chancellor, Otto information transmission that provides a convincing von Bismarck, thought that this created a “new situ- explanationforthiscase,and,Ishallargue,represents ation”intheGerman-Russianrelationship.2Hemeant an essential aspect of interstate diplomacy. The anar- that Germany had increased Russian expectations chic strategic context can provide less resolved states aboutGermany’swillingnesstogotowaronbehalfof withadisincentivetomisrepresentingtheirintentions. Austria, and perhaps decreased Russia’s appraisal of Very often, when states negotiate over important se- the extent to which Germany would support Russian curity concerns, there is a danger that a threat (or aimsgenerally. othernoncooperativebehavior)willresultinabreach Accordingtomosttheoriesofinformationtransmis- in relations, not merely with respect to the issue at sionbetweenstates,thisshouldhavebeenimpossible. hand, but also with respect to other aspects of the Germanycommunicateditspositionprivatelythrough relationship. In such cases, states can send “costless” diplomaticchannels.Thus,Germanelitesdidnotstake signalsabouttheirintentions.Informationisconveyed their reputation before a domestic audience, nor did by threats because states understand the dangers of theiractionscarryexplicitcosts,twocommonlyrecog- altering other states’ perceptions of their intentions, nized mechanisms of information transmission.3 Fur- andyetchoosetothreatenanywaywhentheyaresuffi- ther, Germany’s noncommittal statements can hardly cientlyresolved.Alternatively,ifforeignpolicychoices beconsideredtohavesoengageditsreputationbefore areresponsivetoperceptionsofotherstates’intentions theRussianandinterstateaudiencesthatanyonecould at all, then explicit threats from one state to another, have believed Germany significantly less willing to whether in public or private, can convey information. backdownforfearoftherepercussionsofhavingbeen Thus, this article contributes to the literature on the caught in a bluff. Theories of information transmis- conditionsunderwhichcostlessdiplomaticsignalsare sionthatrelyonthestakingofbargainingreputations, informative.6 A second result of the model is a path by which incompleteinformationcanleadtoconflictthatisdif- RobertF.TragerisAssistantProfessor,DepartmentofPoliticalSci- ferent from the mechanism in other models in the ence, University of California at Los Angeles, 4289 Bunche Hall, literature. War can occur in some equilibria because Box951472,LosAngeles,CA90095-1472([email protected]). resolved states decline to communicate their resolve IamgratefultoMichaelChwe,MariaFanis,ErikGartzke,Mike Horowitz,RobertJervis,AndyKydd,HelenMilner,BarryO’Neill, Kris Ramsay, Sebastian Rosato, Ken Schultz, Art Stein, Dessie 4See,forinstance,Sartori(2005).SeeFearon(1995)forananalysis ZagorchevaandseminarparticipantsattheOlinInstituteforuseful oftheefficacyofcostlessdiplomaticsignals. commentsandsuggestions,aswellastoBobandJudithTerryand 5AstheGermanAmbassadorwrote,“nothingwasmorenatural” OrielCollege,Oxford,foraconduciveenvironmentinwhichtowrite. (Schweinitz1927,350–1)thanfortheTsartoexpectaguaranteeof Ibearresponsibilityforremainingerrorsandomissions. Germanneutrality,andheremainedopenlydisturbedbytheGer- 1Schweinitz (1927, 360). The Russians did not explicitly threaten manresponsefordays(Rupp1941,204;Schweinitz1927,360–364). Austria,butitwasatthistimethatthesaying,“theroadtoCon- AccordingtotheRussiandiplomatKartsov,theideaofdeclaringwar stantinopleleadsthroughVienna”(Rupp1941,232)gainedpopu- onAustria“wasabandoned”because“PrinceBismarckforewarned larityinRussiandiplomaticandmilitarycirclesandmanyRussians that Austria was necessary for Germany for reasons of political andGermansthoughtthatthetense,ongoingAustro-Russian ne- balance of power and that Germany would therefore not permit gotiationscouldleadtowar.SeeIgnatyev(1931,391),Rupp(1941, deliveringAustriaadeath-blow”(Rupp1941,297).SeeTrager(2007, 297),Saburov(1929,82),Schweinitz(1927,359),andGrossePolitik, chap.3). II,54–66,74–9. 6Otherworksonthissubject,inadditiontothosecitedabove,in- 2Bismarck1915,286. clude Guisinger and Smith (2002), Jervis (1970), Kurizaki (2004), 3See,forinstance,Fearon(1994)andKydd(1997). Kydd(2003),Ramsay(2004),andSchelling(1966;1980). 347 DiplomaticCalculusinAnarchy May2010 even though they could, and even though this would change is more often intentional. To bring about this preventthewar.Thiscanoccurwhenonestateishighly sort of change, attempts at communication must suc- resolved,andbelievesthatanotherisalso,butbelieves ceed in conveying information. That is, they must be that the other state does not believe that the first is believed,atleastpartially.Thisarticlewillnotaddress highly resolved. In such cases, if the first state were howsymbolsacquiretheirmeaningsorhowindividuals to signal its resolve, there would be a high probabil- are initiated into language groups.7 Rather, I assume ity that the other state would prepare for conflict. To for analytical purposes that a shared and unchanging avoid this likelihood, the first state declines to con- language exists and ask this second question, namely, vey its resolve to the other. Sometimes, however, the howitisthatattemptsatcommunicationbyadversaries second state would have been willing to comply with canconveyinformation. the first state’s demand in order to avoid war. Thus, In particular, I look at one of the most adversarial in this situation, resolved states mimic the behavior aspects of relations between states, when one is at- of unresolved states in order to catch the other side tempting to coerce another through a threat to use unprepared.Thiscontrastswithothersignalingmodels force.8Here,morethanelsewhere,weexpectcommu- inwhichitisgenerallyunresolvedstatesthatwouldlike nication to be difficult because the state making the toimitatethesignalssentbyresolvedstates. threathasanincentivetomisrepresentitspreferences This second point is similar to results derived from in order to make the threat appear more credible. In other recent models that have begun to expand the such situations, as Jervis (1970) recognized, analysts range of state options beyond those conceived of in distinguishpotentialsourcesofinformationthatcanbe traditionalbargainingmodels.Ritter(2004,chap.2)ar- manipulatedfromthosethatcannot.Thelattercanbe guesthatstatessometimesmaketheiralliancessecret, believed,whereastheformeronlyconveyinformation inspiteofthedrawbacksfromthepointofviewofde- incertaincontexts. terrence,topreventpotentialadversariesfromtaking Withinthecategoryofinformationsourcesthatcan countermeasures.Slantchev(n.d.)presentsanultima- bemanipulated,somemessagesarecredible,evenbe- tum game in which rejected offers lead to conflicts in tweenadversaries,becausesenderswouldnotwantto which each side must choose a level of effort in the misrepresent their preferences although they could. fighting. Because the optimal effort of states depends When the message causes the sender, in some con- on each side’s perception of the strength of the other tingencies,toincurcostsasadirectresultofsendingthe side,statessometimeshaveanincentivetomakeoffers message, such messages are called “costly signals.” In inthepreconflictstagethathidetheirtruestrength.The game-theoreticterms,thedecisiontosendthemessage model below reveals a similar dynamic in the context or not has a direct effect on the payoff function of of costless diplomatic encounters across a wide range the sender. Perhaps the clearest example from inter- of seemingly disparate contexts, from alliance politics national relations is the decision to build arms. This tonuclearbrinkmanship. affects the balance of capabilities directly, but if the The article has four sections. In the first, I locate arms are costly enough,9 it may also send a signal to the argument in the literature on communication in anadversaryaboutthestate’sintentions.10 Theadver- internationalrelations.Inthesecond,Iarguethatthe sarymayconcludethatalessresolvedstatewouldbe strategicoptionsavailabletothreatenedstatesgowell unwillingtopaythosecosts.11 beyond the binary choice to comply or not in tradi- tionalmodelsofcoercion.Thethirdsectionpresentsa modelthatallowsstatesthatarethreatenedtoprepare 7Theliteraturethataddressesthesequestionsistoolargetociteeven for conflicts and to choose themselves to engage in arepresentativesample.Amongphilosophers,theworkofLudwig conflict. When these preparations are effective, infor- Wittgensteinisthemostwidelyappreciated.Withininternationalre- mativecostlesssignalingoccursinplausibleequilibria. lations,seeforinstance,FinnemoreandSikkink(1998),Jervis(1970, 139–224),O’Neill(1999),andWendt(1999,313–69). Thissectiondiscussestheconditions under whichsig- 8SeeSchelling(1966,70–1)forthedefinitionofcoercionassubsum- naling can be effective, and under which wars occur ing“deterrence”and“compellence.”ButseealsoMorgan(2003,3) thatavailablebutunusedsignalscouldprevent.Afinal foradiscussionoftheintimaterelationshipofthesetwofroman sectiondiscussesimplicationsoftheanalysis. analyticalpointofview. 9If spending on arms does not reach a threshold related to the possible values states could place on the issue in question, it will generallybebeuninformative(atleastasacostlysignal). COMMUNICATION, CONSTRUCTION, AND 10Foradefinitionofintentionsthatissimilartothegame-theoretic DETERRENCE conceptofastrategy,seeJervis(1976,48–57).Foranotherdefinition ofintention,seeBratman(1999). Social aspects of the human world exist in language, 11Itisnotarguedherethatstatesmustdrawthisconclusionwhen through which they are created, altered, and reified. they observe other states choosing to build arms, but merely that such a dynamic is plausible and easily grasped. There is a large Withinthesocialrealm,somecomplexconstructs,for literature that discusses costly signaling, especially as it relates to instance, those that would be identified as sources of crisisbargaining.See,forinstance,Fearon(1995;1997),Jervis(1970, cultural difference, are the products of many agents 28–9),Kydd(1997),Morrow(1989),andPowell(1990).Italsomay interactingoverlongperiodsoftimeandconsequently beworthnotingthat,asSartori(2005,58)pointsout,although“audi- encecosts”havebeenmodeledascostlysignals,thisisprobablybest change only very gradually in general. But other as- thoughtofasamodelingshorthand(whenvotersarenotmodeled pects of the social world, such as the “situation” de- explicitly) for what is really a costless process. See also Ramsay scribed by Bismarck, change more quickly, and such (2004)andSmith(1998). 348 AmericanPoliticalScienceReview Vol.104,No.2 Butmessagesneednotbeassociatedwithdirectcosts ial for costless communication to occur. For instance, for there to be disincentives to lie, and thus for the Schellingnotedthat“wordsarecheap,notinherently message to enable to the receiver to learn something credible when they emanate from an adversary....”15 from it. Whether such disincentives exist depends on Fearon, careful not to overstate the case, argued that the strategic context. Suppose, for instance, that an “itremainsunclearwhethercheaptalkisimportantin employer wants to give a high-paying position to an international disputes....” His work as a whole sug- experienced applicant and a low-paying position to gests, however, that, “costless signals... have no ef- an inexperienced one. If there is no way to verify fect” on international outcomes.16 Many other schol- whetheracandidateistellingthetruth,thecandidate ars have followed their lead. I show below that the mayhaveahardtimeconvincingtheemployerthathe preferencesofstateadversariesareinfactsometimes orshedeservesthehigh-payingposition.Ontheother sufficientlyalignedtoallowcostlesscommunicationto hand,ifthehigh-payingpositionisforapilotandthe occur. low-paying one for a flight steward, the candidate’s This distinction between costly and costless signals statementsabouthisorherhoursofflightexperience mayseemmerelytechnical,withlittlesubstantiveim- may well be at least partially informative. Misrepre- portance.Thisisnotthecase.Onithingesthequestion senting qualifications in this case may result in his or of whether diplomacy, particularly that practiced by herflyingplanes,whichfortheinexperiencedmayre- leaders behind closed doors, can play a role in de- sultinacrashthathasnegativeconsequencesforboth termining the course of events in a rationalist frame- employerandemployee.Inthisemploymentexample, work.Macro-leveltheoriesoftheinternationalsystem therefore,thetwosideshaveinterestsincommon;com- havegenerallyclaimedtoexplaininternationalevents municationofprivateinformationmaybepossible.In withoutreferencetodiplomaticcommunication.17This the game-theoretic literature, such signals are called orientationhasreceivedsupportfrommicro-levelthe- costless because the actions available to agents and orizing of conflict processes, which has suggested (if the payoffs associated with material outcomes are all not stated outright) that only directly costly activities unchangednomatterwhichmessageissent.12 suchasmobilizingtroops,buildingarms,andcreating Models in the economics literature show that the “backdowncosts”canconveyinformation.Asaresult, maximal degree of precision of credible costless mes- international relations scholarship has neglected the sagesincreasesastheinterestsofsenderandreceiver studyoftheroleofprivatediplomaticcommunications, grow more aligned.13 In two-player games, when re- boththeoreticallyandempirically. lationships are zero-sum, no “cheap talk” communi- Thereareimportantexceptionstothischaracteriza- cation is possible at all. Understanding the degree to tionoftheliterature,however,andrecentscholarship which interests are aligned, however, turns out to be has shown a renewed interest in the mechanisms of farmoredifficultthanitappearsatfirstglance.14 private diplomacy. Sartori (2002; 2005) has demon- Many scholars of international relations have con- strated that private diplomatic communications can cludedthatrelationsbetweenstatesaretooadversar- be made credible by the desire of states to maintain a bargaining reputation, which makes them hesitant to send misleading signals for fear of being caught 12The term “costly signal” is sometimes used differently from its in a bluff.18 Guisinger and Smith (2002) combine two definitioninthegame-theoreticliteraturetorefertocommunication mechanismsthatrelyonanydisincentivesassociatedwithsending strainsoftheliteraturetoshowthatinthepresenceof thesignal,whetherdirectorarisingoutofthestrategicinteractionof a reputational mechanism along the lines of Sartori’s, agents.Becauseanysignalofresolvethatconveysinformationmust democratic selection of leaders results in an endoge- resultfromadisincentivetounresolvedtypestosendthesignal,all nousadditionaldisincentiveagainstbluffing.Kurizaki informative signals must be “costly” in this sense. The staking of privatereputations,whichconveyinformationbecauseofthe“cost” (2004)showsthatifapubliclythreatenedstatewilllose ofnotbeingbelievedinthefuture(Sartori2005),andeveryother face by backing down, then it is sometimes optimal mechanismofinformationtransmissionarecostlysignalsonthisun- forstatestomakeprivatethreats.Suchthreatsdonot derstanding,butnotaccordingtothewaythesetermsareunderstood increase the probability that the threatened state as- inthegame-theoreticliterature.Recentworkinpoliticalsciencehas signs to the threatener following through, but neither usedthegame-theoreticterminology.Intheinternationalrelations literature,seeKydd(2003),Ramsay(2004),andSartori(2005,51). do these private threats cause that probability to go Inotherliteraturesee,forinstance,GilliganandKrehbiel(1987). tozero.19 Kydd(2003)presentsacheap-talkmodelof 13SeeCrawfordandSobel(1982),FarrellandGibbons(1989),and third-partymediation.20 foranontechnicaldiscussion, FarrellandRabin(1996).Tobetter understandthedistinctionbetweencostlyandcostlesssignals,itmay beusefultoconsiderthefollowing.Ifsendingthesignalcoststhe sender $100 and the receiver of the signal infers something from 15Schelling(1980,150).Elsewhere,Schellingarguesthatwordsused thesender’swillingnesstopay$100,thisconstitutesacostlysignal. toframeanissueaffectperceptionsofresolve.SeeSchelling(1966, Supposethesignalcostsnothingtosend,however,butconveysin- 35–91). formationthatcausesthereceivertotake$100fromthesender.The signalmayonlyhaveaffectedthereceiver’sbeliefsbecauseofthe 16Fearon(1997,69). anticipatedreactionofthereceiverandthesender’swillingnessto 17Forinstance,Mearsheimer(2001);Schweller(1998);Walt(1987); sufferthereceiver’sreaction.Nevertheless,thisscenariorepresents Waltz(1979). acostlesssignalbecausethedisincentivetosendamisleadingsignal 18Jervis(1970,78–83),Schelling(1966;1980),andothershavealso arisesfromthestrategicinteractionofthetwoagentsratherthan argued in favor of a reputational signaling mechanism in private fromadirectcostoftakingtheactionitself.Thisissoeventhough diplomacy. theultimateresult—thelossornotof$100—isthesame. 19SeealsoFearon(1997,84). 14SeeAxelrod(1970). 20Ramsay(2004)describesacheap-talkmodelofpublicdiplomacy. 349 DiplomaticCalculusinAnarchy May2010 Earlierworkdescribesseveralothermechanismsof Further,inmanycaseswherereputationsmayappear privatediplomacy.21Schelling(1966,1980)arguedthat to have been staked, the mechanism I propose here threats sometimes risk an undesired event that nei- representsanalternativeandsometimesmoreplausi- thersidedirectlycontrols,whichcausesthethreatsto bleexplanationofcommunication. convey information. The essence of brinkmanship is Themodelinthisarticlecontributestothisgrowing thatwhenoneclimberwhoisropedtoanothermoves literature by providing a new mechanism of informa- closertotheedge,heorshemayslip.Bydemonstrating tiontransmissionbetweenstatesthatappliestocertain a willingness to slip, the climber conveys information systemiccontextsandappealsneithertothecostliness abouthisorherresolveintheissuebeingnegotiated.22 ofthesignal,nortobargainingreputation.Thetheory Schelling’sanalysisfocusesonhowengaginginlimited appliesequallytomessagesconveyedinpublicandin forms of conflict can constitute an implicit threat be- private. It also demonstrates that a similar signaling cause it demonstrates a willingness to risk even more mechanism is at work in seemingly diverse strategic costly conflict. Private threats may have a similar ef- contexts, such as nuclear brinkmanship and alliance fect,however,inthattheydelayresolutionoftheissue bargaining. and create a crisis atmosphere in which conflict may be more likely. Schelling’s work bears important sim- THE STRATEGIC CONTEXT OF ANARCHY ilarities to the analysis to follow. Here, however, the emphasis will be on the intentional action of actors Inprominentmodelsintheinternationalrelationslit- ratherthanthepartlyexogenousdangerofslidingoff erature, the strategic options of the target of a threat acliffandontheimplicationsofincludingtheoptionto arelimited:itcanstandfirmorconcede.Thisconceptu- prepareinmodelsoftheconflictprocess.Theanalysis alizationdoesnotcorrespondtotheoptionsandincen- tofollowalsomakesitclearthatsomeofthedynamics tivesofstatesintheanarchicinternationalcontext.Ifa ofengaginginlimitedconflictareequallygermaneto statecomestobelieveitcannotachieveitskeystrategic costlesssignalsandthustoprivatediplomacy.23 aimsthroughitscurrentrelationshipwithanotherstate, Ofthesemechanismsforprivateinformationtrans- it may choose to alter that relationship. In particular, mission, the staking of bargaining reputations has re- rather than merely deciding whether or not to back ceived the most attention. Despite some scholarship down, threatened states must decide how to prepare that argues to the contrary, I believe the diplomatic– forconflictiftheybelieveabreachwithathreatening historical record supports the proposition that the state is imminent. In such cases, states often reorient maintenance of a reputation for being true to one’s theirsecuritypoliciesinordertodrainresourcesfrom commitments has been an important force in inter- the threatening state, and they also tend to form new national affairs.24 As in the case of Germany’s tacit alliancesthatarecontrarytothethreateningstate’sse- threat to Russia in 1876, mentioned above, however, curityinterests.Inaddition,whenthetargetofathreat important information is often conveyed by costless believesfutureconflictismorelikely,itwillsometimes diplomacy that cannot be explained by reputational choose to increase arms production, mobilize troops, dynamics. In this case and in many others, in making or strike first. These decisions are often made before athreat,policy-makersonbothsideswerenotprimar- the threatening state chooses to back down or follow ilyconcernedwithbargainingreputation.Rather,Ger- throughonitsthreatandhaveconsequenceswhether many worried about consequences that would follow ornotthestatesinvolvedultimatelygotowar.25 if,asitexpected, itsprivatethreatwere foundcredible. ToillustratethestrategicchoicesavailabletoTargets, considertheresponsesofU.S.PresidentKennedyand Soviet Premier Khrushchev to each other’s threats in theirJune1961meeting.Putsimply,eachthreatenedto 21Jervis(1970)proposesthreeadditionalmechanismsthroughwhich escalatetowariftheotherdidnotacceptasettlement privatethreatscouldconveyinformation.First,ifleadersarereticent oftheBerlinquestionfavorabletohisside.Following tolieformoralreasons,credibilitymayattachtotheirstatements. themeeting,Khrushchevrespondedbyadoptinganew Second, if a country has a stake in the current functioning of the international system, a reticence to lie may derive from a desire set of policies designed to drain the resources of the toensurethatstatesdonottoooftendeceiveeachotherbecause United States. On August 1, he “approved most of a abaselineofhonestcommunicationmayberequiredtomaintain KGB plan to create ‘a situation in various areas of theoverallsystemicequilibrium.Third,liesmayresultinunwanted theworldthatwouldfavorthedispersionofattention “changesintheinternationalenvironment.”Sometimes,ifastate- mentisbelieved,otheractorsmayactinsuchawaythattheactor andresourcesbytheUnitedStatesandtheirsatellites, makingthestatementhasanadditionalincentivetofollowthrough and would tie them down during the settlement of a onthestatement.Forinstance,ifonestateprofesseshostilitytoward GermanpeacetreatyandWestBerlin.”’26Forhispart, another, the reaction of the second state may make it in the first state’sinteresttotakehostileactionsithadnotoriginallyplanned ontaking. 25Worksthatarguethatstatesreacttoperceptionsofintentionsin 22Powell(1988)formalizesthisideainthecontextofinadvertent waysdescribedhereincludeJervis(1976,chap.3),Schelling(1966), war. Schultz(2001),Schweller(1994),andWalt(1987).Oneworkthat 23Theconstructivistliteraturehasemphasizedtheroleofbehavior arguesagainststateresponsivenesstotheintentionsofotherstates in creating norms and shaping expectations, interests, and identi- isMearsheimer(2001).Waltz(1979)doesnotargueagainstacausal ties,buthasnotfocusedonthecommunicationofintentionamong roleforperceptionsofintentions.Rather,hearguesonlyforasep- adversaries.See,however,DerDerian(1987). arateandindependenteffectofthedistributionofcapabilities.See 24For criticisms of a reputational signaling mechanism, see Jervis Waltz(2003,53). (1984),Mercer(1996),Morrow(1994),andPress(2005). 26FursenkoandNaftali(1999,138). 350 AmericanPoliticalScienceReview Vol.104,No.2 hardasitistoimaginetoday,Kennedybegantotake changemyalliances.”Withthat,thealignmentbetween the idea of a nuclear first strike more seriously. He thetwocountriesended.32 toldtheJointChiefsofStaffthat“Berlindevelopments The danger of a great power realignment resulting mayconfrontuswithasituationwherewemaydesire from a general breach in Russo-German relations is to take the initiative in the escalation of conflict from also the explanation for the information conveyed by the local to the general [nuclear] war level.”27 Thus, Germany’s statements in 1876 discussed above. Both because both leaders were unwilling to back down, sidesunderstoodthatevenatacitthreatfromGermany they considered or adopted policies to prepare for a might lead Russia to form an alliance with France, conflicttheythoughtmightbeimminent. Germany’s arch rival since the Franco-Prussian war Alternatively, consider the Japanese strategic cal- six years before. The fact that Germany understood culus in 1941. In November of that year, the United the danger, and yet chose to tacitly threaten anyway, StatesdemandedthatJapanwithdrawfromChina.This meantthatGermanyhadeffectivelycommunicatedits amountedto“surrenderingherpositionasapowerin resolvetodefendAustria-Hungary.33 theFarEast.”28 JapanwasunwillingtoaccedetoU.S. To fix ideas, and to see the relationship between demands, and, precisely because it found U.S. threats preparation for conflict and communication, consider credible,decidedtotakeradicalactiontopreparefor the following stylized examples of international con- the coming conflict. In the hope of demonstrating its textsinwhichcostlesscommunicationispossible.The resolvetoresist,andofengaginginonlyalimitedwar modelpresentedinthenextsectionisdesignedtorep- withtheUnitedStates,Japanoptedtodestroytheof- resentthesesituationsinastylizedway.Asthesenar- fensivecapabilityoftheU.S.fleetatPearlHarbor.29 ratives make clear, signaling dynamics can be similar Thehistoryofinternationalrelationsisfullofexam- inseeminglydiversestrategiccontexts. ples of states responding to diplomatic pressure with Example 1 (External Balancing). A conflict arises actions that go well beyond a simple refusal to com- between two states, a Deterrer and a Target, over a plywithademand.Infact,whereimportantquestions specific issue. In order to get its way, the Deterrer of security are concerned, simply declining to comply would like to signal its willingness to go to war over with demands is likely the exception rather than the theissuetotheTarget.TheDeterrerknows,however, rule.TheJapaneseresponsetoU.S.,British,andDutch thatiftheissueisparticularlyimportanttotheTarget, policy in 1941 was exceptional only in scale and deci- thelattermayformanalliancewithathirdcountryin siveness. order to get its way or prepare for a possible conflict. InresponsetoAustrianthreatsduringtheCrimean The Target would prefer not to make the concessions War, Russia took actions it would not have taken to the third state required to get an agreement, and otherwise. These included colluding with France and the new alliance is also likely to have a negative ef- Sardinia to strip Austriaof northern Italy, tipping the fect on the Deterrer’s security position, especially if balance in Germany in favor of Prussia, permitting the third country is already hostile to the Deterrer. therevolutioninHungarythatresultedintheAustro- Threat-makingthereforehasbothanadvantageanda HungarianAusgleich(insteadofassistinginsuppress- drawback. The advantage is the increased likelihood ingtheHungariansasRussiahadbeforethewar),and thattheTargetstatewillconcedetheissuetotheDe- declining torenewgenerous offersofRusso-Austrian terrer; the drawback is the possibility that the Target cooperation in the Balkans, leading to drastically in- will“balance”againsttheDeterrerbyformingahostile creasedsecuritycompetitionintheregionbetweenthe twocountries.30Morespeculatively,butwithsomejus- alliance. As has been mentioned, this was the princi- palconcerninGermanrelationswithRussiaafterthe tice, the historian Norman Rich argues that the Aus- Franco-Prussian war. Deterrers for whom the issue is trian threats during the Crimean War resulted in “a notsufficientlyimportantareunwillingtoincurtherisk bitterhostilitythatwastoculminateinwarin1914,the ofsuchabreachinrelationsbymakingathreat.When destructionofbothimperialhouses,andtheliquidation oftheHabsburgEmpire.”31 the Target state observes a threat, therefore, it learns theissueisrelativelyimportanttothethreateningstate. A particularly common response to dissatisfaction with another country’s conduct of foreign policy and Example 2 (Internal Balancing). As the name im- its perceived hostile intentions is the realigning of al- plies,thisscenarioissimilartothelast,exceptthatthe liance commitments. In 1864, for instance, Napoleon principlestrategicoptionoftheTarget(thethreatening III wished to use a European conference to revise state’sprincipalconcern)istotransferresourcestoits the post–Napoleonic Wars settlement of 1815. When militarysectorinorder,oneday,toresistthedemands Britain,withwhichFrancewascloselyaligned,refused ofthethreateningstate.ThetimingofChina’sdecision tosupportaconference,Napoleonwasexplicit:“Soit in the 1950s to devote enormous diplomatic and ma- seemsweshallhavenoCongress.Well!Ishallhaveto terialresourcestothepursuitofnuclearweapons,for instance,mayhavebeenpartlyaresultofU.S.threats in the first and second Taiwan Strait Crises. Because 27CitedinPress(2005,5);italicsadded. 28Feis(1950,327). 29SeeGeorge(1991,19)andRussett(1967). 32Mosse(1958,142). 30ForadetailedcomparisonandanalysisofRussianforeignpolicy 33Forananalysisofthiscase,seeTrager(2007,chap.3).Forarelated beforeandaftertheAustrianthreats,seeTrager(2007,chap.2). argumentonthefollow-oneffectsofalliancerealignments,seeHealy 31Rich(1965,123). andStein(1973). 351 DiplomaticCalculusinAnarchy May2010 such arms production alters the future bargaining re- Ineachofthesenarratives,thedecisionstheTargetof lationshipbetweenthenations,internalbalancingwill athreattakeswhenitmeanstoresistthedeterring(or often constitute a significant long-term drawback to compelling) state’s demands have a negative impact threat-making. on the Deterrer’s utility. If the Target chooses either internal or external balancing, the Deterrer’s utility Example 3 (First Strike). If a Deterrer threatens a willbenegativelyaffectedevenifitchoosesnottogo Target,themilitaryandstrategiccontextmaybesuch to war. This is true when the increased capabilities of thatiftheTargetisunwillingtobackdownandbelieves the Target increase the likelihood that the Target will theDeterringstateisalsosufficientlyunlikelytoback decidetogotowaritself,andmayalsobetruewhenthe down,theTarget’sbestoptionistostrikefirst.Thiswas Targetwillnotcontemplatewarinthenearterm.Inthe thesituationforJapanin1941.Itwasalsoaworryfor contextofRusso–Germanrelationsin1876,Bismarck U.S.PresidentKennedyduringtheCubanmissilecrisis. wasexplicitonthispoint.EvenatacitGermanthreatto HerecognizedthataU.S.threattodestroythemissiles Russia,hearguedinoneforeignpolicycircular,“could inCubainfourdayscouldresultinaSovietthreatto induce [the Tsar] to conclude flawed resolutions and takeactioninthreedays,aswellasfurtherescalations alliancesthatwouldbeverydisadvantageousforboth that could result in nuclear war in that time frame.34 sides.”36 A Franco-Russian alliance would have had In such military-strategic contexts, therefore, threat- consequences for Germany whether or not the Ger- makingonceagaininvolvesatrade-offsimilartothat mansbackeddownin1876.37 inExamples1and2.Threatsincreasethechancethata InternalandexternalbalancingonthepartofaTar- stategetswhatitwantswithrespecttotheissueathand, get negatively affects the Deterrer’s expected utility but can also create a danger that the threatened side from peace because it changes the balance of power will begin an unwanted military conflict. Once again, betweenthem.Ifthetwocountriesareinvolvedinan- thewillingnessoftheDeterrertoincursuchariskcan other crisis in the future, the weaker relative position causethethreattoconveyinformationtotheTarget. of the Deterrer will usually mean that it is less likely to get its way and more likely to fare badly if conflict Example 4 (Too Costly Deterrence). Faced with a should actually break out. Thus, if future crises are threat,theTargetmightconsideradoptingpoliciesthat of the sort described here or, for example, in Fearon woulddeterthethreateningstatefromattacking.Such (1994, 1997, 1998), Schultz (1998, 2001) or Slanchev activities, for instance mobilizing forces on a border, (2005),theDeterrer’sexpectedfutureutilitydecreases maybetoocostlytosustainforlong.Ratherthanmain- in the capabilities of its adversary.38 Although there tain a high level of preparation, therefore, the Target may be some contexts in which states are indifferent statemightprefertogotowar.Powell(1993)analyzesa totheincreasingcapabilitiesofanadversary,theywill strategiccontextthatleadstoasimilardynamic.From moreoftenviewsuchdevelopmentswithunderstand- the perspective of diplomatic signaling, if we think of ableconcern. theTarget’sdecisionasprecedingtheDeterrer’sdeci- Inthemodeldescribedbelow,weallowforthepos- siontogotowarorbackdown,thedangerofsuchan sibilitythattheTargetofathreat,havingmadecostly outcomeplaysasimilarroletotheriskofafirststrike preparationsforwar,mightchoosetobeginone.This inExample3. results in a concrete risk to the coercing state of ap- Example 5 (Resource Drain). Other reactions that pearingtomenacetheotherstate.Evenifthecoercing statesmayhavetothreatsalsohavelong-termconse- state backs down, the other state may make prepara- quencesforthethreateningstate.AstheSovietUnion tionsforwarandchoosetofightone.Moregenerally, didfollowingtheViennameeting,forinstance,astate however, we might think of the preparations of the may choose to drain the resources of another state in Target negatively affecting the coercing state’s utility order to get its way on a particular issue. As in Ex- becauseoftheeffectofpreparationsonthebalanceof amples1–4,theriskthatathreatenedstatewilladopt power, even when the coercing state backs down and such a course provides a disincentive to less resolved thesidesarenotinimmediateconflict. states to signal their willingness to engage in conflict oversuchacontentiousissue,makingcommunication possible. Example 6 (Mobilization). Whenathreatenedstate 36GrossePolitik,v.II,p.37. declines to back down and believes conflict likely, it 37Note that Russia elected not to attack or explicitly threaten mayelecttomobilizeitstroops.Withthecostofthemo- Austria-Hungary and that Russia also did not pursue an alliance withFranceatthistime.TheFranco-Russianalliancecameabout bilizationpaid,thechoicetogotowarlooksmoreat- 15 years later, after much intervening history, including Russia’s tractivetothemobilizedstatethanithadpreviously.35 declaredfrustrationwithGermanpolicyintheCongressofBerlin, Ifweallowforthepossibilitythatthemobilizedstate theAustro-Germanallianceof1879(directedpartly,andonlypartly willgotowar,weonceagainhaveatradeoffforstates secretly,againstRussia),andtheGermanfailuretorenewtheRein- suranceTreatywithRussiain1890. that consider threat-making, and this again results in 38Kydd(2005)isapartialexceptionbecauseincreasedrelativeca- thepossibilityofinformativesignals. pabilitiesofanadversarymayonoccasionmakeitmoretrustingand therebyresultinanetimprovementofathreateningstate’sexpected utility.Wecouldalsoconsidermultistateinteractionsinwhichthe 34MayandZelikow(2002,43–4). increasedcapabilitiesofanadversaryarebeneficial,butthereverse 35Slanchev(2005). isofcoursethemoreusualcase. 352 AmericanPoliticalScienceReview Vol.104,No.2 COMMUNICATION IN ANARCHY FIGURE1. StagesoftheGame We now turn to a formal model of coercion in which weallowforthepossibilitythatthreatenedstatesmay Deterrer decidetotakeactionsthatgobeyondstandingfirmor First stage Makes a costless threat or acquiesces backing down. In the model, there are two players, a Deterrer or threatening state and a Target or threat- Target enedstate.Theplayersareindexedbyi ∈I ≡{d,t}. Second stage Decides (1) whether to take the action in Themodelbelowisdifferentfrompreviousmodels question and (2) whether to prepare for in the international relations literature in two impor- conflict tant respects. First, the Target can chose to prepare for conflict when it believes it is sufficiently likely, or Deterrerand Target reorientitsforeignpolicyinotherwaysthatarehostile Third stage Each decides whether or not to go to war totheinterestsofthethreateningstate.IftheDeterrer takes a threatening posture, and if the Target’s costs of war are sufficiently low relative to the importance of the issue in question, the Target may be convinced actionsets,thesequenceofmoves,andplayerutilities totakethesesortsofmeasures.Second,inadditionto are all unchanged. If the initial communication stage the Deterrer having the option to attack the Target, is important at all, therefore, it is only because the theTargethastheopportunitytoattacktheDeterrer. Deterrer’s message affects the Target’s beliefs about Having prepared for war, the Target may opt for it the Deterrer’s intentions. This is possible in equilib- even if the Deterrer does not. Because the Target’s riumwhentheDeterrerisawareoftheconclusionsthe actions may lead to an outcome that is even worse Target will draw from a particular messaging strategy foranunresolvedDeterrerthanthepeacefuloutcome of the Deterrer (and thus also aware of how these wheretheTargetisundeterred,aresolvedDeterrerhas conclusions will likely affect its actions), and yet the anincentivetomakethreatsvis-a-visaparticularissue Deterrer’sbestoptionisneverthelesstousethatvery thatlessresolvedstateswouldbeunwillingtomake.As messagingstrategy.WerestrictattentiontotheDeter- Ishowbelow,thisdynamiccausesthreatstobemean- rer’sdecisiontothreatenornot,whichwerepresentby ingful even though no direct cost is associated with themessagem∈M≡{0,1}.Weshallinterpretm=1 makingthem.Onegeneralimplicationofthemodelis asapromisetotakeviolentactioniftheTarget takes thereforethatifstatesrespondatalltoperceptionsof a particular action, as well as a promise not to take other states’ intentions in formulating foreign policy, violentactionintheeventtheTargetcooperates. thenaverbalthreatmadebyonestateagainstanother, In the second stage, the Target has two decisions whetherinpublicorprivate,canconveyinformation. tomake:whethertotaketheactioninquestionornot Followingothermodelsintheinternationalrelations (choosinga ∈A ≡{0,1}),andwhethertopreparefor 1 1 literature,weshallsupposethereisabargainingspace conflict(choosinga ∈A ≡{0,1}).IftheTargettakes 2 2 X≡[0,1] such that the Deterrer prefers outcomes theaction,settinga =1,itunilaterallymovesthesta- 1 closer to 1 and the Target outcomes closer to 0. The tusquotos−(cid:1),towarditsidealpoint,where(cid:1)∈(0,s]. statusquoatthebeginningofthegameiss∈X.Players If the sides remain at peace, this will then be the bar- havevonNeumann–Morgensternutilityfunctionsde- gainingoutcome.Then,inthethirdstage,theDeterrer finedoveroutcomesinthebargainingspace,x∈X,and andTargetdecidewhetherornottogotowarbychoos- whatevercostsoffightingandpreparationforconflict ing r ∈R ≡{0,1}, where 1 represents conflict initia- i i theplayerspay,c.Specifically; tion. First, the Deterrer chooses r . If r =1, conflict i d d occurs;ifnot,theTargetchoosesr.Waroccursifeither u (x)=x−c t d d side opts to begin one; both sides must choose peace and toobtainthatoutcome.Weletrrepresentanindicator variable that equals 1 when the sides go to war and 0 ut(x)=1−x−ct. otherwise.Thus,r=1ifandonlyifri =1forsomei. Ifthesidesshouldfightawar,theDeterrerwillwin Thus, players have risk-neutral preferences over out- the war with common knowledge probability p(a ), comesinthebargainingspace.Weassumethisbecause 2 and is then able to choose its ideal outcome in the itsimplifiestheexpositionwithoutsubstantivelyalter- bargainingrangeX.Similarly,iftheTargetshouldwin ing the key points of the analysis. The costs players the war, it may choose its ideal bargaining outcome. pay in the game, c and c, will be defined below as d t Weassumethatoneofthetwosideswillwinthewar. functionsofothervariablestoreflecttheoutcomesof When the Target prepares, the chances that it wins a player actions during the game, so that, for instance, warmayincrease:1−p(1)≥1−p(0)⇔p(0)≥p(1). the players do not pay a cost of conflict when no war WeshallmodeltheTarget’scostsofwarandprepa- is fought. (They may still pay a cost of preparing for rationasconsistingofseveralcomponents.Ifthesides conflict,however.) go to war, the Target’s war costs are η ∈[η,η]≡(cid:3), Figure 1 depicts the stages of the game. It begins t t t t withtheDeterrer’sattempttoinfluencetheTargetby whereη >0andηtisprivateinformationoftheTarget. t sendingacostlesssignal.WhatevermessagetheDeter- IftheTargetchoosestoprepare,itincurssomeprepa- rersends,thegamethatfollowsispreciselythesame; ration costs, k ≥0, whether or not a war is fought, t 353 DiplomaticCalculusinAnarchy May2010 but reduces its costs of conflict by β ∈[0,η). Thus, Deterrer options in the first stage × 4 Target options t preparations imply an increase in the sunk cotsts that inthesecondstage×3terminalnodesineachStage3 theTargetpayswhetherornotitgoestowarandade- branch). creaseinthevariablecostsassociatedwiththeconflict Tomakethesignalingprobleminteresting,weshall itself.(Wemakenoassumptionabouttheneteffectof make severalassumptions about payoffs.First,weas- preparationsontheoverallcostofconflict.)Thus, sume the Deterrer prefers not to go to war when the Targetcomplieswithitswishesbynottakingtheaction, ct(a2,r,ηt)=kta2+r(ηt−βta2). and that there is a possibility the Deterrer would be willingtofightiftheTargetdidnotprepareandtookthe We take a similar approach to modeling the Deter- actioninquestionandapossibilitytheDeterrerwould rer’s costs, but we suppose the Deterrer has already notbewillingtofightinthiscase.Thisisequivalentto madeanyrelevantpreparationsforconflictanddonot modeltheDeterrer’schoiceofpreparationsexplicitly. s>p(0)−c (1,η )>s−(cid:1)>p(0)−c (1,η ). (1) For simplicity, we suppose the Target’s preparations d d d d do not affect the Deterrer’s costs of conflict—only its Second, we assume the Target prefers peace when it probabilityofvictory.Thus, takes the action in question and does not prepare to its most preferred war outcome and that there is a cd(r,ηd)=rηd, possibility the Target would prefer a prepared war to where η ∈[η ,η ]≡(cid:3) , η >0, and η is private in- accepting the initial status quo and a possibility the d d d d d d Targetpreferstheinitialstatusquotoapreparedwar. formationoftheDeterrer.Bothsourcesofprivatein- Thisisequivalentto formation are independently distributed according to thecontinuous,strictlyincreasing,commonknowledge 1−s+(cid:1)>1−p(1)−c(1,1,η)>1−s>1−p(1) t distributionfunctions(cid:5) . t Thus,theDeterrer’suηtiilitydependsonthebargain- −c(1,1,η). (2) t t ing outcome, whether the players go to war, and the Similarly to other models of coercion, these assump- Deterrer’s type, whereas the Target’s utility depends tionsimplythattheDeterrer’smostpreferredoutcome on thosesamefactors and alsoon whether or not the occurs when the Target complies with the Deterrer’s Targetchoosestoprepare.Therefore,weshallwritethe players’utilityfunctionsasu (x,r,η ):X×R×(cid:3) → wishesbynottakingtheactioninquestion(andalsonot R and u(x,r,η,a ):X×Rd×(cid:3) ×dA →R.39 Subdsti- attacking the Deterrer). The Target’s most preferred t t 2 t 2 outcome occurs when it takes the action in question, tutingthecostfunctionsintotheplayerutilityfunctions does not prepare for conflict, and the Deterrer does yieldsthefollowingutilitiesforpeace: notattack.Playersarewillingtogotowarwhenthey u (s,0,η )=s−(cid:1)a consider the costs of war to be low relative to their d d 1 evaluation of the issues at stake and their chances of ut(s,0,ηt,a2)=1−s+(cid:1)a1−kta2. victory.41 An example of parameters satisfying these assumptionsisshowninFigure3.Thefigurealsorepre- Similarly,theplayers’expectedutilitiesforwarare40 sentsthemodelintermssimilartothoseusedinFearon Eu (r=1|a ,η )=p(a )−c (1,η )=p(a )−η (1995)andcanusefullybecomparedtoFigure1ofthat d 2 d 2 d d 2 d paper. Eu(r=1|a ,η)=1−p(a )−c(a ,1,η) ThepreparationsoftheTargetmayormaynothave t 2 t 2 t 2 t aneffectontheTarget’scostsofconflictandtheplay- =1−p(a )−η +βa −ka . 2 t t 2 t 2 ers’ probability of victory. We shall say that prepara- tions are effective if and only if k >0, p(0)>p(1), The formal structure of the game is shown in Fig- t and [(1−p(1))−(1−p(0))]>k −β. The last con- ure2.WhicheverchoicetheDeterrermakesinthefirst t t dition states that the Target prefers a prepared to an stage, the Target has the four Stage 2 options shown unpreparedwar,orinotherwords,thattheoverallin- in the figure. Whichever of these the Target opts for, creaseintheTarget’scostsasaresultofpreparation(if thesameStage3structureshownfollows.Asthefigure preparingdoesinvolveanetincreaseincosts)mustbe shows, the players’ utilities over the Stage 3 terminal outweighed by the benefit of the increased likelihood nodeoutcomesdependontheTarget’sStage2choice. of victory. We shall say preparations are ineffective if Thefullgametree,therefore,has24terminalnodes(2 k =β =0 and p(0)=p(1).42 Note that in Figure 3, t t preparationsareeffective. 39NotethatalthoughtheTarget’schoiceofpreparationdoesnot affecttheDeterrer’sutilitydirectly,itdoesaffectthelikelihoodof outcomes(victoryanddefeat)overwhichtheDeterrerhasdifferent 41Here,playersareuncertainabouteachother’scostsofconflict. preferences. Wemightalsoconsideramodelinwhichplayersareuncertainabout 40So long as player utility functions are bounded, we can de- theimportanceoftheissueinquestiontotheotherside.Amodelof rive these expected utilities without assuming risk neutrality over thisform,whichgeneratesresultssimilartothosepresentedbelow, bargainingoutcomesbysettingud(1,0,ηd)=ut(0,0,ηt,0)=1and canbefoundinTrager(2007,chap.3). ud(0,0,ηd)=ut(1,0,ηt,0)=0 without loss of generality. Because 42Theeffective/ineffectivedistinctiondoesnotexhaustallregionsof thesides’warutilitiesdonotdependonwhichsidechooseswarin theparameterspace.Weshallnotanalyzecaseswherepreparations thethirdstage,theorderofplayerchoicesinthisstagewillhaveno impacttheprobabilityofvictorybutarenotcostlyorarecostlybut substantiveimpactontheanalysis. donotaffectthechancesofvictory. 354 AmericanPoliticalScienceReview Vol.104,No.2 FIGURE2. FormalStructure 1stStage 2ndStage Deterrer Target (Don’t (Threaten) Threaten) 3rdStage Deterrer (Don’t (Attack) Attack) Target (Don’t (Attack) Attack) FIGURE3. PlayerUtilitiesSatisfyingModelAssumptions High cost Target’s Low cost Deterrer’s expected utility from expected utility from a conflict when the Target does not prepare prepared conflict High cost Deterrer’s expected utility from conflict when the Low cost Target’s expected Target does not prepare utility from a prepared conflict Deterrer’s peace utility if Target’s peace utility if it takes the Target takes the action the action and does not prepare DDetterrer’’s peace uttiilliitty TTargett’’s peace uttiilliitty at the status quo at the status quo 355 DiplomaticCalculusinAnarchy May2010 Equilibria with Ineffective Preparations over the issue in question than the Target had previ- ously thought. (We shall see that, in this equilibrium, We can now ask whether, in such a strategic context, thissuppositioniscorrect.)RealizingthattheDeterrer theTargetcanlearnfromthecostlesssignalssentbythe is more likely to follow through, the Target is more Deterrer.Commonly,incheaptalkgames,signalerscan likely to decide that the issue is not worth risking a conveyinformationthatdoesnotinfluencethecourse fight over and to back down. If the Target’s costs of ofevents.Ifcommunicatedinformationwillnotinflu- war are sufficiently low relative to the value it places ence actions, it makes little difference to the receiver on the issue, however, the Target may decide not to oftheinformationwhetherornotheorshebelievesit back down and to make costly preparations for war. to be true. In these equilibria, signals are informative TheTarget’sdecisionmaybeadifficultonebecauseon butnotinfluential.Weshallfocusonwhetherequilib- the one hand, preparations such as alliances, building ria with influential signals can exist. In such equilib- arms,orstrikingfirstmayprovideadditional security, ria,therearesignalsthatincreasetheprobabilitythat butontheotherhand,suchactionscarrytheirownad- the Target both does not take the action in question ditionalcosts.BecausetheTarget’spreparationsaffect (a =0) and does not attack the Deterrer (r =0). 1 t itsowncalculations about therelativebenefits ofwar Let q(m)=Pr(a =0,r =0|m) be the probability t 1 t andpeace,havingprepared,itmaydecidetoattackthe theTarget’sstrategysatisfiesa =0,r =0givensignal 1 t Deterrer. m induced by the players’ strategies and beliefs in a In the first stage, in deciding whether or not to particularequilibrium. threaten,theDeterrerunderstandsthesedynamics.If theDeterrer’scostsofwararehighrelativetothevalue Definition. Anequilibriumisinfluentialifthereexist itplacesontheissueinquestion,theneventhoughby signalsm(cid:6) (cid:7)=m(cid:6)(cid:6) playedwithpositiveprobabilityinthe threateningitstandsabetterchanceofgettingitsway, equilibriumsuchthatq(m(cid:6))>q(m(cid:6)(cid:6)). it will not be willing to make a threat. This benefit to t t threatening does not outweigh the increased risk of a IftheTarget’spreparationsdonotaffectitsprobabil- breach in relations with the Target and the attendant ityofvictoryortheplayers’costsofconflict,theDeter- increased risk of a costly conflict. Thus, the Deterrer rer’scostlesssignalscannotconveyinformationtothe willonlybewillingtothreatenifitisrelativelyhighly TargetinawaythatinfluencestheTarget’sactions;no resolved.This,inturn,impliesthatoursuppositionthat influential equilibrium exists. If preparations have no theTargetlearnsfromthethreatiscorrect.44 effectonplayerutilitiesoveroutcomes,thenthismodel Aprincipalobstacletoinfluentialcheaptalksignals is very similar to others in the international relations is the incentive that unresolved types have to mimic literature.Insuchcases,thereasoninformativesignal- the signals sent by resolved types. In other models in ingisimpossibleiswellunderstood: thereisabenefit the literature, unresolved types have every incentive to being thought willing to fight and no drawback.43 tomimicbecausetheycanalwaysbackdownanden- Therefore,theDeterreralwaystriestosendthesignal sure themselves of an outcome they like just as well that will most convince the Target of its resolve, but astheoneinwhichtheymakenothreat.Inthemodel because that signal is sent in every case regardless of described here, however, there may be a danger that whether it corresponds to the truth of the matter, the the Target will respond to a threat by preparing for Targetlearnsnothingfromit.Proposition1expresses war and, having done so, launch a strike of its own. thisformally. When this is possible, low-resolve types face a risk in misrepresenting their levels of resolve by mimicking Proposition 1. If preparations are ineffective, no in- thebehaviorofhigh-resolvetypes.45 fluential perfect Bayesian equilibrium exists (in pure strategies). 44As described, the logic mayappear circular. But note thatit is circular only in the way that the logic of any truly strategic Nash Influential Equilibria equilibrium(whereplayers’optimalactionsaredependentuponthe actionsofotherplayers)mustbecircular. When preparations have an effect, in some cases in- 45Inthemodel,theTargetcantakeanactionthatshiftsthebar- fluential equilibria exist in the model. To understand gainingoutcomeinitsfavorby(cid:1)ornottakethataction.Asaresult, theTargetsometimespreferstogotowarbecausetheshiftinthe how these equilibria function intuitively, suppose the bargainingoutcomeisnotsufficienttocauseafullypreparedTarget Deterrer makes a threat and the Target learns from topreferpeace.IfitwerefeasiblefortheTargettotakeanaction thisthattheDeterrerismorelikelywillingtogotowar unilaterallythatmovedthebargainingoutcomesufficientlyfurther towardtheTarget’sidealpointfollowingpreparationsforconflict, however,andifweallowedforthispossibilityinthemodel,then the Target would never choose war in equilibrium and influential 43Thelogichereisonlyslightlymorecomplicatedbecause,unlike signalingwouldbeimpossible.Theassumptionofafixedactionne- thesituationinmostmodelsintheliterature,theTargetalsodecides gotiatedoverbythestatesisprobablyreasonableinsomecasesand whetherornottogotowarlateron.TheproofofProposition1must notinothers.Evenifweweretochangethemodeltoallowforan also demonstrate, therefore, that no influential equilibrium exists increasein(cid:1)followingpreparations,however,influentialsignaling inwhichresolved,threatenedTargetsdeclinetotaketheactionin wouldstillbepossibleifwerelaxedtheassumptionofriskneutrality question,therebycommittingthemselvestofightingawar.Ifsuch overbargainingoutcomes.Moregenerally,foralternatebargaining adynamicwerepossible,lessresolvedDeterrersmightdeclineto protocols,influentialsignalingwouldbepossibleaslongasTarget threaten,resultingininfluentialsignaling.AstheproofofProposi- typeswithhigherexpectedvaluesforwartakeactionsthatimplya tion1intheAppendixdemonstrates,however,thiscannotoccur. strictlyhigherlikelihoodofconflict.Thisisanassumptionoraresult 356

Description:
Diplomatic Calculus in Anarchy: How Communication Matters. ROBERT F. TRAGER .. sult in a crash that has negative consequences for both employer and termining the course of events in a rationalist frame- work. Macro-level
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.