Democratic Incongruities Representative Democracy in Britain David Judge Democratic Incongruities Democratic Incongruities Representative Democracy in Britain David Judge Emeritus Professor of Politics, University of Strathclyde © David Judge 2014 Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 2014 978-0-230-31446-7 All rights reserved. No reproduction, copy or transmission of this publication may be made without written permission. No portion of this publication may be reproduced, copied or transmitted save with written permission or in accordance with the provisions of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, or under the terms of any licence permitting limited copying issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency, Saffron House, 6–10 Kirby Street, London EC1N 8TS. Any person who does any unauthorized act in relation to this publication may be liable to criminal prosecution and civil claims for damages. The author has asserted his right to be identified as the author of this work in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. First published 2014 by PALGRAVE MACMILLAN Palgrave Macmillan in the UK is an imprint of Macmillan Publishers Limited, registered in England, company number 785998, of Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire RG21 6XS. Palgrave Macmillan in the US is a division of St Martin’s Press LLC, 175 Fifth Avenue, New York, NY 10010. Palgrave Macmillan is the global academic imprint of the above companies and has companies and representatives throughout the world. Palgrave® and Macmillan® are registered trademarks in the United States, the United Kingdom, Europe and other countries. ISBN 978-1-349-33969-3 ISBN 978-1-137-31729-2 (eBook) DOI 10.1057/9781137317292 This book is printed on paper suitable for recycling and made from fully managed and sustained forest sources. Logging, pulping and manufacturing processes are expected to conform to the environmental regulations of the country of origin. A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. Typeset by MPS Limited, Chennai, India. Contents Preface and Acknowledgements vi 1 Democratic Incongruities: Old Models and New Perspectives 1 2 The ‘Problem’ of the People 25 3 The ‘Problem’ of Representational Transmission of Power 47 4 The ‘Problem’ of Elected Representatives 77 5 The ‘Problem’ of Representative Government 107 6 The ‘Problem’ of Citizen Participation 135 7 The ‘Problem’ of ‘Post-’: Post-Representative, Post-Parliamentary, Post-Democracy 172 References 195 Index 223 v Preface and Acknowledgements ‘Know your audience’ should be the guiding dictum for all authors. In the case of this book the audience is known and apparent: it is me. Or, to avoid accusations of being self-indulgent, I should make it clear that the audience is ‘people like me’ who want to understand how representative democracy works in Britain. There are already a multitude of books and articles that tell us how it works, most of which are intensely critical of the ‘democratic deficit’ or the degree of ‘democratic drift’ observ- able in Britain; and most of which point to a fundamental mismatch, an incongruity, between democratic theory and political practice. In essence, British democracy does not work as a standard account of rep- resentative democracy stipulates that it should. Even in its own terms there is a series of mismatches between the prescriptions of that account and routine political practice: citizens would be expected, as the essence of democratic engagement, to participate in elections, in contrast to the actual propensity of significant numbers of the British citizenry not to engage even in this minimal level of participation; political parties would serve as representational transmitters of power from voters to governors rather than the other way round; representative institutions would represent the ‘shared experiences’ of the various peoples of the political nation and internalise the values of political equality, instead of institutionalising limited representativeness and sustaining represen- tational inequalities; governments would be authorised by, and held accountable to, elected representatives (and ultimately to the electorate) rather than being enmeshed in governance networks insulated from electoral representative processes. If the starting point for understanding is thus taken to be a ‘stand- ard model’ of representative democracy, then that model does not get us very far, as there is a distinct lack of fit between such an account and political practice in Britain. (The focus of attention in this book is Britain and its constituent countries of England, Scotland, and Wales. Given the differences and complexities of politics in Northern Ireland the following analysis only mentions Northern Ireland when it is spe- cifically appropriate to do so in the context of the United Kingdom state (UK). In turn, the term UK is used, rather than Britain, when the legal and constitutional entity of ‘the state’ is being referred to). Yet one of the incongruities to be analysed in this book is why, in spite of evidence vi Preface and Acknowledgements vii to the contrary, UK governments continue to propound such a standard account as ‘the official model’ of representative democracy in Britain. Clearly, alternative models have been available. For most of the period since the acceptance of representative democracy as a viable mode of government in Western Europe, political theorists have illu- minated the democratic deficiencies of that state-form. However, in recent years there have been significant developments of democratic theory, with political theorists pursuing, vigorously and productively, a ‘representative turn’ in the conceptualisation of democracy. In particular, theories of legitimate representative democracy have been developed out of a conceptual separation of democracy from repre- sentation, and representation from election. The former separation leads towards participatory and deliberative forms of citizen engage- ment beyond formal representative institutions; the latter separation points in the direction of non-electoral modes of representation beyond electoral representation. In each direction new theories have helped to locate complex ecologies of representation in the broader ecosystem of democracy. Moreover, several of these theories have inspired ‘democratic innovations’ designed as practical enhancements of representative democracy. And, despite continuing to subscribe to the ‘standard account’ of representative democracy, successive British governments have sought to incorporate some of these innovations into the practice of British governance. To what effect, and how incongruously, will be examined in later chapters. But if the target audience of this book is those political scientists, political theorists, political practitioners, and students of politics more generally, who want to know how representative democracy works in Britain, then what is the ‘distinctive selling point’ of this book? There are a host of empirical analyses that show that democracy in Britain is deficient, there are a plethora of contending analytical models – of network governance, multi-level governance, differentiated polity, asymmetric power, post-parliamentary governance – that claim to provide more compelling explanations of how it actually works, and there are many elaborate theories – based on deliberative or participatory premises – as to how it should work. So: why yet another book tramping over familiar terrain? My answer is short: there are a number of outstanding concerns left untouched or unresolved in many existing analyses of British repre- sentative democracy and which are worthy of attention. I use ‘concern’ here in two senses: first, as a matter of importance and interest, and second as a matter of anxiety or unease. viii Preface and Acknowledgements In the first sense, my concern is with the conjunction of two discrete concepts – ‘representation’ and ‘democracy’ – into ‘representative democracy’. This is a matter of importance and interest, not least because representative democracy is often treated as an oxymoron. Whereas ‘democracy’ privileges popular participation and inclusion in decision-making processes, ‘representation’ posits the absence and exclusion of ‘the people’ from decision-making in conceiving of re-presentation as ‘mak[ing] present again … in some sense something which is nevertheless not present literally or in fact’ (Pitkin 1967:8–9 original emphasis). This inclusion–exclusion paradox is at the core of representative democracy and has been of concern to me throughout my academic career and has surfaced in some of my earlier books. More importantly, it has also become of importance for new waves of demo- cratic theorists in their ‘reconceptualisations’ of representation and their recognition that political representation is, indeed, as much about exclusion as inclusion, and that electoral representation simultaneously separates and links representatives from the represented. Yet, even if direct popular inclusion is episodic, and confined to the moment of election, the intervals between elections nonetheless provide political spaces which allow for exclusion to be mitigated in continuing processes of mediated representation. In this sense, political representation can be conceived as systemic, encompassing not only electoral processes and institutions but also non-electoral processes, and ‘informal’ or ‘self- authorised representation’. At the point of intersection between mediated and unmediated participatory processes, and between electoral and non-electoral representation, the fundamental question is posed of the compatibility – both ideationally and practically – of representation with democracy. This question provides an organising thread throughout the book. It is commonplace to treat this question rhetorically and to answer affirma- tively that unmediated participation and non-electoral representation are simple complements and supplements for the mediated participation and electoral representation of representative democracy. In the analysis that follows in this book, however, a more sceptical approach is taken in the discussion of the democratic enhancement of representative democ- racy. What particularly concerns me (in terms of interest and impor- tance) is how notions of, and schemes for, the democratic enhancement of representation serve to alter the legitimating frame provided by elections in representative democracy, and do so by inhering discordant legitimation claims into a reconceived conjunction of representation and democracy. In this process, electoral claims come to be destabilised Preface and Acknowledgements ix while non-electoral participatory claims are simultaneously defused. A mismatch, an incongruity, is thus to be found at the theoretical core of reconceptualisations of representative democracy. My other concern, in the second sense of unease, is that these theoretical incongruities come to find reflection in the mismatched practice of ‘democratic innovations’. This concern links to an extensive audience that has already been assembled to voice anxiety about citizens’ distrust, disconnect, disengagement, and disappointment with the processes and institutions of representative democracy in Britain. While these anxieties are not exclusive to Britain, they are more pronounced and more stri- dently expressed in reflecting the deeper levels of disenchantment with formal politics in Britain than in many other European representative democracies. One powerful explanation of this negativity is that it arises from a profound sense of popular frustration with, and disem- powerment within, the existing system of representative democracy. In seeking to redress the perceived deficiencies of representative democracy, a number of ‘democratic innovations’ – rooted in deliberative democ- racy, or direct democracy, or increasingly e-democracy – have been implemented by successive British governments. The concern examined within this book is that the democratic potential of these innovations becomes transmuted in their accommodation within a legitimating frame provided by electoral representation. Theories of unmediated citizen engagement become entangled in mediated processes and insti- tutions of representative democracy. My concern is with the assumption that ‘democratic innovations’ simply complement and supplement, and so enhance, representative democracy. However, the interaction between mediated and unmediated forms of citizen engagement also holds the alternative negative potential that, in the process of enhancement, both participation and representation may be altered and diminished in incongruous ways. Before reaching this end-point in the analysis, however, other more immediately pressing concerns need to be investigated. As noted above, there are many observable mismatches and incompatibilities between theory and practice. In part, this ‘jarring effect’ reflects incongruities within a standard account of representative democracy itself. Whereas the standard model is predicated upon a simple principal–agent relation- ship between individual representatives and individual citizens; such an unmediated relationship comes to depend upon mediated relationships for its institutional realisation – through ‘constituencies’ designed to organise individual voters into collectivities (based upon territory, or social class, or gender, or ethnicity), and political organisations formed x Preface and Acknowledgements around those collectivities (political parties, organised groups, and social movements). How those constituencies are constituted and how they are mediated becomes of prime concern both in terms of inter- est and of unease. Equally, a standard account, while adhering to the value of political equality, in the notion of equally weighted votes in elections, has no intrinsic requirement of representational equality for all citizens. Yet the search for greater representational equality, through strategies to promote descriptive representation and to link substantive representation to the outcomes of those strategies, brings with it further incongruities. No book on representative democracy in Britain could avoid raising concerns about the ‘Westminster model’. This is a model that has come to provide a short-hand descriptor for a distinctive institutional structure which captures the representative and responsible elements of representative democracy yet transmutes those elements into a particular ‘power-concentrating’ form of government. In itself this transmutation is of concern. Yet a further concern has attracted the attention of a broad and critical audience of political scientists, consti- tutional lawyers, and political practitioners – who are all keen to point out the extent of divergence between the ideational foundations of the Westminster model and the practice of modern British governance. The point of intersection between this orthodox and longstanding concern and the specific concerns of this book is to be found, however, in the incongruous proposition that a model of transmuted democratic repre- sentation that no longer fits political practice nonetheless still provides a legitimating frame for state decision-makers. This stacking of incon- gruity upon incongruity is sufficient to attract concern, in terms of both interest and unease, but it is the stacking of a further incongruity onto this already teetering analytical construction that elevates ‘concern’ to academic ‘disorientation’: the legitimating framework deployed by decision makers to authorise their actions is derived from the ‘standard’ account – the pre-mutated version – of democratic representation rather than the mutated version in the Westminster model that contemporary governments seek to defend. When critics of the Westminster model call upon governments to provide a new narrative or theory of govern- ment beyond the existing legitimating frame they are, therefore, asking either for an alternative to representative democracy, as conceived in the standard model, or for the acceptance of ‘reconceptualisations’ of democracy which still, in their various representative forms, presume a frame of electoral representation. Incongruous solutions thus come to be posited for incongruous ‘problems’.