ebook img

Critical Pedagogy and Marx, Vygotsky and Freire: Phenomenal Forms and Educational Action Research PDF

166 Pages·2016·2.16 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Critical Pedagogy and Marx, Vygotsky and Freire: Phenomenal Forms and Educational Action Research

Critical Pedagogy and Marx, Vygotsky and Freire Also by Luis S. Villacañas de Castro GIRO COPERNICANO Y CIENCIAS SOCIALES Critical Pedagogy and Marx, Vygotsky and Freire Phenomenal Forms and Educational Action Research Luis S. Villacañas de Castro Assistant Professor, University of Valencia, Spain © Luis S. Villacañas de Castro 2016 Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 2016 978-1-137-56243-2 All rights reserved. No reproduction, copy or transmission of this publication may be made without written permission. No portion of this publication may be reproduced, copied or transmitted save with written permission or in accordance with the provisions of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, or under the terms of any licence permitting limited copying issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency, Saffron House, 6–10 Kirby Street, London EC1N 8TS. Any person who does any unauthorized act in relation to this publication may be liable to criminal prosecution and civil claims for damages. The author has asserted his right to be identified as the author of this work in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. First published 2016 by PALGRAVEMACMILLAN Palgrave Macmillan in the UK is an imprint of Macmillan Publishers Limited, registered in England, company number 785998, of Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire RG21 6XS. Palgrave Macmillan in the US is a division of St Martin’s Press LLC, 175 Fifth Avenue, New York, NY 10010. Palgrave Macmillan is the global academic imprint of the above companies and has companies and representatives throughout the world. Palgrave® and Macmillan® are registered trademarks in the United States, the United Kingdom, Europe and other countries. ISBN 978-1-349-55762-2 ISBN 978-1-137-56244-9 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-1-137-56244-9 This book is printed on paper suitable for recycling and made from fully managed and sustained forest sources. Logging, pulping and manufacturing processes are expected to conform to the environmental regulations of the country of origin. A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Names: Villacañas de Castro, Luis Sebastián, 1982– Title: Critical pedagogy and Marx, Vygotsky, and Freire: phenomenal f orms and educational action research / Luis S. Villacañas de Castro, Assistant Professor, University of Valencia, Spain. Description: New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2015. | Includes bibliographical references. Identifiers: LCCN 2015025950 | ISBN 9781137562432 (hardback) Subjects: LCSH: Critical pedagogy. | Marx, Karl, 1818–1883—Influence. | Vygotski˜ı , L. S. (Lev Semenovich), 1896–1934—Influence. | Freire, Paulo, 1921–1997—Influence. | BISAC: EDUCATION / Educational Psychology. | EDUCATION / Secondary. | EDUCATION / Philosophy & Social Aspects. | PHILOSOPHY / Movements / Phenomenology. Classification: LCC LC196 .V55 2015 | DDC 370.11/5—dc23 LC record available at http://lccn.loc.gov/2015025950 Typeset by MPS Limited, Chennai, India. Contents Introduction: The Pedagogical Obstacle of the Phenomenal Forms 1 Part I Marx, Freud, and Pedagogy 1 Beyond The Ignorant Schoolmaster: On Education, Marxism, and Psychoanalysis 23 Part II Epistemology, Critical Pedagogy, and Liberal Principles 2 The Pedagogical Problem: Vygotsky’s Encounter with Marx’s Phenomenal Forms 45 3 The Pedagogical Solution: Freire’s Critical Pedagogy and Social Democracy 67 Part III Theory and Practice of Educational Action Research 4 The Critical Potential of John Elliott’s LiberalPedagogy 93 5 A Practical Case of Participatory Meta-Action Research 115 References 146 Index 159 v Introduction: The Pedagogical Obstacle of the Phenomenal Forms An ongoing project This book is a further development from a previous one, published only in Spanish, whose title can be translated asThe Copernican turn and the social sciences (Villacañas de Castro, 2013). It was a philo- sophical work relating to a general epistemological problem lying at the heart of the social and natural sciences. On the other hand, the present volume is firmly rooted in pedagogy. This difference reflects the professional journey that I have made in the meantime, from being a Graduate Student at a Faculty of Philosophy to becoming a member of staff at a Faculty of Education, where I currently lecture and carry out research. Despite the various shifts brought about by this transition, an underlying interest has remained throughout and inspired me to write this volume. This is why I consider both books to be part of a single, ongoing project. Accordingly, the first aim of this introduction is to make the nature—the essence—of the continuity I am alluding to clear, an objective which cannot be satisfied without summarizing (no matter how briefly) The Copernican turn and the social sciences. This summary should prepare the reader for the original contribution that I make in the following five chapters. Accordingly, the first three sections of this introduction present some of the ideas developed in that earlier work, while the last three begin to deal with those developed in this one. Let us start with my previous book. My aim then was to analyze a problem which I considered to be no less than an epistemological mystery, or enigma, presented by those revolutionary theories which, 1 2 Critical Pedagogy and Marx, Vygotsky and Freire in my view, had enacted a Copernican turn in the realm of the sciences. Four scientific theories fell within the scope of that concept: Sigmund Freud’s psychoanalysis, Karl Marx’s contribution to sociology, Neo- Darwinism (the paradigm which ensued when Darwin’s and Mendel’s discoveries in biology were articulated), and relativity theory in the field of physics. I assume readers possess some basic notions of them, although this is not necessary to understand this project. I defined these Copernican turns as scientific discoveries whose revolutionary nature consisted precisely of the fact that they had contributed new knowledge about particular objects (the psychic apparatus, the mode of production, the natural habitat, and the universe) but also about the position that human beings held in relation to those realities, insofar as they formed part of them. Actually, an individual crystal- lized where these four objects intersected. A Copernican turn thus involved two kinds of knowledge: about the objectt and the subjectt; knowledge about specific realities; and also new knowledge about how human beings should understand themselves in relation to those four objects. All four Copernican turns revealed that human beings were neither independent nor separate from the realities which they studied, but were inscribed in them, embedded in their materiality. Instead of downplaying the objective quality of outside reality in order to stress its subjective side, this argument focused on the objective quality of dimensions to which the human being had normally attributed a subjective character. Copernican turns Many consequences unfolded from this ontological argument. For instance, the scrutiny which scientists professed to exercise with neutrality and detachment suddenly seemed to be epistemologically unsound, since it developed from within the subject matter under analysis. The ‘positivistic myth of the researcher as detached secretary to the universe’, as Kemmis and McTaggart (2005, p. 570) described it, forcefully crumbled down. At the same time, dimensions which humanity had always interpreted as evidence of its own exceptional mode of existence in the world (of its own transcendence from the natural plane) were suddenly revealed to be connected to objective, material developments. As one may imagine, all sorts of sentiments were stirred against those discoveries. Although he did not refer to Introduction 3 them as Copernican turns (and left Marx’s theory out of his analysis), at one point in his later work Sigmund Freud described the impact of these theories (including his own, psychoanalysis) as inflicting narcissistic blows to humanity, an expression which he pulled from his own theory, and through which he attempted to stress their traumatic character. ‘The universal narcissism of men, their self- love’, Freud (1917) said, ‘has up to the present suffered three severe blows from the researches of science […]: the cosmological one […], the biological blow to human narcissism [… and], the third blow, which is psychological in nature, [and] probably the most wounding’ (pp. 3612–13). It seemed as if science had unveiled a kind of knowl- edge that challenged the privileged position that human individuals had presumed to hold in history and in the universe. Freud was not the first to identify this resistance, of course. Darwin, Einstein, Marx—all of them had to face fanatical opposition to their discoveries. Centuries before them, Galileo even experienced danger when he bore out Copernicus’ heliocentric cosmological model, the first Copernican turn proper and the discovery which set in motion a process that Einstein would draw to an end. In the 18th century, philosopher Immanuel Kant approached this experience again from a philosophical perspective. His observations on Copernicus’ original hypothesis of the Earth orbiting around the Sun formulated, for the first time, the structure of Copernican turns. On account of the preci- sion of his commentary, I have always kept it at the heart of my own theoretical developments: We have here the same case as with the first thought of Copernicus, who, not being able to get on in the explanation of the movements of the heavenly bodies, as long as he assumed that all the stars turned round the spectator, tried whether he could not succeed better, by assuming the spectator to be turning round, and the stars to be at rest. (Kant, 2001, p. 12) As I have mentioned, centuries later, Marx, Darwin, Freud, and Einstein became perfectly aware of the cognitive and affective conse- quences effected by their turns. They anticipated the resistance which their contemporary and future generations would per force undergo, as people tried to accommodate their commonsensical, superficial impressions to the ideas implied by these scientific breakthroughs—or 4 Critical Pedagogy and Marx, Vygotsky and Freire more concretely, as they attempted to see themselves in terms of the concrete dynamics which ruled their own divided mental apparatus, the mode of production, the natural habitat, and the surrounding universe in which they worked, reproduced, and lived. Since then, the only factor which has proven capable of attenuating the enmity raised against these theories has been downright ignorance, lack of acquaintance with them—something which could actually be interpreted as a kind of resistance in itself. Yet neither Freud, Marx, Darwin nor Einstein developed a profound epistemological reflec- tion on this topic. None of them made the leap from a scientific to a meta-scientific plane of thought. This being the case, when I started to analyze the nature of Copernican turns, I had to come up with my own terminology and ways of illustrating my argument. This is not to say that I found no guidance in other authors; for example, I resorted constantly to the works of Thomas Kuhn (his theorization of paradigm shifts) and Louis Althusser (his analysis of Marx’s change of problematic), among others. But in the end it was Kant’s previous quote which proved to be the most determining influence on my own understanding, and set the terms of my discussion. Following suit from it, I ended up describing Copernican turns as if, at some point in the course of a scientific investigation, the observer had gradually started to question his or her own subjective position vis- à-vis the object of inquiry; and as if, in addition, this revision had ended up becoming instrumental for discovering something radically new in the nature of the object. The subjective and the objective dimensions of this epistemological process were both integrated into my perspective, since they characterize a revolutionary scientific development that can, in fact, only be explained as a dialogue or an interaction between the two. Let me bring the discussion to a more general plane, by remind- ing the reader that it is only when we know exactly which place we occupy in reality that we can establish with certainty how much more our concrete perceptions owe to the essence of the real objects we are observing than to our local position. What is more, there is no question that some vantage points simply make it impossible for the real facts of a situation to be accessed and truthfully conveyed by our impressions. Indeed, this idea is closely tied to the Copernican breakthrough, for it was only when these scientific observers were able to know themselves—to know humanity—fully that they could

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.