ebook img

Context and Cognition: Interpreting Complex Behavior PDF

160 Pages·2004·0.439 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Context and Cognition: Interpreting Complex Behavior

Context and Cognition Foxall Interpreting Complex Behavior Context and Cognition Gordon R. Foxall Interpreting Complex Behavior While the general wisdom has it that behaviorism is dead, it not only survives but is intellectually active in areas such as psychological theory, the analysis of language and cognition, and behavioral economics. It is a successful, albeit lim- ited, source of behavioral science. Its chief difficulty arises when its practitioners look out from their laboratory windows and attempt to explain the complexities of human behavior that will never be amenable to direct experimental investigation. C Behavior analysis has failed to establish a methodology of interpretation to deal o n fully with such complexity. The message of this essay is that it cannot do so with- t e out embracing intentional explanation in the form of an interpretive overlay that x t plugs the gaps in its explanations of life beyond the lab. a n d Gordon Foxall is Distinguished Research Professor at Cardiff University, Wales, UK C o g n Chapter 1 Intentional Behavior it i o Chapter 2 Radical Behaviorist Interpretation n Chapter 3 The Intentional Stance Chapter 4 The Contextual Stance Chapter 5 Intentional Ascription in Practice Chapter 6 The Personal Level Chapter 7 Behavioral Continuity Chapter 8 Equifinality and Delimitation Chapter 9 Intentional Behaviorism 52995 Gordon R. Foxall 9 781878 978462 Context ISBN 1-878978-46-2 Press ii Chapter 1 Txxx iii Context and Cognition: Interpreting Complex Behavior Gordon R. Foxall Cardiff University CONTEXT PRESS Reno, NV ii Chapter 1 iv Chapter 1 ________________________________________________________________________ Context and Cognition: Interpreting Complex Behavior Paperback pp. 158 ________________________________________________________________________ Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Foxall, G. R. Context and cognition : interpreting complex behavior / Gordon R. Foxall.— 1st ed. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references. ISBN 1-878978-46-2 (pbk.) 1. Behaviorism (Psychology) I. Title. BF199.F69 2004 150.19’43—dc22 2003023282 ________________________________________________________________________ © 2004 CONTEXT PRESS 933 Gear Street, Reno, NV 89503-2729 All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording, or otherwise, without written permission from the publisher. Printed in the United States of America Txxx v Table of Contents Preface......................................................................................... vi Chapter 1 Intentional Behavior .......................................................... 11 Chapter 2 Radical Behaviorist Interpretation.................................... 27 Chapter 3 The Intentional Stance....................................................... 37 Chapter 4 The Contextual Stance....................................................... 55 Chapter 5 Intentional Ascription in Practice..................................... 73 Chapter 6 The Personal Level............................................................. 87 Chapter 7 Behavioral Continuity....................................................... 101 Chapter 8 Equifinality and Delimitation........................................... 117 Chapter 9 Intentional Behaviorism ................................................... 125 Notes.............................................................................................141 References......................................................................................145 vi Chapter 1 Preface He who knows only his own side of the case knows little of that. (John Stuart Mill, 1859) The authority exercised by schools of thought within the social scientific disciplines often seems a counter-productive consequence of the compartmental- ization of knowledge, inimical to intellectual vision if only because every way of seeing is a way of not seeing. It is, nevertheless, what this essay celebrates. For, unlike religious and political ideologies which can be imposed by force upon their chosen adherents, scientific ideas naturally evoke their antitheses and do battle with them. Unless such an idea is powerfully stated, unless the evidence for it is articulated with vigor, it is unlikely to bring forth the combative reaction upon which intellectual progress depends. The view that methodologies come and go over time, replacing one another in a process of paradigmatic conflict and supersession, holds sway over many social scientists. It is a view reflected in the common but superficial understanding that behaviorism has given way to cognitivism in psychology and that there is no going back. However, to the contrary, intellectual progress in social science relies heavily on the clash of extant theories, paradigms, and methodologies as well as on the more linear accumulation of knowledge that takes place within each. The co-existence of competing frameworks of conceptualization and analysis, far from providing evidence that psychology is a pre-paradigmatic field of inquiry that is yet to attain the status of mature science, is vitally necessary to the growth of knowledge. (Cf. Feyerabend, 1975; Kuhn, 1970). Such growth requires, however, that the adherents of the rival approaches interact, consider their several positions and methods, and are sufficiently open-minded to appreciate the intellectual challenges posed by synthesis and integration as opposed to the cozy acceptance of this or that locally-established world-view. Such interaction aids the process in which one paradigm impinges on, but never replaces, another, producing new syntheses, innovative predictions, and more satisfying explanations, none of which would be forthcoming but for the initial clash. But a clash of ideas is not a war. The intellectual is an arena in which no one need be hurt by friendly fire, and there need be no other kind. An essay is an attempt, neither a treatise nor a manifesto. In so designating what follows, I draw attention to the tentativeness of knowledge and argument. Holding our views tenaciously is essential to the fruitful interaction of our cherished theories with others’, but it is not the point of the exercise. A hundred years from now even our devoutest disciples, if we had them, would smile at our present schemes: perhaps we have something to learn from them. And so, to the point. Whilst the general wisdom has it that behaviorism is dead, it not only survives but is intellectually active in areas such as psychological theory, the analysis of Txxx vii language and cognition, and behavioral economics. It is a successful, albeit limited, source of behavioral science. Its chief difficulty arises when its practitioners look out from their laboratory windows and attempt to explain the complexities of human behavior that will never be amenable to direct experimental investigation. Behavior analysis has failed to establish a methodology of interpretation to deal fully with such complexity. The message of this essay is that it cannot do so without embracing intentional explanation in the form of an interpretive overlay that plugs the gaps in its explanations of life beyond the lab. The science of which behaviorism is the philosophy has produced not only a unique experimental analysis of behavior but also an array of applications to social and economic practice, and a basis of interpretation from which complex activities such as those involved in human economic behavior can be accurately predicted. It would be a travesty if the general wisdom prevailed to the extent of eclipsing these accomplishments. But the gaps remain: radical behaviorist interpretation is unable to deal with the personal level of explanation (at which an individual knows what pain is without being able to analyze it further, a level on which physiological accounts of pain cannot operate), or with the problem of why behavior persists in the absence of the immediate rewarding consequences that form the central plank in behaviorism’s explanatory scheme, or with the need to delimit the range of consequences that can reliably account for complex behavior. The attribution to individuals of desires and beliefs (“intentional ascription”) can perform these functions in the absence of which behavioral interpretation both founders and flounders. But the resulting methodology, which has the potential to unify aspects of behaviorism and cognitive psychology, is subtle and not without irony. There seems on the surface little hope of compromise between psychologists who are willing to attribute mental functioning to both humans and nonhumans, and those for whom behavior is always the result of non-cognitive learning and environmental history. Nevertheless, despite the tendency of behaviorists and cognitivists to misunderstand and disparage one another when in truth neither of their systems of thought is complete without the other, it is possible to find a new resting place for the debate in which they currently assume opposing positions. The differences between their methodologies, which revolve around the meanings they attribute to the term intentional behavior, have also the potential to unite them. The paradox is that the brand of behaviorism which is the central theme of the book, Skinner’s radical behaviorism, appears fundamentally antithetical to the approach which can rescue it, Dennett’s “intentional stance.” To those behaviorists who define thinking, deciding, believing and other cognitive activities as behaviors, albeit private, that are ontologically similar and subject to the same causal factors as public behaviors, intentional behavior is no more or less than the behavior that these events constitute. Hence Skinner (1974) portrays thinking, knowing, believing, and the like simply as “covert behavior.” This is of course an a priori assumption necessary to sustain a particular philosophy of psychology as it seeks to broaden its range of application from the experimental laboratory to the interpretation of everyday behavior, and it is not subject to direct viii Chapter 1 empirical evaluation. The other meaning of intentional behavior is behavior that can be explained fully only in terms of the ascription of intentional content, particularly desiring and believing. It is not that this behavior is caused by cognitive events in some mechanistic fashion: rather that understanding and perhaps predicting the behavior requires the ascription to it of cognitive content or intentionality. In this vein, Dennett (1978, p. 271) defines an intentional system, which might be a person, an animal or a machine such as a chess-playing computer, as one “whose behavior can be (at least sometimes) explained and predicted by relying on ascriptions to the system of beliefs and desires (and other intentionally characterized features) — what I will call intentions here, meaning to include hopes, fears, intentions, perceptions, expectations, etc.” Whilst this essay is generally concerned to clarify the relationship between these understandings of intentional behavior, it is largely concerned with the authors mentioned and their explanatory systems: that is, with radical behaviorism, a philosophy of psychology that invokes the first definition, in relation to Dennett’s intentionally-based approach which provides a basis for the currently far more dominant social cognitive psychology. Differentiating the meanings of these portrayals of intentional behavior and appreciating their place in diverse styles of scientific discourse is prerequisite to understanding the symbiotic association between behavior analysis and cognitivism. The methodology of Skinner’s paradigm is constructed on what we may call the contextual stance, the view that behavior is predictable in so far as it is assumed to be environmentally determined; specifically, in so far as it is under the control of a learning history that represents the reinforcing and punishing consequences of similar behavior previously enacted in settings similar to that currently encountered. In evaluating the exploitation of this methodological perspective in practice, it is essential to recall that modern behavior analysis, no longer confined to the rat and pigeon psychology that prevailed during the heyday of behaviorism, nowadays treats subject areas that lie at the very heart of cognitive psychology, among them thinking, decision making and language. Its proponents claim that radical behaviorism is sufficient to deal with these phenomena, indeed with all human and animal behavior, on its own terms. That means without resort to “mentalistic” concepts such as beliefs, attitudes and intentions which are the very stuff of modern information processing views of behavioral causation. Such views, which predominate in contemporary cognitive psychology, encapsulate an alto- gether different, indeed incommensurable, stance. The intentional stance (Dennett, 1978, 1983, 1987a) claims that the behavior of systems such as people and computers can be predicted from the desires and beliefs, and other intentional, idioms, that can be rationally attributed to them. We shall return to both stances. For now it is enough to state the major question raised in this essay: whether the conceptual independence of behavior analysis can be maintained without its practitioners’ adopting the countervailing stance in order to predict and explain complex human behavior. This extends the success criterion of behavioral science beyond mere prediction and control/influence into the realm Txxx ix of explanation and understanding. Putting prediction on the pedestal goes too far. As the physicist, David Deutsch (1977, p. 6) puts it, “Prediction is not the purpose of science, it is part of the characteristic method of science.” Prediction without understanding the nature of the world is in any case a highly limited goal of science and the elevation of prediction to occupy the sole position of importance in science may be antithetical to progress. As he further says, “Whereas an incorrect prediction automatically renders the underlying explanation unsatisfactory, a correct predic- tion says nothing at all about the underlying explanation. Shoddy explanations that yield correct predictions are two a penny…” (p. 65). A catholicity of vision that has not generally characterized behavior theory must become part of the scientific purview of its adherents. Recognition that the psychological theory it provides is unlikely to be of universal and exclusive application, that it has bounds that are defined by its competitors, and that the exploration of those bounds can expedite the growth of knowledge, is essential to intellectual progress. I thank Dermot Barnes-Holmes, Dawn Burton, Jean Foxall, Michael Kirton, Leonard Minkes, Jorge Oliveira-Castro, and John O’Shaughnessy for their com- ments. The book has some of its origins in a presentation to the annual conference of the Association for Behavior Analysis in New Orleans in 2001. I am grateful for encouragement received on that occasion, particularly from Norman Somach. Of course, the usual disclaimer applies. The essay is critical, within the spirit of academic discourse, of several behaviorist approaches to the interpretation of complex human behavior. My criticism of these theories is solely for their not accomplishing that for which they were never intended: a level of behavioral explanation over and above description, prediction and control. Nor is my criticism in any way ad hominem: the authors of these theories are after all the proverbial giants on whose shoulders the rest of us stand, even if we necessarily see things a little differently from that viewpoint. Gordon Foxall Penarth September 2003

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.