Constructive Negations and Paraconsistency TRENDS IN LOGIC Studia Logica Library VOLUME 26 Managing Editor Ryszard Wójcicki, Institute of Philosophy and Sociology, Polish Academy of Sciences, Warsaw, Poland Editors Vincent F. Hendricks, Department of Philosophy and Science Studies, Roskilde University, Denmark Daniele Mundici, Department of Mathematics “Ulisse Dini”, University of Florence, Italy Ewa Orłowska, National Institute of Telecommunications, Warsaw, Poland Krister Segerberg, Department of Philosophy, Uppsala University, Sweden Heinrich Wansing, Institute of Philosophy, Dresden University of Technology, Germany SCOPE OF THE SERIES Trends in Logic is a bookseries covering essentially the same area as the journal Studia Logica – that is, contemporary formal logic and its applications and relations to other disciplines. These include artificial intelligence, informatics, cognitive science, philosophy of science, and the philosophy of language. However, this list is not exhaustive, moreover, the range of applications, com- parisons and sources of inspiration is open and evolves over time. Volume Editor Heinrich Wansing The titles published in this series are listed at the end of this volume. Sergei P. Odintsov Constructive Negations and Paraconsistency 123 Sergei P. Odintsov Russian Academy of Sciences Siberian Branch Sobolev Institute of Mathematics Koptyug Ave. 4 Novosibirsk Russia ISBN 978-1-4020-6866-9 e-ISBN 978-1-4020-6867-6 Library of Congress Control Number: 2007940855 © 2008 Springer Science+Business Media B.V. No part of this work may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise, without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use by the purchaser of the work. Printed on acid-free paper. 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 springer.com Contents 1 Introduction 1 I Reductio ad Absurdum 13 2 Minimal Logic. Preliminary Remarks 15 2.1 Definition of Basic Logics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15 2.2 Algebraic Semantics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21 2.3 Kripke Semantics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28 3 Logic of Classical Refutability 31 3.1 Maximality Property of Le . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32 3.2 Isomorphs of Le . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35 4 The Class of Extensions of Minimal Logic 41 (cid:2) 4.1 Extensions of Le . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41 4.1.1 Intuitionistic and Negative Counterparts (cid:2) for Extensions of Le . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45 4.2 Intuitionistic and Negative Counterparts for Extensions of Minimal Logic . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 48 4.2.1 Negative Counterparts as Logics of Contradictions . . 52 4.3 Three Dimensions of Par . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53 5 Adequate Algebraic Semantics for Extensions of Minimal Logic 57 5.1 Glivenko’s Logic . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 57 5.2 Representation of j-Algebras . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 59 5.3 Segerberg’s Logics and their Semantics . . . . . . . . . . . . . 62 5.4 Kripke Semantics for Paraconsistent Extensions of Lj . . . . 78 v vi Contents 6 Negatively Equivalent Logics 81 6.1 Definitions and Simple Properties . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 81 6.2 Logics Negatively Equivalent to Intermediate Ones . . . . . . 84 6.3 Abstract Classes of Negative Equivalence . . . . . . . . . . . 88 + 6.4 The Structure of Jhn up to Negative Equivalence . . . . . . 91 7 Absurdity as Unary Operator 101 7.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 101 7.2 Le and L(cid:2) ukasiewicz’s Modal Logic . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 104 7.3 Paradox of Minimal Logic and Generalized Absurdity . . . . 108 7.4 A- and C-Presentations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 113 7.4.1 Definitions and First Results . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 113 7.4.2 Logic CLuN . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 119 1 7.4.3 Sette’s Logic P . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 123 II Strong Negation 129 8 Semantical Study of Paraconsistent Nelson’s Logic 131 8.1 Preliminaries . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 133 8.2 Fidel’s Semantics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 135 8.3 Twist-structures . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 138 8.3.1 Embedding of N3 into N4 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 142 8.4 N4-Lattices . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 145 8.5 The Variety of N4-Lattices . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 147 ⊥ ⊥ 8.6 The Logic N4 and N4 -Lattices . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 155 ⊥ 9 N4 -Lattices 159 ⊥ 9.1 Structure of N4 -Lattices . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 161 ⊥ 9.2 Homomorphisms and Subdirectly Irreducible N4 -Lattices . 167 ⊥ 10 The Class of N4 -Extensions 177 10.1 EN4⊥ and Int+ . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 177 10.2 The Lattice Structure of EN4⊥ . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 185 10.3 Explosive and Normal Counterparts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 195 10.4 The Structure of EN4C and EN4⊥C. . . . . . . . . . . . . . 201 ⊥ 10.5 Some Transfer Theorems for the Class of N4 -Extensions . . 211 11 Conclusion 223 Bibliography 227 Index 237 Chapter 1 Introduction Thetitleofthisbookmentionstheconceptsofparaconsistencyandconstruc- tive logic. However, the presented material belongs to the field of paracon- sistency, not to constructive logic. At the level of metatheory, the classical methods are used. We will consider two concepts of negation: the nega- tion as reduction to absurdity and the strong negation. Both concepts were developed in the setting of constrictive logic, which explains our choice of the title of the book. The paraconsistent logics are those, which admit in- consistent but non-trivial theories, i.e., the logics which allow one to make inferences in a non-trivial fashion from an inconsistent set of hypotheses. Logics in which all inconsistent theories are trivial are called explosive. The indicated property of paraconsistent logics yields the possibility to apply them in different situations, where we encounter phenomena relevant (to some extent) to the logical notion of inconsistency. Examples of these situ- ations are (see [86]): information in a computer data base; various scientific theories; constitutions and other legal documents; descriptions of fictional (and other non-existent) objects; descriptions of counterfactual situations; etc. The mentioned survey by G. Priest [86] may also be recommended for a first acquaintance with paraconsistent logic. The study of the paraconsis- tency phenomenon may be based on different philosophical presuppositions (see, e.g., [87]). At this point, we emphasize only one fundamental aspect of investigations in the field of paraconsistency. It was noted by D. Nelson in [65, p. 209]: “In both the intuitionistic and the classical logic all contradic- tions are equivalent. This makes it impossibleto consider such entities at all in mathematics. It is not clear to me that such a radical position regarding contradiction is necessary.” Rejecting the principle “a contradiction implies everything”(ex contradictione quodlibet) the paraconsistent logic allows one 1 2 1 Introduction to study the phenomenon of contradiction itself. Namely this formal logical aspect of paraconsistency will be at the centre of attention in this book. We now turn to constructive logic. Constructive logic is the logic of con- structive mathematics, logic oriented on dealing with the universe of con- structive mathematical objects. The common feature of different variants of constructive mathematics is the rejection of the concept of actual infin- ity and admitting only the existence of objects constructed on the base of the concept of potential infinity. In any case, passing to constructive logic from the classical one changes the sense of logical connectives. For example, Markov [60] defines the constructive disjunction as follows: “The construc- tive understandingof the existence of a mathematical object corresponds to the constructive understanding of the disjunction of sentences of the form “P or Q”. Such a sentence is considered as accepted if at least one of the sentences P, Q was accepted as true.” Of course, this understanding of dis- junction does not allow one to accept the law of excluded middle and leads to the rejection of classical logic. In the setting of constructive logic, there are two basic approaches to the concept of negation and they are considered in our investigation. Since the Brouwer works, the negation of statement P, ¬P, is under- stood as an abbreviation of the statement “assumption P leads to a con- tradiction”. Note that this concept agrees well with paraconsistency. The above understanding of negation does not assume the principle “contra- diction implies everything” (ex contradictione quodlibet) responsible for the trivialization ofinconsistent theories.Thefirstformalization ofintuitionistic logic suggested by A.N. Kolmogorov [44] in 1925 was paraconsistent. In this work, A.N. Kolmogorov reasonably noted that ex contradictione quodlibet (in the form ¬p → (p → q)) has appeared only in the formal presentation of classical logic and does not occur in practical mathematical reasoning. However, A. Heyting was sure that using ex contradictione quodlibet is ad- missible in intuitionistic reasoning and he added the axiom ¬p → (p → q) to his variant Li of intuitionistic logic [35]. Note that adding ex contradic- tione quodlibet creates some problems with interpretation of Li as calculus of problems [45]. One cannot consider the implication P → Q as the prob- lem of reducing the problem Q to the problem P. In Li, the implication P → Q means that the problem Q can be reduced to the problem P or the problem P is meaningless. This difficulty was known to A. Heyting, but he did not considered this as a serious problem. According to A. Heyting [36, p. 106], “... it (ex contradictione quodlibet — S.O.) adds to the precision of the definition of implication” and “I shall interpret implication in this wider sense.” 1 Introduction 3 Only in 1937 I. Johansson [41] questioned the using of ex contradictione quodlibet in constructive reasoning and suggested the system, which we de- note by Lj. Axiomatics for Lj can be obtained by deleting ex contradictione quodlibet from the standard list of axioms for intuitionistic logic, more ex- actly, Li = Lj+{¬p → (p → q)}. In [41], Johansson proved that many im- portantpropertiesofnegationprovableintheHeytinglogicLicanbeproved also in the system Lj. Since that the logic has the name “Johansson’s logic” or “minimal logic”(see the title of Johansson’s article). Note that, in fact, Johansson came back to the Kolmogorov’s variant of intuitionistic logic. More exactly, the implication-negation fragment of Lj coincides with the propositional fragment of the system from [44]. Kolmogorov considered the first-orderlogic,butinthelanguagewithonlytwopropositionalconnectives, implication and negation. Unfortunately, the logic Lj was for a long time on the borderline of studies in the field of paraconsistency, which was traditionally motivated by the following “paraconsistent paradox” of Lj. Although Lj is not explosive, admits non-trivial inconsistent theories, we can prove in Lj for any formulas ϕ and ψ that ϕ,¬ϕ (cid:3)Lj ¬ψ. This means that the negation makes no sense in inconsistent Lj-theories, because all negated formulas are provable in them. In this way, inconsis- tent Lj-theories are positive. It should be noted that studies in the field of paraconsistency were directed during a long period to searching for “the most natural system” of paraconsistent logic, which is maximally close to classical logic (cf. [39, p. 147]). The above paradox obviously shows that Lj cannotplaytheroleofsuchlogic.However,recently moreattention hasbeen paidto thestudyof paraconsistent analogs of well-known logical systems.In this respect, Johansson’s logic Lj is worthy of attention as a paraconsistent analog of intuitionistic logic Li. Turning to the second main approach to negation in constructive logic, the concept of strong negation. Note that the strong negation is namely a proper constructive negation. As happens with most fundamental logical concepts, the concept of strongnegation was developedindependentlybymanyauthorsandwithdif- ferent motivations. Constructive logic with strong negation was suggested for the first time by D. Nelson in 1949 [64]. The truth of a negation of statement in intuitionistic and minimal logic can be stated only indirectly, via reducing a negated sentence to an absurdity. As a consequence of this, the negation in these logics has the following feature, unsatisfiable from the
Description: