ebook img

Constructive Mathematics: Proceedings of the New Mexico State University Conference Held at Las Cruces, New Mexico, August 11–15, 1980 PDF

355 Pages·1981·4.432 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Constructive Mathematics: Proceedings of the New Mexico State University Conference Held at Las Cruces, New Mexico, August 11–15, 1980

Lecture Notes ni Mathematics Edited yb .A Dold dna .B nnamkcE 873 evitcurtsnoC scitamehtaM Proceedings of the New Mexico State University Conference Held ta saL Cruces, New ,ocixeM August ,51-11 1980 Edited yb .F Richman galreV-regnirpS Berlin Heidelberg New York 1981 Editor Fred Richman Department of Mathematics, New Mexico State University Las Cruces, NM 88003, USA AMS Subject Classifications (1980): 03 F 50, 03 F 55, 03 F 65 ISBN 3-540-10850-5 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg NewYork ISBN 0-387-10850-5 Springer-Verlag New York Heidelberg Berlin This work is the whole whether or All to subject reserved, copyright. rights are reprinting, specifically those of is concerned, translation, of the part material reproduction of broadcasting, re-use illustrations, yb or photocopying machine similar means, dna storage ni data § Under 54 banks. of Copyright the German waL where copies are made for to fee is a payable use, than private other Wort", "Verwertungsgesellschaft ,hcinuM © yb Berlin Springer-Verlag Heidelberg 1891 Printed ni Germany Printing dna binding: Offsetdruck, Beltz Hemsbach/Bergstr. 012345-0413/1412 PREFACE Constructive mathematics is distinguished by the fact that those engaged in it maintain an awareness of their relationship to the objects in the mathematical universe, and are concerned with manipulating those objects rather than merely describing them. Following Hao Wang we may say that constructive mathematics is a "mathematics of doing" while classical mathematics is a "mathematics of being." Constructivists feel that the mathematics they do is more meaningful, their theorems more incisive and informative, because of this perspective. The current resurgence of interest in constructive mathematics has two principal sources. One is Errett Bishop's "Foundations of constructive analysis". This book, in which Bishop expounds a constructive philosophy of mathematics and develops several areas of mathematics, using standard notation, from that point of view, can be appreciated by mathematicians who are unschooled in logic and recursive function theory. The other major influence has been the digital computer. The notion of computation in principle has become familiar through computer programming, making the idea that pure mathematics should be based upon computation, should have "numerical meaning", more attractive. There are several identifiable schools of constructive mathematics, all tracing their ancestry, in part, to L. E. J. Brouwer. Each takes its own view of the relationship of the mathematician to the mathematical universe, often based upon a particular ontological conunitment. The school of Markov admits only mathematical objects that are, ultimately, finite strings of symbols from a finite alphabet. This results in a list of all partial functions of positive integers, from which follows such nonclassical theorems as that every real valued function on the unit interval is (pointwise) continuous. This list may also be used to produce a counterexample to the Heine-Borel theorem. The intuitionists, who are the direct descendants of Brouwer, view all mathematical objects as creations of the mind and use this idea in their proofs. The two characteristic features of this school are choice sequences and bar induction. The former is the idea of a sequence of integers generated, in effect, by a "black box" so that no information is available beyond certain constraints given in advance and the knowledge of a finite number of values. The latter has its principal application in the fan theorem which says that a rooted tree, each of whose branch points is of finite degree, and in which every path is bounded, is finite. This theorem, which is proved classically by VI contradiction, is proved positively by the intuitionists by appealing to the source of our knowledge that every path is bounded. The notion of choice sequence leads immediately to the nonclassical theorem that every real valued function on the unit interval is continuous; the fan theorem implies that such a function is uniformly continuous. This contrasts with the Markov school which constructs an example of a function that is not uniformly continuous. Those who follow the lead of Errett Bishop take a free-wheeling finitist view with a minimum of (conscious) philosophical commitment. The Bishop school is conservative, in contrast to the intuitionists and the Markov school, in that no classical theorem is refuted. Any proof in the spirit of Bishop is also a classical proof, the difference being that the former will concern itself with the question of how to compute the data needed for the conclusion of the theorem in terms of the data given by the hypothesis. The ultrafinitist school of Yessenin-Volpin views very large numbers, such as 1030 , as inaccessible. In this way they arrive at different notions of the natural number series. There are also workers in recursive function theory whose results are often germane to constructive mathematics, and whose informal techniques are quite similar, but who work in a classical framework and may be thought of as developing a classical model of constructive mathematics. And there are those engaged in "predicative" mathematics, going back to Weyl, who are uneasy with the construction of least upper bounds for arbitrary bounded sets of real numbers, but quite content (unlike all the aforementioned) with the construction of least upper bounds for arbitrary bounded sequences of real numbers. Finally, there are those interested in algorithms that work in practice, rather than just computation in principle. Constructive mathematics arrived in Las Cruces in the Spring of 1970 when Stanley Tennenbaum, who was visiting New Mexico State University's department of mathematics, gave a series of seminars based on Bishop's book. No one could remember a better attended seminar. In 1971 Henry Cheng, a student of Bishop, accepted a position at NMSU, and in 1972 Bishop was the principal speaker at the annual NMSU Holiday Symposium. During this time an active group of constructive mathematicians was formed at NMSU including Mark Mandelkern, Gordon Berg, William Julian, Ray Mines and Fred Richman. In 1973 Y. K. Chan, another of Bishop's students, visited NMSU for a year. In January 1979 Mines and Richman organized two special sessions in constructive mathematics at the annual meeting of the American Mathematical Society in Biloxi. During that meeting the Las Cruces constructive group had the opportunity of meeting A. Seidenberg who had been studying finitistic techniques in algebra for several years, Anil Nerode who studied field theory from the point of view of recursive functions, Andrej Scedrov an intuitionistic logician from SUNY at Buffalo, Douglas S. Bridges who had just completed a book on constructive functional analysis in the spirit of Bishop, and Allan Calder who was writing an exposition of constructive mathematics for Scientific American. We were also able to renew our contacts with Newcomb Greenleaf who was working on Cantorian set theory from a constructive viewpoint, and with Y. K. Chan. Shortly after the Biloxi meeting it was decided that a larger meeting in a more relaxed atmosphere was in order. It was apparent at Biloxi that everyone would benefit by an exchange of ideas among the various schools of thought in constructive mathematics. Thus the 1980 Las Cruces conference on constructive mathematics was planned. The papers in this volume are in the order of their presentation at the conference. The following talks were given at the conference but will be published elsewhere: C. N. Delzell Maharishi Int. Univ. A CONSTRUCTIVE CONTINUOUS and L.S.U. SOLUTION TO HILBERT'S- 17th PROBLEM W. Julian New Mexico State U. z-COVERING DIMENSION V. Lifschitz University of Texas CALCULABLE NATURAL NUMBERS M. Mandelkern New Mexico State U. CONTINUITY OF MONOTONE FUNCTIONS J. Myhill SUNY at Buffalo CONSTRUCTIVE VS. NONCON- STRUCTIVE IN A CLASSICAL SETTING lV The conference would not have been possible without the support of the Arts and Sciences Research Center and the Department of Mathematical Sciences at New Mexico State University, nor without the efforts of the organizers Bill Julian and Ray Mines. Fred Richman February 1981 Las Cruces, New Mexico TABLE OF CONTENTS Page SEIDENBERG'S CONDITION P Fred Richman . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1 FIELDEXTENSIONS Wim Ruitenburg . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12 DEDEKIND DOMAINS Ray Mines and Fred Richman . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16 EFFECTIVE MATHEMATICS THE COMPUTER ALGEBRA VIEWPOINT James H. Davenport - . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31 ON SOME OPEN PROBLEMS IN CONSTRUCTIVE PROBABILITY THEORY Y. K. Chan . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 44 CONSISTENCY AND INDEPENDENCE RESULTS IN INTUITIONISTIC SET THEORY Andrej Scedrov . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 54 COMPUTABILITY OF ORDINAL RECURSION OF TYPE LEVEL TWO W. A. Howard . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 87 A CONSTRUCTIVE APPROACH TO CLASSICAL MATHEMATICS Jonathin P. Seldin . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 105 ON THE NOTION OF STANDARD NON-ISOMORPHIC NATURAL NUMBER SERIES David Isles . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . iii REFLECTIONS ON BISHOP'S PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS Nicolas D. Goodman . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 135 FORMALIZING CONSTRUCTIVE MATHEMATICS: WHY AND HOW? Michael Beeson . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 146 INDEPENDENCE OF PREMISSES AND THE FREE TOPOS J. Lambek and P. J. Scott . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 191 AN INTUITIONISTIC INFINITESIMAL CALCULUS Richard Vesley . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 208 LIBERAL CONSTRUCTIVE SET THEORY Newcomb Greenleaf . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 213 LOCATING METRIC COMPLEMENTS IN EUCLIDEAN SPACE Bridges, Calder, Julian, Mines and Richman . . . . . . . . 241 A DISJUNCTIVE DECOMPOSITION THEOREM FOR CLASSICAL THEORIES Joan Rand Moschovakis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 250 TOWARDS A CONSTRUCTIVE FOUNDATION FOR QUANTUM MECHANICS Douglas S. Bridges . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 260 ABOUT INFINITY, FINITENESS AND FINITIZATION A. S. Yessenin-Volpin . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 274 A CLASS OF THEOREMS WITH VALID CONSTRUCTIVE COUNTERPARTS Michael Gelfond . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 314 RATIONAL CONSTRUCTIVE ANALYSIS James R. Geiser . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 321 SEIDENBERG'S CONDITION P Fred Richman i. ~@~9[~@! ~!~!~{" In the theory of discrete fields, that is, fields in which equality is decidable, a central role is played by factorial fields. A discrete field k is (~P~K~!Z) ~g~R~!~! if every (separable) polynomial with coefficients in k is a, possibly trivial, product of irreducible polynomials. Van der Waerden [vdWl] gave an example of a countable discrete field which illustrates why the notion of faetoriality has some content. A simplified version of this example is achieved by letting {an} be an ascending sequence of zeros and ones, and letting k be the union of the fields Q(ian), where Q is the rational numbers and i is the imaginary unit. Then the polynomial 2 x + 1 factors over k if and only if n a = 1 for some 2 n. Were k factorial then either x + 1 would be irreducible, in 2 which case n a = 0 for all n, or x + 1 would factor in Q(ia n) for some n, in which case a = 1 for that n. n In the unexpurgated edition of van der Waerden's Modern Algebra [vdW2] it is shown that a finite dimensional separable extension of a factorial field is factorial. The treatment of this theorem in [vdW2] has been criticized and modified in [MR] and [S3]. The notion of a separably factorial field turns out to be, in some sense, more natural. Every finite dimensional extension of a separably factorial field is separably factorial [MR; Theorem 3.9]. Hence every finitely generated separable extension of a separably factorial field is finite dimensional (and separably factorial). On the other hand there are Brouwerian counterexamples to the theorem that a finite dimensional extension of a factorial field is factorial [S2], [MR; Example 4.3]. The property that finitely generated separable extensions are finite dimensional characterizes separably factorial fields among countable discrete fields as every nonconstant polynomial over a countable discrete field has a root in some discrete extension field [JMR; Theorem 3.8]. It is an open question whether thls result holds for arbitrary discrete fields. If we could construct root fields for polynomials over arbitrary discrete fields the answer would be "yes". However this would imply what might be called "the world's simplest axiom of choice": Let S be a set such that if x E S, then x = {a,b) where a # b. If x,y E S implies x = y, then there is a choice function on S, that is, a function f : S - uS such that f(x) e x for each x in S. Let S be a set as above, and let k be the following extension of the field of rational numbers. An element of k is a formal linear combination of the rational number 1 and elements of us = (a : aexeS for some x in S}. An element of k is equal to 0 if the coefficient of 1 is 0 and the sum of the coefficients of the elements of uS is 0. Addition is defined coordinatewise and multiplication is determined by setting the square of each element of uS equal to 2. If K is a discrete field containing k, and ~2 = 2 for ~ e K, then ~ provides a choice function on S by setting f(x) equ~l to that element of x that is equal to ~ in K. Classically this axiom of choice is trivial; constructively it appears to be as difficult as being able to choose an element out of each set in an arbitrary collection of two-element sets. However the latter axiom of choice has a Brouwerian counterexample in the set of pairs of antipodal points of a circle. Seidenberg [Sl] introduced a condition that is an inseparable version of separably factorial, namely that every finitely generated purely inseparable extension is finite dimensional. 2. ~ ! @ ~ g ~!~!~- Let k be a dlscrete fleld of finite characteristic p. Seidenberg's condition P arises from considering th the problem of whether a given element of k has a p root in k, that is, whether the subfield p k of pth powers of elements of k is detachable from k. The condition introduced by Seidenberg in IS1] is the first conditlon in the following theorem. THEOREM I. Let k be a discrete field of finite characteristic p. Then the following conditions are equivalent: i) Given aij • k for l(i(m and l(j4n, either there exist x. E k p, not all zero, with ~ a..x = 0 for 3 13 3 all i; or, whenever E a..x. = 0 for all i, with x. • k p, 13 3 3 then x. = 0 for all j. 3 2) If K is a finite dimensional extension of k, then p K is detachable from K. 3) If K is a finite dimensional purely inseparable extension of k, then p K is detachable from K. 4) Every finitely generated extension field K of k with p K c k is finite dimensional. 5) Every finitely generated kP-subspace of k is finite dimensional. PROOF. To derive 2 from I let Wl' '" "" Wn be a basis for K over k, and let lP~ ~n I bi~ j. Then an arbitrary element a ~ of K is in p K if and only if there exist x in p k such 3 ] i that n n x (~P n n E3=I a3~ 3 EI=I 1 1 = Ej=I Ei=I Xlbi3o) ~ that is, aj = ~i=l n i x b i3 for all j or, since the wP 1 are independent over k p, that the system of equations n b = 0 x0aj ~i=l xi i3 has a nontrivial solution in k p. Obviously 3 follows from 2. To

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.