ebook img

Conscience and Allegiance PDF

492 Pages·2016·3.27 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Conscience and Allegiance

Conscience and Allegiance: An Investigation into the Controversy over Oaths of Allegiance and Supremacy during the Reign of William III and II, 1689-1702. Ph.D. History, 2016. Jeffrey Alexander John Chambers University of Dublin, Trinity College. Declaration I declare that this thesis has not been submitted as an exercise for a degree at this or any other university and it is entirely my own work. I agree to deposit this thesis in the University’s open access institutional repository or allow the library to do so on my behalf, subject to Irish Copyright Legislation and Trinity College Library conditions of use and acknowledgement. Jeffrey Alexander John Chambers Acknowledgements I would like to thank my supervisor, Dr Robert Armstrong, for his great help, advice and support over the years. The Irish Research Council, Government of Ireland Postgraduate Scholarship funded my Ph.D. and I am grateful for this blessing. I am thankful for the constant encouragement on this journey from my mum, Liz, and brother, Richard. I would also like to thank all those who have helped me on my journey over the years. TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION 1 CHAPTER ONE: HISTORY AS A GUIDE IN THE INITIAL ALLEGIANCE DEBATES FROM JANUARY 1689. 31 CHAPTER TWO: PASSIVE OBEDIENCE AND NON-RESISTANCE. 62 CHAPTER THREE: CONQUEST THEORIES, 1689-92. 99 CHAPTER FOUR: CONTRACTS, LIBERTIES AND ALLEGIANCE. 134 CHAPTER FIVE: TOLERATION, ESTABLISHED CHURCHES AND ALLEGIANCE. 183 CHAPTER SIX: ALLEGIANCE AND PERCEPTIONS OF CATHOLIC ALLEGIANCE. 228 CHAPTER SEVEN: RIGHTFUL AND LAWFUL: ALLEGIANCE TO DE JURE MONARCHS. 260 CHAPTER EIGHT: PROVIDENTIAL THEORY IN THE LATE 1690S. 315 CHAPTER NINE: ABJURATION: DEFENDING THE ESTABLISHMENT. 348 CONCLUSION 389 APPENDICES 396 BIBLIOGRAPHY 413 Introduction In the winter of 1688-9 King James II and VII fled Britain and was replaced on the thrones of England, Scotland and Ireland by his son-in-law William of Orange and daughter Mary in events known as the Glorious Revolution. Across the Three Kingdoms bitter public debates erupted over whether subjects could take Oaths of Allegiance to the new monarchs despite having sworn allegiance to James, who was alive and demanding allegiance as the legitimate King. James Hamilton, Earl of Arran’s January 1689 speech to Scottish nobles meeting in London highlighted this moral conundrum. Arran hailed William’s rescuing the Kingdoms ‘from Popery’ but that did not allow Arran to ‘Violate’ his ‘Duty’ to James; Arran said that he disliked James’s ‘Popery’ but had ‘sworn and do owe Allegiance’ to James’s ‘Person.’ James was ‘the KING’ and it was his ‘Right’ to have subjects’ allegiance, making it ‘impossible for’ Arran to ‘sign away’ allegiance and offer it to William.1 In Early Modern Europe Allegiance Oaths were the strongest bonds of loyalty to monarchs. From local to national level these were prerequisites for obtaining political, civil and frequently religious offices. Publicly swearing allegiance bound subjects’ consciences to a ruler, allowing governments to claim popular support and legitimacy. This was a big political and moral decision.2 Numerous contemporary polemicists described allegiance as crucial to a government’s viability and legitimacy; without allegiance there would be chaos. The trust involved in swearing allegiance was ‘the Foundation of peace’ in a kingdom.3 Debates over paying William allegiance were crucial to the Revolution because without allegiance William’s regime and the Revolution settlements would not survive. 1 James Hamilton, Earl of Arran, A Short Speech Made by the Right Honourable the Earl of 2 John Spurr, ‘“The Strongest Bond of Conscience:” Oaths and the Limits of Tolerance in Early Modern England,’ in Harold E. Braun & Edward Vallance (eds.) Contexts of Conscience in Early Modern Europe, 1500-1700 (London, 2004), pp.151-6; Alexandra Walsham, ‘Ordeals of Conscience: Casuistry, Conformity and Confessional Identity in Post-Reformation England,’ in Braun, Vallance (eds.) Contexts of Conscience, pp.34-48; Edward Vallance, Revolutionary England and the National Covenant: State Oaths, Protestantism and the Political Nation, 1533-1682 (Woodbridge, 2005), pp.17-22; Tim Harris, Revolution The Great Crisis of the British Monarchy, 1685-1720 (London, 2007), pp.16-20; Mark Goldie, ‘The Unacknowledged Republic: Officeholding in Early Modern England,’ in Tim Harris (ed.) The Politics of the Excluded, c.1500-1850 (Basingstoke, 2001), pp.153-85. 3 Pierre Allix, An Examination of the Scruples of those who Refuse to Take the Oath of Allegiance (London, 1689), p.17; Gilbert Burnet, An Enquiry into the Present State of Affairs… (London, 1689), pp.3-4; Sir Robert Howard, Historical Observations upon the Reigns of Edward I, II, III, and Richard II… (London, 1689), p.43. 1 Allegiance Oaths symbolised political legitimacy and public approval of a government. These Oaths as public declarations, and the various public justifications of positions on allegiance, became, according to Steven Pincus and Julian Hoppit, public interpretations of the Revolution.4 Given this importance research on post-Revolution Allegiance debates in the Three Kingdoms has been surprisingly limited. Mark Goldie’s ‘The Revolution of 1689 and the Structure of Political Argument’ is the most influential history of England’s Allegiance Controversy and has been cited in numerous histories of the Revolution or of oaths in general. Goldie examined English allegiance pamphlets published between 1689 and 1694 and the frequency of the ideas these polemics employed to either justify or reject allegiance to William as a de facto King, a King in possession of the throne. This provided insights into contemporary political thought, public expressions of opinions by the politically involved, on the Revolution.5 Goldie and Howard Nenner have said that the justifications of the Revolution and allegiance to William as de facto King show the popular wariness of accepting the Revolution and its implications.6 Gerald Straka and Charles Mullet also examined the Allegiance Controversy and, like Goldie, considered this mainly in the terms of an English Anglican phenomenon in the first years of William’s reign.7 Edward Vallance, David Martin Jones, J.P. Kenyon and Kevin Sharpe also examined early-1690s English Allegiance debates as part of broad studies into seventeenth-century loyalty oaths or to explain the changing post- Revolution politics.8 However the distinctness of the post-Revolution 4 Steve Pincus, 1688: The First Modern Revolution (London, 2009), pp.441-2; Julian Hoppit, A Land of Liberty? England 1689-1727 (Oxford, 2000), pp.34-6. 5 Mark Goldie, ‘The Revolution of 1689 and the Structure of Political Argument,’ Bulletin of Research in the Humanities, 83 (1980), pp.473-520; Harris, Revolution, pp.358-9 Footnotes 114, 115; Pincus, 1688, pp.440-1 Footnote 11; Vallance, Revolutionary England, p.201 Footnote 2. 6 Mark Goldie, ‘The English System of Liberty,’ in Mark Goldie & Robert Walker (eds.) The Cambridge History of Eighteenth-Century Political Thought (Cambridge, 2006), pp.40-5; idem ‘The Revolution of 1689,’ pp.473-5; Howard Nenner, ‘The Later Stuart Age,’ in J.G.A. Pocock (ed) with the assistance of Gordon J. Schochet & Lois G. Schowerer The Varieties of British Political Thought, 1500-1800 (Cambridge, 1993), pp.196-208. 7 Mark Goldie, ‘Edmund Bohun and Jus Gentium in the Revolution Debate, 1689-1693,’ Historical Journal, 20, No. 3 (Sep., 1977), pp.569-86; idem, ‘The English System of Liberty,’ pp.40-7; Gerald Straka, Anglican Reaction to the Revolution of 1688 (Madison, 1962); Charles F. Mullet, ‘A Case of Allegiance: William Sherlock and the Revolution of 1688,’ Huntington Library Quarterly, 10, No. 1 (Nov., 1946), pp.83-103; idem, ‘Religion, Politics, and Oaths in the Glorious Revolution of 1688,’ The Review of Politics, 10, No. 4, (Oct., 1948), pp.462-74. 8 Vallance, Revolutionary England, pp.193-209; J.P. Kenyon, Revolution Principles The Politics of Party 1689-1720 (Cambridge, 1990), passim; Kevin Sharpe, Rebranding Rule The Restoration and Revolution Monarchy, 1660-1714 (London, 2013), pp.322-9, 358-70; David 2 allegiance debates and the importance of the later-1690s allegiance debates to the success of the Revolution are neglected. Only a few historians have examined mid-1690s debates over allegiance to William as de jure, rightful and lawful, King while Abjuration oaths are barely mentioned.9 This thesis seeks to give the fullest account of allegiance debates in England, Scotland and Ireland. It examines debates over allegiance to William as de facto and de jure King along with the overlooked late-1690s rhetoric on allegiance, at Abjuration oaths and at public views on allegiance by those outside the Anglican Communion. Tim Harris convincingly argues that late-Stuart period ideas on allegiance should be considered and examined as part of a British, as opposed to purely English, History of Political Thought. A History of British Political Thought examines the political ideas and public discourse surrounding events, like the Revolution, in the Three Kingdoms. Polemicists across the Kingdoms used common ideas, albeit in circumstances unique to each Kingdom, to justify allegiance.10 Existing research on post-Revolution allegiance debates in Scotland and Ireland is even more limited than the historiography on the English debates. The few histories of Irish political thought on the Revolution focus mainly on Irish Anglican representations of the Revolution in the subsequent years and decades. Most references to Irish Anglican allegiance polemics refer to their citation of popular Providential or Conquest theories to justify allegiance to William as de facto King. J.I. McGuire argues that because Ireland was largely under Jacobite control until 1690-1 Irish Anglicans merely adapted ‘well argued’ English allegiance polemics to Irish circumstances.11 S.J. Connolly and others also argue that English arguments were adapted to Irish circumstances but that Irish Anglicans were less restrained than English Martin Jones, Conscience and Allegiance in Seventeenth-Century England: The Political Significance of Oaths and Engagements (Rochester, 1999); H.T. Dickinson, Liberty and Property: Political Ideology in Eighteenth-Century Britain (London, 1977). 9 Pincus, 1688, pp.440-3, 446-7, 450-6, 463-70; Edward Vallance, ‘Loyal or Rebellious? Protestant Associations in England 1584-1696,’ Seventeenth Century, 17, Issue 1 (2002), pp.15-8; Sharpe, Rebranding Rule, pp.329-33, 347, 404-6, 457-8, 482-94; Geoffrey Holmes, British Politics in the Age of Anne (London, 1967), pp.63-5, 87-90. 10 Tim Harris, ‘In Search of a British History of Political Thought,’ in David Armitage (ed.) British Political Thought in History, Literature and Theory, 1500-1800 (Cambridge, 2006), pp.98-108; J.G.A. Pocock, Gordon Schochet & Lois G. Schwoerer, ‘The History of British Political Thought: A Field and its Futures,’ in Armitage (ed.), British Political Thought in History, Literature and Theory, pp.10-9. 11 J.I. McGuire, ‘The Church of Ireland and the “Glorious Revolution” of 1688,’ in Art Cosgrove & Donal McCartney (eds.) Studies in Irish History Presented to R. Dudley Edwards (Dublin, 1979), pp.137-8. 3

Description:
CHAPTER THREE: CONQUEST THEORIES, 1689-92. 99 .. Revolution in Scotland,' Records of the Scottish Church History Society .. 42 Geoff Baker, Reading and Politics in Early Modern England: The Mental World of a Destruction of Cyprus; Being a Secret History of the War of the Revolution in
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.