ebook img

Commentary and Tradition: Aristotelianism, Platonism, and Post-Hellenistic Philosophy PDF

468 Pages·2010·2.715 MB·English, French, Italian
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Commentary and Tradition: Aristotelianism, Platonism, and Post-Hellenistic Philosophy

Pierluigi Donini Commentary and Tradition Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca et Byzantina Quellen und Studien Herausgegeben von Dieter Harlfinger · Christof Rapp · Marwan Rashed Diether R. Reinsch Band 4 De Gruyter Pierluigi Donini Commentary and Tradition Aristotelianism, Platonism, and Post-Hellenistic Philosophy edited by Mauro Bonazzi De Gruyter ISBN 978-3-11-021872-5 e-ISBN 978-3-11-021873-2 ISSN 1864-4805 LibraryofCongressCataloging-in-PublicationData Donini,Pierluigi,1940− [Selections.Polyglot.2011] Commentary and tradition : Aristotelianism, Platonism, and post- Hellenisticphilosophy/PierluigiDonini;editedbyMauroBonazzi. p.cm.−(CommentariainAristotelemGraecaetByzantina;v.4) Italian,English,French,andGerman;introductorymatterinEnglish. Includesbibliographicalreferencesandindex. ISBN978-3-11-021872-5(hardcover:alk.paper) 1.Aristotle. 2.Platonists. I.Bonazzi,Mauro,1973− II.Title. B485.D64 2010 180−dc22 2010043239 BibliografischeInformationderDeutschenNationalbibliothek DieDeutscheNationalbibliothekverzeichnetdiesePublikationinderDeutschen Nationalbibliografie;detailliertebibliografischeDatensindimInternet überhttp://dnb.d-nb.deabrufbar. (cid:2)2011WalterdeGruyterGmbH&Co.KG,Berlin/NewYork DruckundBindung:Hubert&Co.GmbH&Co.KG,Göttingen (cid:2) GedrucktaufsäurefreiemPapier PrintedinGermany www.degruyter.com Table of Contents Introduction by Mauro Bonazzi and Robert W. Sharples 7 Acknowledgments 13 ARISTOTLE AND THE ARISTOTELIAN TRADITION Il libro Lambda della Metafisica e la nascita della filosofia prima 17 Mimesis tragique et apprentissage de la phronesis 37 Cause, volontarietà e decisione in Aristotele, Rhet. I 10-15 (unpublished) 53 Aristotele, De motu animalium 701a7 85 Alessandro e i metodi dell’esegesi filosofica 87 L’objet de la Métaphysique selon Alexandre d’Aphrodise 107 (cid:441)(cid:473)(cid:351)(cid:454) (cid:462)(cid:297)(cid:514)(cid:454)(cid:234)(cid:494)(cid:532) in Alessandro di Afrodisia 125 Alexander’s De fato. Problems of Coherence 139 Doti naturali, abitudini e carattere nel De fato di Alessandro 155 (with Paolo Accattino) Alessandro di Afrodisia De an. 90, 23 sqq., a pro- posito del (cid:516)(cid:518)(cid:815)(cid:521) (cid:511)(cid:713)(cid:520)(cid:504)(cid:511)(cid:508)(cid:516) 169 Senarco, Alessandro e Simplicio su movimenti e grandezze semplici nel De caelo 173 La giustizia nel medioplatonismo, in Aspasio e in Apuleio 179 PLATONISM AND POST-HELLENISTIC PHILOSOPHY The History of the Concept of Eclecticism 197 Testi e commenti, manuali e insegnamento: la forma sistematica e i metodi della filosofia in età postellenistica 211 Medioplatonismo e filosofi medioplatonici. Una raccolta di studi 283 Le fonti medioplatoniche di Seneca: Antioco, la conoscenza e le idee 297 Plutarco, Ammonio e l’Academia 315 Science and Metaphysics: Platonism, Aristotelianism, and Stoicism in Plutarch’s On the Face in the Moon 327 I fondamenti della fisica e la teoria delle cause in Plutarco 341 Platone e Aristotele nella tradizione pitagorica secondo Plutarco 359 L’eredità academica e i fondamenti del platonismo in Plutarco 375 Il De genio Socratis di Plutarco: i limiti del dogmatismo e quelli dello “scetticismo” (unpublished) 403 La connaissance de dieu et la hiérarchie divine chez Albinos 423 Sokrates und sein Dämon im Platonismus des 1. und 2. Jahrhunderts n.Chr. 437 6 Table of Contents A Bibliography of Pierluigi Donini’s Works 453 Index 459 Introduction by Mauro Bonazzi and Robert W. Sharples1 1. Commentary and Tradition presents a selection of articles, two of which unpublished, that Pierluigi Donini dedicated to the Aristotelian and Platonist tradition in a period spanning over 30 years of activity. The main reason which prompted the collection of these articles into a single book depends on the fact that many of them, in spite of their outstanding relevance, often appeared in journals and volumes which are difficult to find – a problem many colleagues often complained about. Moreover, the growing attention paid to Early Imperial philosophy in recent times further confirmed the value of the enterprise. The affinity of the articles both in content and style will also guarantee the unity of the volume. Collected together, these articles will provide a key to Aristotelianism and Platonism by pointing out major problems and themes. Indeed, Donini’s work, as it will emerge in the introduction, constitutes a necessary condition for an adequate understanding of Post-Hellenistic and Early Imperial philosophy. 2. Pierluigi Donini’s work on Aristotle and on the Aristotelian tradition, both in the papers collected in this volume and elsewhere, is characterised by the clarifi- cation of problematic passages and by the questioning of generally accepted interpretations. On several occasions in the papers in this volume Donini solves a problem simply by suggesting a new way of construing the syntax of an ancient text: this applies, for example, both to Aristotele, De motu animalium 701a7 and to Senarco, Alessandro e Simplicio su movimenti e grandezze semplici nel De caelo. And, as demonstrated in Alessandro di Afrodisia e i metodi dell’esegesi filosofica, in doing this Donini is following in the footsteps of the ancient com- mentator Alexander, to the interpretation of whom he has himself greatly con- tributed. One theme of Donini’s work has been Aristotle’s Metaphysics, and the con- troversy about the true nature of “first philosophy” for Aristotle – theology, or the study of being quabeing in all beings; (cid:418) or(cid:445)? In his book La metafisica di Aris- totele: Introduzione alla lettura (Rome 1995) Donini makes the important sug- 1 During the preparatory stages of this book, we received the sad news that Bob Sharples had passed away. He had very kindly agreed to contribute to this introduction with his extreme competence, discussing the works of Donini dedicated to Aristotelianism. This loss is a great sorrow for us, since we have lost a dear friend, who was always ready to discuss and collaborate, and at the same time one of the most competent and acclaimed scholars. [Pierluigi Donini and Mauro Bonazzi] 8 Introduction gestion that, while the “theological” book (cid:418) cannot have been intended to stand where it now does, since its first part on sensible beings is redundant in the context of the Metaphysics as a whole and suggests that (cid:418) was conceived by Aristotle as a self-contained treatise, Aristotle may have intended some discussion of immaterial being to stand at that point in his work, and editors may in this sense have been true to Aristotle’s intentions in putting (cid:418) in its present position. InIl libro Lambda della Metafisica e la nascita della filosofia prima Donini takes up the thorny question of Aristotle’s remark in (cid:418) 1 that changeable and un- changeable beings will be studied by different sciences if they do not have a common first principle, and suggests that Aristotle’s readiness in (cid:418) to accept that they may be the objects of a single science may reflect an early period when he had not yet fully broken free from the Academy’s conception of the inclusiveness of physics. In L’objet de la Métaphysique selon Alexandre d’Aphrodise Donini examines the position of the commentator Alexander of Aphrodisias on the object of “first philosophy” for Aristotle, and shows that, while Alexander’s solution can hardly be described as true to Aristotle – Alexander is, after all, trying to formu- late a consistent view whereas Aristotle’s may have changed over time – it is at least possible to improve the internal consistency of Alexander’s view by a simple modification to the punctuation of one sentence in the standard edition of his commentary. Alexander’s supposition that Aristotle’s views were consistent in all his works, and the ways in which he deals with texts which from this point of view are problematic, are also examined by Donini in Alessandro di Afrodisia e i metodi dell’esegesi filosofica. In Alexander’s De fato: Problems of coherence, Donini defends his earlier claim (in Tre studi sull’aristotelismo nel II secolo d.C., Turin 1974) that there are inconsistencies in the way the concept of nature is used in the De fato, both between the natures of individuals and the nature of human beings as a species, and also between nature as what determines our actions for the most part and the more Aristotelian notion of a natural endowment which is the basis on which individuals develop different characters. He also considers the difficulties which Alexander finds in combining an Aristotelian account of deliberation and decision with his own notion of freedom from determinism as involving the possibility for alternatives (on which see now S. Bobzien, The inadvertent conception and late birth of the free-will problem, “Phronesis” 43 (cid:62)1998(cid:64), pp. 133-175) and makes the interesting suggestions that Alexander’s solution in terms of alternative goals of action is more suited to ordinary people than to the Aristotelian phronimos, and that Alexander may be following a trend of his times in concentrating on the former rather than on the latter. But, as Donini rightly comments, this has the unwelcome implication that, the closer to moral virtue one is in Aristotle’s under- standing of that term, which Alexander in De fato shows no sign of rejecting, the lessfree one is in Alexander’s understanding of that term. In Doti naturali, abitu- dini e carattere nel De fato di Alessandro Donini returns to the discrepancies be- tween different parts of Alexander’s De fato, and points out that the latter part of that work presents not so much Aristotle’s theory of moral development as one Introduction 9 which is influenced by, and shows connections with, what is argued in the earlier part of the De fato itself. Determinism and character development in Aristotle are further examined by Donini in Ethos: Aristotele e il determinismo, Alessandria 1989, and in Volontarietà di vizio e virtù (Aristotele Etica Nicomachea III.1-7), in E. Berti-L.M. Napolitano Valditara (eds.), Etica, Politica, Retorica: Studi su Ari- stotele e la sua presenza nell’età moderna, L’Aquila 1989, pp. 3-21. Moral development in Aristotle is also the theme of Mimesis tragique et ap- prentissage de la phronesis, in which Donini argues that the Poetics fits into Aristotle’s scheme of intellectual enquiry as a part of ethics and politics; watching or reading tragedies assists adults in developing phronesis (but not the young, which is why tragedy is not explicitly discussed in Politics VIII). Interestingly, Donini suggests that the reason why the link between tragedy and the context of moral development in the citizens of a polis is not made explicit in the Poetics is Aristotle’s belief that the effects of tragedy can be achieved through private reading as well as through seeing a performance in a public context. In Cause, volontarietà e decisione in Aristotele, Rhet. I 10-15 Donini exam- ines Aristotle’s treatment of proairesis in these sections of the Rhetoric. He argues that differences from the concept as treated in the Ethics – notably its wider extension – are to be explained not by changes in Aristotle’s views over time, but by the different concerns and contexts in the different works. On another issue Donini revolutionised the study of Alexander by showing that his views were closer to Aristotle’s than had been thought. Alexander defines the soul as the capacity resulting from the mixture of the bodily elements (De anima 24.21-23). His view had commonly been dismissed, above all by Paul Moraux in the work that began the modern study of Alexander (Alexandre d’Aph- rodise: Exégète de la noétique d’Aristote, Liège-Paris 1942) as an example of the materialism which, according to some, marked the degeneration of ancient phi- losophy generally, and of the Aristotelian tradition in particular, after Aristotle himself. But Donini, in L’anima e gli elementi nel De Anima di Alessandro di Afrodisia, “Atti dell’Accademia delle Scienze di Torino” 105 (1971), pp. 61-107, shows that by referring to the capacity arising from the mixture, when his older contemporary Galen identified soul with the mixture, simply, Alexander is arguing for a more Aristotelian position than others did. Donini’s insight has been developed in the context of ancient thought about the relation between body and soul and of modern arguments in analytical philosophy concerning the relation between body and mind by V. Caston, Epiphenomenalisms: Ancient and Modern, “Philosophical Review” 106 (1997), pp. 309-363. In (cid:439)(cid:471)(cid:349)(cid:452) (cid:460)(cid:295)(cid:512)(cid:452)μ(cid:492)(cid:530) in Alessandro di Afrodisia Donini considers the different analyses of the influence of the heavens on the sublunary world, and in particular its relation to the presence of soul in individual living creatures, advanced by Alexander in Quaestio 2.3. He shows that this is part of Alexander’s response to the criticism by the Platonist Atticus (fr. 8 des Places) that Aristotle makes the world, as it were, episodic; but there is nothing in Alexander’s accounts ap- proaching the Platonic doctrine of the World-Soul. 10 Introduction InLa giustizia nel medioplatonismo, in Aspasio e in Apuleio Donini examines the problematic reference in the prologue to Aspasius’ commentary on the Ethics2 to “theoretical justice” as possessed by God. He shows the connection to the account of justice by Aspasius’ younger contemporary Apuleius in his On Plato, where iustitia speculatrix utilitatis alienae is a virtue of the philosopher-rulers of the Republic, and argues that the background to Apuleius’ account is an attempt by Platonists to systematise Plato’s views in a way similar to what the Aristote- lian commentators were doing with Aristotle. 3. Along with the Aristotelian tradition, Platonism is another favourite theme of Donini’s work and the other major issue of the present volume. As in the case of Aristotelianism his research promoted a better understanding of this philosophical tradition by questioning generally accepted interpretations. Platonism is tradition- ally reduced to one of the two following options: either as a sort of perennis philosophia or as an incoherent form of eclecticism. Against the first tendency Donini constantly argues in favour of its historical complexity; and against the latter he shows that, in spite of this apparent confusion, the Platonists’ doctrines rest on conscious argumentative strategies. He successfully steers a middle course between these different and misleading interpretations by emphasizing the cen- trality of Plato’s dialogues. Indeed, Platonism can neither be reduced to the peren- nial transmission of a corpus of “secret doctrines” as opposed to the philosophical contents of the dialogues nor as a syncretistic attempt to assemble bits and pieces of other philosophies into one single system.3 One major result of his ground- breaking monograph Le scuole l’anima l’impero. La filosofia da Antioco a Plotino (Turin 1982), consists of clearly taking out any interpretation of Platonism which does not acknowledge the pivotal role of the dialogues; and many of the papers here presented confirm this view apropos of many specific and substantial issues. Most notably, I fondamenti della fisica e la teoria delle cause in Plutarco argues that Plutarch’s theory of causes heavily depends on a stringent and original interpretation of the Timaeus. Needless to say, the Timaeus is the great protagonist of many other papers. But it is not the only one, and other dialogues are equally important, as for instance the Republic when Donini gives his balanced account of Albinus/ Alcinous’ theology in La connaissance de dieu et la hiérarchie divine chez Albinos. When read against the background of the dia- logues, Alcinous’ presentation of God acquires a consistency otherwise difficult 2 Often referred to as Aspasius’ commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics: but while As- pasius includes the “common books” (Nicomachean Ethics 5-7 = Eudemian Ethics 4-6) in his commentary on the former, it is not clear that he regarded them as actually belonging to the Nicomachean Ethics, and in fact there are indications that he did not do so. See J. Barnes, An introduction to Aspasius, in A. Alberti-R.W. Sharples (eds.), Aspasius: the Earliest Extant Commentary on Aristotle’s Ethics, Berlin 1999, pp. 1-50, at p. 21. 3 More in general, The History of the Concept of Eclecticism correctly argues against the adoption of this category by showing that it seriously hinders an adequate understanding of Post-Hellenistic philosophy.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.