ebook img

Collected Papers Volume 2: Collected Essays 1929 - 1968 PDF

556 Pages·2009·1.981 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Collected Papers Volume 2: Collected Essays 1929 - 1968

Collected Papers Volume 2 Gilbert Ryle was one of the most important and yet misunderstood philos- ophers of the twentieth century. Long unavailable, Collected Essays 1929–1968: Collected Papers Volume 2 stands as testament to the astonishing breadth of Ryle’s philosophical concerns. This volume showcases Ryle’s deep interest in the notion of thinking and contains many of his major pieces, including his classic essays ‘Knowing How and Knowing That’, ‘Philosophical Arguments’, ‘Systematically Misleading Expressions’ and ‘A Puzzling Element in the Notion of Thinking’. He ranges over an astonishing number of topics, including feelings, pleasure, sensation, forgetting and concepts, and in so doing hones his own philosophical stance, steering a careful path between behaviourism and Cartesianism. Together with the first volume of Ryle’s collected papers and the new edition of The Concept of Mind, these outstanding essays represent the very best of Ryle’s work. Each volume contains a foreword by Julia Tanney, and provide essential reading for any student of twentieth-century philosophy of mind and language. Gilbert Ryle (1900–1976) was Waynflete Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy and Fellow of Magdalen College, Oxford, an editor of Mind and a president of the Aristotelian Society. Julia Tanney is Senior Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of Kent and has held visiting positions at the universities of Picardie and Paris-Sorbonne. COLLECTED PAPERS VOLUME 2 Collected Essays 1929–1968 Gilbert Ryle First published 1971 by Hutchinson This edition published 2009 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon, OX14 4RN Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 270 Madison Ave, New York, NY 10016 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2009. To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk. © 2009 The Estate of Gilbert Ryle: Hertford College, University of Oxford © 2009 Julia Tanney for Foreword All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data A catalog record for this book has been requested ISBN 0-203-87530-3 Master e-book ISBN ISBN10: 0–415–48549–5 (hbk) ISBN10: 0–203–87530–8 (ebk) ISBN13: 978–0–415–48549–4 (pbk) ISBN13: 978–0–203–87530–8 (ebk) C ONTENTS Foreword vii Introduction xx 1 Negation 1 2 Are there propositions? 13 3 Systematically misleading expressions 41 4 Imaginary objects 66 5 ‘About’ 86 6 Internal relations 89 7 Mr Collingwood and the ontological argument 105 8 Back to the ontological argument 120 9 Unverifiability-by-me 126 10 Induction and hypothesis 137 11 Taking sides in philosophy 160 12 Categories 178 13 Conscience and moral convictions 194 14 Philosophical arguments 203 15 Knowing how and knowing that 222 16 Why are the calculuses of logic and arithmetic applicable to reality? 236 17 ‘If’, ‘so’, and ‘because’ 244 18 Heterologicality 261 vi CONTENTS 19 Thinking and language 269 20 Feelings 284 21 The verification principle 300 22 Thinking 307 23 Ordinary language 314 24 Proofs in philosophy 332 25 Pleasure 339 26 Sensation 349 27 The theory of meaning 363 28 Predicting and inferring 386 29 On forgetting the difference between right and wrong 394 30 A puzzling element in the notion of thinking 404 31 Use, usage and meaning 420 32 A rational animal 428 33 Abstractions 448 34 Thinking thoughts and having concepts 459 35 Teaching and training 464 36 Thinking and reflecting 479 37 The thinking of thoughts: What is ‘le Penseur’ doing? 494 Index 511 F OREWORD The first article in this collection appeared 20 years before the 1949 publication of The Concept of Mind and it and those that follow deal with a question that occupied Ryle in the 1920s and 30s: ‘What constitutes a philosophical problem; and what is the way to solve it?’ (1970, 12) Having produced various papers, responses, articles and discussion notes on philosophy’s proper goals and methods, Ryle decided—when invited to contribute to Hutchinson’s Philosophical Library series—the time was right to ‘exhibit a sustained piece of analytical hatchet-work being directed upon some notorious and large-sized Gordian Knot.’ (ibid) Thus Ryle went straight to work on The Concept of Mind demonstrating the method he had long, in these early papers, described and defended. In retrospect, this was a shame: though many read The Concept of Mind, far fewer heard his papers or read his articles. Had the readers of the book had a clear sense that Ryle’s method of analysis was a type of ‘conceptual cartography’ they would have realised that Ryle did not construe the task of analysis as did the early Russell and Moore—at least in terms of how they characterised the task, if not in how they prosecuted it (Collected Papers 1, 280). Ryle’s identification as a logical behaviourist—and thus the mistaken assimilation of his work with that of the Vienna Circle—would never have gained the momentum it did. For Ryle’s method reversed the main assumptions of philosophy of language resurrected from Plato by Mill—that the main function of words is to name or denote objects, viii FOREWORD qualities or relations—assumptions which Frege and Russell were just beginning to question and which would later be altogether demolished by Wittgenstein. Awareness of his work in logic and language would have brought home how inapt is the description of Ryle as an empiricist or an anti-realist about the mental or about dispositions. Indeed, familiarity with his work in general would give one pause in describing Ryle as an ‘ist’ about anything. In the articles in his Collected Papers Volume 2 we discover important leit- motifs that occur throughout Ryle’s work: his interest in what accounts for the difference between expressions that make sense or those that are nonsensical; the role of philosopher as cartographer; the importance and ubiquity of systematically misleading expressions; the inflections of mean- ing or elasticities of significance that characterise words, phrases, sentences and their paraphrases; the difficulty for thinkers in general and philosophers in particular as they begin to think about and then wield their technical tools to tackle abstract concepts; the relation between words, sentences, concepts and propositions; and his introduction to philosophy of the notion of thin and thick descriptions. These articles are a striking anticipa- tion in print of the ideas and themes that also interested Wittgenstein though the method and style of philosophising are Ryle’s inimitable own. Sentences do not simply report and describe; only some words function as names and then only some of the time. Ryle’s insistence on recognising the indefinitely many other functions of expressions, as well as the possi- bility of descriptions ascending an ever-increasing ladder of sophistica- tion that would require an indefinite number of syntactically variegated subordinate clauses to unpack, puts him well at odds with those who hanker after an ideal of language as one suited to the aims of mathematical logic. It puts him at odds with any philosophical position—including today’s reductive ‘naturalism’—that attempts to force these expressions and descriptions into the too few dockets that formal logicians have to offer. Indeed much philosophy in the Anglo-Saxon tradition would be transformed, if not decimated, if Ryle’s—and Wittgenstein’s corresponding—lessons were heeded. According to Urmson (1967, 269), ‘Systematically Misleading Expres- sions’ was ‘easily the first, although incompletely worked out, version of a view of philosophy closely akin to that which Wittgenstein was then beginning to work out independently, and which is often spoken of as having been first suggested by Wittgenstein.’ The thesis is that there are FOREWORD ix many expressions that occur in non-philosophical discourse which do not present puzzles to those who use them. They do, however, tend to mislead philosophers and others into thinking that (to adopt the way Ryle puts it later) the work or job these expressions perform is of one kind rather than another. For example, ‘Carnivorous cows do not exist’ is a sentence that is nei- ther false nor senseless; it presents no philosophical puzzle when used in appropriate circumstances—for example, to reassure a child who is afraid a cow might eat him. But sentences of the form ‘x exists’ and ‘x does not exist’ tend to puzzle philosophers who makes the unquestioned grammat- ical assumption—a major irritant for Ryle—that subject-predicate expres- sions function by attributing a quality or property to an object, where the object is what is supposedly signified by the grammatical subject. For such expressions do not assert or deny of an object that it is non-existent; rather they deny of cows that they have the property of being carnivorous. The tendency to populate the world with imaginary objects derives, in part, from a confusion about various ways of understanding the remark that a proposition is about something, for if we persist in thinking that both ‘Mr Pickwick visited Rochester’ and the philosophers’ sentence ‘Mr Pickwick is an imaginary entity’ are about Mr Pickwick in the same sense of ‘about’, ‘so long will people continue to suppose that there is a Mr Pickwick somewhere—in Dickens’ head, perhaps, or in a mysterious repository called an “universe of discourse.”’ (this edition, 70)1 In this example we see a particular confusion that comes from conflating the philosophers’ referential sense of ‘about’ with the way a sentence can be about (in a different sense) its grammatical subject. Indeed, the philosopher-logician is apt to get into trouble in forgetting the different uses of ‘about’. For the notions they explicate—the logical subject, subject of predicates, subject of attributes, substance, particular, term, constituent of a fact or proposition, denotation, description, incomplete symbol and logical construction—all contain or hinge on this word (86). A number of statements—quasi-ontological, those allegedly about uni- versals, descriptive, quasi-descriptive and quasi-referential ‘the’-phrases— come under Ryle’s scrutiny because they tend to mislead with the same consequences, for they all suggest the existence of special objects. Indeed, 1Unless otherwise stated, page numbers refer to this edition of Collected Papers Volume 2.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.