ebook img

Cognitive Science and Genetic Epistemology: A Case Study of Understanding PDF

200 Pages·1990·4.014 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Cognitive Science and Genetic Epistemology: A Case Study of Understanding

COGNITIVE SCIENCE AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY A Case Study of Understanding PATH IN PSYCHOLOGY Published in Cooperation with Publications for the Advancement of Theory and History in Psychology (PATH) Series Editors: David Bakan, York University John Broughton, TetI&hers College, Columbia University Robert Rieber, John Jay College, CUNY, and Columbia University Howard Gruber, University of Geneva· COGNITIVE SCIENCE AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY: A Case Study of Understanding David Leiser and Christiane Gillieron A CRITICAL PSYCHOLOGY: Interpretation of the Personal World Edmund V. Sullivan CRITICAL THEORIES OF PSYCHOLOGICAL DEVELOPMENT Edited by John M. Broughton DEVELOPMENTAL APPROACHES TO THE SELF Edited by Benjamin Lee and Gil G. Noam FRANTZ FANON AND THE PSYCHOLOGY OF OPPRESSION Hussein Abdilahi Bulhan HUMANISTIC PSYCHOLOGY: Concepts and Criticisms Edited by Joseph R. Royce and Leendert P. Mos PSYCHOSoctAL THEORIES OF THE SELF Edited by Benjamin Lee THEORETICAL PSYCHOLOGY: The Meeting of East and West A. C. Paranjpe WILHELM WUNDT AND THE MAKING OF A SCIENTIFIC PSYCHOLOGY Edited by R. W. Rieber COGNITIVE SCIENCE AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY A Case Study of Understanding DAVID LEISER Ben-Gurian University of the Negev Beer-5heva, Israel AND CHRISTIANE GILLIE RON University of Geneva Geneva, Switzer/and PLENUM PRESS • NEW YORK AND LONDON Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Leiser, David. Cognitive science and genetic epistemology: a case study of understanding / David Leiser and Christiane Gillieron. p. cm.-(PAT H in psychology) Includes bibliographical references. 1. Seriation (Psychology) 2. Genetic epistemology. 3. Cognitive science. I. Gillieron, Christiane. II. Title. III. Series. BF445.L45 1989 89·22970 153.4-dc20 CIP ISBN-13: 978-1-4684-5651-6 e-ISBN-13: 978-1-4684-5649-3 001: 10.1007/978-1-4684-5649-3 © 1990 Plenum Press, New York Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1s t edition 1990 A Division of Plenum Publishing Corporation 233 Spring Street, New York, N.Y. 10013 All rights reserved No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording, or otherwise, without written permission from the Publisher FOREWORD Some 10 years ago, Leo Apostel presented an analysis of developments taking place in genetic epistemology and artificial intelligence, and re marked that the two disciplines appeared to be converging, without one dominating or assimilating the other. In his view, significant formal and experimental progress would be required in the post-Piagetian era: ge netic epistemology would need to take into account developments in artificial intelligence, while remaining an independent discipline at the frontiers of biology, logic, and psychology. The work of David Leiser and Christiane Gillieron, both psychol ogists with a Genevan training who are concerned by the procedural aspects of intelligence, is an important contribution. Their studies, which open up new theoretical perspectives, are carried out with metic ulous attention to research methodology. Going beyond merely ad dressing criticisms about the status of Piagetian operational structures, their work will help fill the gap between genetic epistemology and cog nitive science. The authors' main purpose is to analyze the relations between pro cedures and structures via a series of carefully constructed seriation experiments. The study of these relations not only occupies an impor tant place in the current concerns of Piaget-inspired psychology, but it also allows an assessment of the contributions of studies in artificial intelligence to genetic epistemology, as well as a view of their limita tions. As computational treatments deal in symbols, they refer predomi nantly to mental representations and eliminate almost all reference to constructions through operations. Genetic epistemology, by contrast, emphasizes systems of actions and operations that lead to logical co herence and the search for reasons. The authors aim to identify levels of descriptions that ensure the transition between cognitive representa tions and operations. Specifically, they show how only the higher levels v vi FOREWORD of abstractions (often neglected by certain cognitive scientists) can ac count for the subject's understanding. There are various ways, not all operative, to carry out a task suc cessfully and to arrive at the same result. To be sure, a correct solution does not necessarily imply an understanding of the procedure adopted; but can one countenance fundamental progress in knowledge without a construction tending toward that coherence which founds categories and nonns? Even imperfect knowledge that follows deviant paths has this tendency toward coherence. To ignore this tendency is to neglect that which lies at the heart of all cognitive behavior: the phenomenon of understanding. The way Leiser and Gillieron construe the problem they treat is in fundamental agreement with my own views. In a paper on the relations between procedures and structures (Inhelder and Piaget, 1979), several differences between procedures and structures were pointed out: struc tures are basically atemporal, whereas procedures necessarily unfold temporally; similarly, structures are characterized by their coherence while procedures show great variety and specificity. Furthennore, I agree with G. Cellerier, that the most general property of intelligence is to be found in the construction of ad hoc models which, progressively, become operatory. Along similar theoretical lines, Leiser and Gillieron explore the passage from temporality to atemporality and the construc tion of normative structures. They raise the fundamental problem of how a new procedure is invented, and how a successful procedural invention can lead to an understanding that goes beyond its specificity. A related, also fundamental problem is that of the so-called tem poral decalage. Many psychologists have wondered why certain struc tures fail to be manifested in all appropriate contexts. Jean Piaget and myself studied the structuring of certain aspects of reality (such as quan tity and mass) by the subject. We did so by analyzing the logic of his behavior. A procedural approach to the decalages we noted can throw new light on this question. Is it possible to solve a seriation problem without applying the supposedly necessary operations? Leiser and Gillieron present early successes in seriation that rely on various pro cedures (e.g., spatial procedures) and that do not involve the operations we considered prototypical; in these cases, success on the task does not imply understanding of the procedure. As I see it, the originality of the research presented in this volume lies in that the authors study the general paradigm of seriation in all of its variations. Working with adults at the level of mental representa tions, without allowing the subjects to manipulate, and with children who act on objects that vary along different dimensions (e.g., length, FOREWORD vii weight), they analyze in detail the temporal unfolding of certain pro cedures as well as the part played by spatial structures, and do so with exceedingly ingenious and subtle methods. The "spatial core of organi zation," emphasized by Piaget and myself in different contexts as a source for other comparable or isomorphic organizations (such as time and size) is brought into prominence for seriation problems. The au thors also clarify the relations between anticipatory schemes which typ ically illustrate top-down processes, and the empirical discovery of pro cedures which are bottom-up processes. In our work of the 1940s and 1950s, Piaget and I were much con cerned with transitivity and reversibility as characteristic manifestations of operativity. Leiser and Gillieron argue that these characteristics of operativity are often not relevant for the invention of specific pro cedures. Indeed, identical behavior can appear at different levels of operativity, and the same result can be obtained by dissimilar pro cedures. As pointed out by the authors, all thought tends toward co herence which only overall, operative structure can guarantee. In other terms, inventing a procedure is very different from understanding it. Knowing why procedures work requires a system of operations. Leiser and Gillieron introduce their readers to a set of problems I share; their clearly worked-out conceptual framework and methodology throw light on the relation between general cognitive competence and specific knowledge on how to solve a problem, studied in real time and in the course of development. In order to bridge the gaps between genetic psychology and epistemology on the one hand, cognitive sci ence on the other hand, it is to be hoped that further research will be inspired by the work reported in this volume. BARBEL INHELDER University of Geneva Geneva, Switzerland PREFACE This book is concerned with the connection between procedures and structures, the former emphasized by cognitive scientists of the Ameri can persuasion, and the latter honored by older cognitivists in the vein of genetic epistemology. In the chapters that follow, we strive to show, by a case study, that the two approaches are not antagonistic but com plement each other. Piaget's genetic epistemology is an attempt to explicate knowledge by scrutinizing its causal genesis. Starting from his view that norms have an objective reality since they appear as such to human subjects, who assuredly exist, Pia get believed that describing the construction of normative systems (especially logic) was a way to understand episteme. Knowledge links mathematics and reality. This is particularly true of scientific knowledge: modeling the world is mathematizing it. A general epistemology directed toward the whole enterprise of knowledge must therefore consider both the deductive and the empirical sciences in their mutual interdependence. To some mathematicians or logicians, the mere claim that they are interdependent could seem blasphemous: formal disciplines are not concerned with reality. The ghost of psychologism is still frightening. For genetic epistemology, however, the link between reality and logico mathematical beings is the main problem to be solved, and a genetic and naturalistic approach plays a central role in its solution (Gillieron, 1987). Indeed, looking at the development of cognition in the child is Piaget's clever trick to answer the question of both the "logic" of the real and the reality of logic (Piaget, 1972/1947). To some psychologists, too, such concerns will seem foreign and inopportune. Yet the time has come to understand that Piaget was not a child psychologist, and that his "cognitive structures" were not aimed at modeling the child's solutions to ordinary tasks. These tasks were care fully calibrated to answer specific questions such as the priority of logical ix x PREFACE thinking over empirical theorization. In other words, the "model" was nested in the task, and a behavioral approach to the Genevan experi ments would simply miss the mark. A bottom-up look at the publicly observable data, going from the description of some "performance" to an abstract model of "competence," is far opposite the genetic way. Genetic psychology is adult-centered, indeed, scientist-centered. It starts from the end, the final stage, and reconstructs its construction. Even so, and each in its own way, cognitive science and genetic psychology are concerned with tasks and the ways of the subject who faces them. This book is a case study of one such task-seriation. Speaking of one task is already taking a stand, for we wish to refer to a class of experimental tasks. But this illustrates perfectly a problem that pervades the problem-solving literature and demonstrates what Piaget meant by mathematization. In reality, no two things are ever the same; they are only similar. Now, similarity means assimilation, i.e., active work of a subject who identifies, recognizes, and calculates. In structions such as "Put the balls in order according to their weight" and "Put the sticks in order according to their length" are the same for somebody who knows what is changed and what is conserved. The gerund form in "mutatis mutandis" hides a norm, the norm the experi menter shares with the subject, if they understand each other. (It is worth noting that in genetic psychology mutual understanding is a cen tral clue to the communalities of norms.) When are two tasks variants of a single problem, or when are they instances of two different problems? Doubtlessly, when they have the same structure. But the same structure for whom, the subject or the experimenter? This question does not usually bother one who sets up an experi ment by "covering up" a structure; he feels he knows where he stands and where his tasks originated. To somebody who is unclear about the psychological status of structures of understanding, the situation is more confused. One occasional way out is to look at solutions rather than at problems, and define isomorphism by the mapping of the steps of two procedures. The term "isomorphism" then loses its original meaning. In any event, if an experimenter presents two tasks with the hope that the subject will apply the "same" solution to both, this means that he himself is able to do so, i.e., they are the same for him. But the experimenter is always one step ahead, for he knows that the "prob lems" he formulates have a solution. For the subject, who is ignorant of the solution, do the two problems also have the same structure? And the same holds in the more interesting case of the experimenter-less subject, who stands directly before nature, and, in particular, of the scientist. PREFACE xi One may point to the difference between the structures of the sub ject and those of the observer. Of course, this does not answer the question of why a form applies to a particular content, because the very fact that the experimenter already has a solution implies that the subject could, in principle, find it too (after all, both are human beings). But when there is no experimenter and the subject consistently fails, the fault lies not with him but with reality, which resists his efforts. Why is it that reality sometimes accepts, sometimes resists, mathematization? This question is at the core of the discussion of "horizontal decalages." When designing two problem isomorphs, experimenters, who often manage to disguise a structure with appropriately confusing in structions, may obscure their similarity. The first part of the book will show us treading this way. Now, horizontal decalages are not the result of instructions, but of reality. No wonder it is such a vexing topic; it is also a puzzle to the epistemologist, not just to a subject who complies with the experimenter by finding an already existing solution. This is why we do not claim to provide a general answer to the question of decalages, although the second part of the book might be read with this concern in mind. We want to relate specific solutions to a more general cognitive organization and analyze the understanding of the task at four different levels. These are hierarchically ordered and go from the most literal reading of the instructions (which needs assimilation anyway), from the most procedural to the most abstract, context-free, atemporal structural knowledge. We still believe in an evolutionary approach and address the question of the emergence of such a general organization. The book is structured in two parts, which represent two argu ments. On the one hand, adults are guided by operational structures. The first part addresses this question, and discusses the first two levels at length. On the other hand, children who are not yet "good" mathe maticians in the adult sense still are guided by some supraprocedural conception. When the child's rationality differs from the experimenter's, she may end with a "bad" yet coherent and anticipatory procedure. The developmental pattern of solutions, and the way they integrate logical, operatory properties such as transitivity or reversibility (or fail to do so), is treated in Part II. As expected, a general discussion brings the things together and opens the field to further investigation. Most of the data presented here were gathered during the years 1972-1976. We feel, however, that they are still pertinent to the current debate, which in turn has challenged our views and nourished our dis cussions. We thank the Archives de Psychologie and its publisher, Mede cine et Hygiene, for permission to use the already published part of our material.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.