1 CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE IN 2 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS’ NATURAL LAW THEORY 3 TABLE OF CONTENTS 4 I. Opening statement................................................................4 5 II. Developing, examining, and answering the central question......6 6 A. Laying the groundwork .....................................................7 7 1. The preliminary assumptions.........................................7 8 2. The conditions for civil disobedience...............................8 9 3. The dismissive judgment issue in Aquinas’ law.................9 10 B. Summarizing Aquinas’ law...............................................13 11 1. Aquinas classifies the types of law. ..............................13 12 2. Aquinas’ natural law....................................................14 13 C. Answering the central question.........................................16 14 1. The basis for the assessment of laws............................16 15 2. The assessment of Aquinas’ laws..................................18 16 3. The court of conscience...............................................19 17 III. Passing muster on a ‘morally difficult case’...........................23 18 A. The abortion arguments..................................................23 19 1. A fetus is only a ‘potential human’................................24 20 2. A fetus is not an ‘actual human’....................................25 21 B. The replies from Aquinas’ court of conscience....................25 22 1. A reply to a fetus is only a ‘potential human’..................26 23 2. A reply to a fetus is not an ‘actual human’.....................27 24 IV. Summing up Aquinas’ civil disobedience...............................30 25 V. Closing statement...............................................................31 1 Page ii of 34 11/17/2013 26 CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE IN ST. THOMAS AQUINAS’ 27 NATURAL LAW THEORY 28 The purpose of this paper is to develop and explain ‘civil 29 disobedience’ based on Aquinas’ natural law theory. 30 I. Opening statement 31 The central question is, ‘Is civil disobedience allowed in Aquinas’ 32 natural law theory?’ If his theory allows civil disobedience, then it 33 must also answer: (1) how does an individual decide that a law is 34 unjust, (2) how does an individual make this decision concerning 35 just versus unjust; and (3) what does the individual do about an 36 unjust law?a These questions and the central question will be 37 answered in this paper. At the heart of the civil disobedience 38 question in Aquinas’ natural law theory is the dismissive judgmentb 39 issue, “that which is not just does not seem to me to be a law.”c Is 2 a Norman Kretzmann, “Lex Iniusta Non Est Lex: Laws on Trial in Aquinas’ Court 3 of Conscience,” Philosophy of Law, Eds. Joel Feinberg and Hyman Gross, 5th 4 ed. (Belmont: Wadsworth, 1995) 7-8. 5 b New Shorter Oxford English Dictionary, 5th ed. (Oxford: Oxford University, 6 2002) CD-ROM. Dismissive is defined as, "Of the nature of or characterized by 7 dismissal; tending to dismiss; suggesting unworthiness of any further 8 consideration; disdainful.” As such, a dismissive judgment is a judgment of an 9 object that is denied or dismissed as unworthy of any consideration. 10 c St. Augustine, De libero arbitrio, I v 11, Kretzmann 8. Kretzmann points out 11 that there is a problem between the quote from Augustine, “lex mihi esse non 12 videtur, quae iusta non fuerit” and the ‘quote’ “Lex iniusta non est lex”, some 13 philosophers attribute to Augustine and Aquinas. The later, “An unjust law is 14 not a law,” is opposed to the former, “To me that which is not just does not 15 seem to be a law.” 16 Page iii of 34 11/17/2013 40 it a paradoxical judgment for Aquinas? Alternatively, is it a 41 reasoned intellectual judgment for Aquinas? Finally, may humans 42 disobey an unjust law? As the basis for my developing my critical 43 analysis of this issue, I have chosen the argument from Norman 44 Kretzmann’s article “Lex Iniusta Non Est Lex: Laws on Trial in 45 Aquinas’ Court of Conscience.”d Kretzmann’s article provides a very 46 insightful analysis of the dismissive judgment issue. He analyzes 47 and draws a valid conclusion on dismissive judgment and the 48 central question of civil disobedience. Additionally, he provides an 49 excellent analysis of Aquinas’ motives for supporting this doctrine. 50 Finally, with a minor modification, Kretzmann’s argument provides 51 an answer to the civil disobedience issue. 52 However, developing, examining, and answering the question of 53 civil disobedience in Aquinas’ natural law theory is only the start. 54 Does Aquinas’ account of civil disobedience hold up when explaining 55 a modern civil disobedience case? To answer this, we will next 56 examine a modern civil disobedience case in Aquinas’ court of 57 conscience. Should an anti-abortion activist disobey the laws of the 58 United States to protect “unborn” children? Does civil disobedience 59 in Aquinas’ natural law theory pass muster on this ‘morally difficult 60 case’? 17 d Kretzmann 7-19. 18 Page iv of 34 11/17/2013 61 We will use the two verdicts developed from the discussion of 62 the central question to inspect this ‘morally difficult case’. First, 63 whether or not an ‘unjust law is no law’, as moral reasoning 64 individuals, we must learn to weigh the cost of disobeying the law 65 versus obeying the unjust law, i.e., obey by ‘turning the other 66 cheek’ for the good of society. Second, an ‘unjust law is no law’, as 67 creatures of a divine being, we must always be disobeyed, i.e., such 68 ‘an unjust law is no law’ and we have no choice but to disobey the 69 unjust law. Let us begin by developing and answering the central 70 question, “Is civil disobedience allowed in Aquinas’ natural law 71 theory?” 72 II. Developing, examining, and answering the central 73 question 74 The desideratum for answering the central question of civil 75 disobedience in Aquinas’ natural law theory is as follows. First, it is 76 essential to the theory that we understand Thomist civil 77 disobedience, i.e., whether the dismissive judgment, “an unjust law 78 is not a law”, is commonsensical or paradoxical and how can it be 79 used explain civil disobedience. We will begin by laying out the 80 preliminary groundwork, the assumptions, basis for the argument, 81 and the issue. Next, it is essential to the theory that we 19 Page v of 34 11/17/2013 82 understand Aquinas’ conception of law, in particular the relationship 83 of natural and human laws. We will summarize Aquinas’ four 84 classifications of law and the types to be used for this analysis. 85 Thirdly, it is essential to the theory that we understand the Thomist 86 view of dismissive judgment and its motives. This will sum up the 87 basis for an assessment of law, Aquinas’ assessment of law, and 88 assessment of law in the court of conscience, the agent intellect. 89 A. Laying the groundwork 90 Let us begin by outlining the preliminary assumptions, conditions 91 for civil disobedience, and the issue of how to determine the justice 92 of a law. 93 1. The preliminary assumptions 94 Kretzmann uses Aquinas’ system as a basis for his investigation. 95 The focus of the discussion is on disagreements between a moral 96 system and a legal system. As such, disagreements between 97 individuals over the moral assessment of laws (e.g., people arguing 98 over their individual assessments of a law as just or unjust) are to 99 be ignored. Kretzmann also writes that in a Thomist viewpoint, 100 there is a fundamental connection between moral philosophy and 101 Christian theology. As such, Aquinas’ legal system does not 20 Page vi of 34 11/17/2013 102 separate morality from theology (i.e., the human beings in Aquinas’ 103 society are Christians). Nevertheless, even with this linkage, a 104 secularized version of Aquinas is still proper for developing, 105 examining, and answering the question of civil disobedience.e 106 2. The conditions for civil disobedience 107 Dismissive judgment (i.e., a disdainful judgment that dismisses 108 thereby denying a premise or object) concerns whether a law is 109 unjust. However, in this moral judgment, what information must a 110 human being in a society need to determine justice? For 111 Kretzmann, the following questions must be answered concerning a 112 dismissive judgment of a law in terms of civil disobedience: f 1) can 21 e Kretzmann 7. And Frederick Copleston S.J., Aquinas, (Baltimore: Penguin 22 1957) 219. “[We] can say with truth that Aquinas believed in a set of 23 unalterable moral precepts. The question arises… whether [Aquinas’ moral] 24 theory is compatible with the empirical fact that different people and different 25 social groups [i.e., different religions] have divergent moral convictions [i.e., 26 religious convictions]…. [However, I make] the following relevant point, 27 namely that differences in moral convictions do not themselves constitute a 28 disproof of the theory…. For there might be an unchangeable moral law and 29 at the same time varying degrees of insight into the content of this law” [i.e., 30 reasoning humans in different social groups have just not ‘discovered’ the 31 unalterable moral law]. 32 f Joel Feinberg, “Civil Disobedience in the Modern World,” Philosophy of Law, 33 Eds. Joel Feinberg and Hyman Gross, 5th ed. (Belmont: Wadsworth, 1995) 34 121-123. Although Kretzmann does not specifically deal with what constitutes 35 ‘the act civil of disobedience’, which is also an important conclusion for a 36 discussion of civil disobedience. ‘The act of civil disobedience’ as ‘lawbreaking’ 37 against an unjust law can have distinct flavors. A Thomist ‘act of civil 38 disobedience’ according to Feinberg’s article would be defined as “not to 39 undermine authority but to protest its misuse.” Of the flavors in the article, 40 Rawl’s approach to the ‘act of civil disobedience’ seems best in terms of 41 Aquinas, as it requires the use of ‘reason’ to determine ‘the act of civil 42 disobedience’. Since the use of reasoning to determine ‘the act of civil 43 disobedience’ would seem to be a requirement for a Thomist theory. For 44 Aquinas then, ‘the act of civil disobedience’ would be similar to John Rawl’s 45 Page vii of 34 11/17/2013 113 an individual decide whether a law is unjust; 2) how can an 114 individual make such a decision; and 3) what can or should the 115 individual do about an unjust law. g However, which kind of 116 dismissive judgment should apply to the law and civil 117 disobedience?h 118 3. The dismissive judgment issue in Aquinas’ law 119 Every thing, being, or substance has inclusive conditions that 120 determine its completion. Law is a thing for Aquinas. An inclusive 121 condition, which could be either non-evaluative or evaluative, is a 122 “condition” that a thing, being, or substance must have to be 46 “conscientious refusal” than “warfare against the state.” (Especially 47 considering Aquinas’ ‘doctrine of the mean’ as well as ‘perversions of law’ as 48 developed respectively in Summa Theologica, I-II. Q. 64 A. 1 Obj. 3. and 49 Summa Theologica, I-II. Q. 92 A. 1 RObj. 3. Further, Aquinas does not seem 50 to advocate armed revolt which would be far away from the ‘mean’.) The ‘act 51 of civil disobedience’ requires four characteristics: (1) it must be public; (2) in 52 must be nonviolent; (3) it must be either direct or indirect deliberate 53 unlawfulness; and (4) it must be conscientiously aimed towards the ‘good of 54 society’. Therefore, a reasoned ‘the act of civil disobedience’ as “conscientious 55 refusal” seems to me in alignment with Thomist philosophy. 56 g Kretzmann 9. Kretzmann’s paper is contingent on the plausibility of the notion 57 of civil disobedience: its role, justification, and nature. Kretzmann deals 58 thoroughly with the justification for civil disobedience. However, Kretzmann 59 seems unaware in the article that he is facing a problem in the areas of the 60 role and nature of civil disobedience; I feel that he has left his argument open 61 to questioning in these two areas. In spite of this, for the purpose of this 62 paper I feel that we can properly explain Aquinas and civil disobedience 63 without specifically dealing with the distinctions concerning the role and nature 64 of civil disobedience. It seems to me that for Aquinas, an entitlement for the 65 ‘role of civil disobedience’ might be understood as both a ‘right’ and a ‘duty’ to 66 disobey the unjust law, i.e., for unjust laws vis-à-vis ‘divine law’ there is a 67 duty to civil disobedience and for unjust laws vis-à-vis ‘reasoning to the 68 natural law’ there is a mere right to civil disobedience. Please note: The 69 ‘nature’ or the act of civil disobedience was discussed in a previous footnote. 70 Thank you to Dr. Corlett for pointing out this problem with Kretzmann’s article. 71 h Kretzmann 7-8. 72 Page viii of 34 11/17/2013 123 considered complete. Non-evaluative means that the thing simply 124 has the condition (e.g., the leg of a chair is a non-evaluative 125 condition of “chair-ness”). Evaluative conditions are abstracted by 126 reason to determine whether the conditions for inclusion in the form 127 of the thing have been met (e.g., “masterpiece” is an evaluative 128 condition of “musical masterpiece”, because an evaluation must be 129 made to determine inclusion).i 130 There are two of the kinds of things: non-natural conventional 131 kinds and natural conventional kinds.j Of non-natural conventional 132 kinds, their inclusive conditions are non-evaluative (e.g., for a 133 Haiku poem or soldier, they simply need to meet the defining 134 conditions). Of the natural conventional kinds, some are overtly 135 and invariably evaluative. An example of this would be fine artwork 136 or gifted person where an evaluation determines whether the 137 condition is met for its inclusion. There are also natural 138 conventional kinds that are not overtly or invariably evaluative. 139 Evaluative conditions that are not overt involve implicit evaluative 140 conditions and are linked with things that have a familiar human 141 function. An illustration of this would be artwork or anthropologist. 142 For these kinds of things with non-overt evaluative conditions, the 73 i Kretzmann 8. 74 j Kretzmann 8. 75 Page ix of 34 11/17/2013 143 non-evaluative conditions must be met before applying the 144 evaluative (i.e., “He is no general,” makes sense only if “A bad 145 general is not really a general, despite the fact that he holds the 146 rank and commands an army”). Is it the natural conventional kind 147 of things, with conditions that are both non-evaluative and 148 evaluative, but not overtly or invariably evaluative, and has an 149 important human function, which is the appropriate kind to apply 150 dismissive judgment?k It is here that Kretzmann’s argument has a 151 problem interpreting Aquinas. 152 The problem with Kretzmann’s argument is, “How do you explain 153 ‘without being overtly evaluative’ condition in Aquinas?” l The 154 etymology of ‘overt’ is the Latin word aperire–exposed to view or 155 knowledge, open, evident, straightforward.m Is Kretzmann correctly 156 saying, “Without being exposed, evident and open to knowledge”? 157 Is this not a contradiction of Aquinas’ writings? For Aquinas, 158 humans possess a unique inclination towards reason.n This 76 k Kretzmann 9. 77 l There is another problem, that of conscientia or synderesis? Which 78 ‘conscience’ from Aquinas do you use? [Aquinas, Summa Theologica, I. Q. 79 79 A. 12 and I. Q. 79 A. 13. The Human Constitution, trans. Richard Regan, 80 (Scranton: University of Scranton Press, 1997) 75-78.] While Kretzmann 81 points out that he is aware that he is facing a problem in this area, I feel that 82 he has left his argument open to question form this area as well. However, for 83 the purpose of this paper I feel that we can properly explain Aquinas and civil 84 disobedience without specifically dealing with this distinction. 85 m The Shorter Oxford English Dictionary. 86 n St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, I. Q. 79 A. 4 and I. Q. 79 A. 8, The 87 Human Constitution, trans. Richard Regan, (Scranton: University of Scranton 88 Press, 1997) 57. 89 Page x of 34 11/17/2013
Description: