ebook img

CAUSALITY, MEMORY ERASING AND DELAYED CHOICE EXPERIMENTS PDF

4 Pages·0.05 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview CAUSALITY, MEMORY ERASING AND DELAYED CHOICE EXPERIMENTS

Causality, Memory Erasing and Delayed Choice Experiments 5 9 9 1 n Y. Aharonova,b, S. Popescua and L. Vaidmana a J 8 a School of Physics and Astronomy 1 v 6 Raymond and Beverly Sackler Faculty of Exact Sciences 0 0 Tel–Aviv University, Tel–Aviv 69978 ISRAEL 1 0 5 9 b Physics Department / h p University of South Carolina - t n Columbia, South Carolina 29208 a u q : v Recently, Ingraham [1] suggested “a delayed-choice experiment with par- i X tial, controllable memory erasing”. We shall show that he cannot be right r a since his predictions contradict relativistic causality. We shall explain a sub- tle quantum effect which was overlooked by Ingraham. LetusfirstsketchIngraham’sargument. Heconsideredtwoatomslocated close to each other. The atoms have four relevant levels: the ground state c | i and three excited levels, a , b , b . The first laser pulse puts the atoms into ′ | i | i | i the superposition 1 ( a c + c a ). The atom in the state a immediately 1 2 1 2 √2 | i | i | i 1 emits a photon γ and ends up in the state b . Then the quantum evolution | i of the system is: 1 1 ( a c + c a ) ( b c γ + c b γ ) (1) 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 1 2 2 √2 | i | i → √2 | i| i | i| i We are looking for an interference between the states of the photon γ emitted from the two atoms on a distant screen. Since there is a “memory” in the atoms of which atom emitted the photon (the state b ), no interference | i pattern is expected. Now we add a second pulse, after the first one, but before the photon γ reaches the screen. The second pulse excites the atom in the state b to the | i state b whichimmediatelydecaystothegroundstate c andemitsaphoton ′ | i | i φ. In the limiting case, when the wavelength of the photon φ is much larger than the distance between the atoms, the states φ and φ of the photon 1 2 emitted from the two atoms are practically identical, φ φ φ . 1 2 | i ≃ | i ≡ | i Therefore, thememoryofwhichatomemittedthephotonγ iserased. Indeed, the quantum evolution is 1 1 1 ( b c γ + c b γ ) ( b c γ + c b γ ) c c φ ( γ + γ ) 1 2 1 1 2 2 ′1 2 1 1 ′2 2 1 2 1 2 √2 | i| i | i| i → √2 | i| i | i| i → √2| i| i | i | i (2) Consequently, in the experiment with these two laser pulses we expect to see an interference pattern on the screen. If the above analysis were correct we could send signals faster than light in the following way. Consider an experiment performed on an ensemble 2 of such pairs of atoms. Bob, who has to receive the signal, is prepared to measure the interference pattern on the screen. Alice, who is located near the atoms, decides to apply or not to apply the second laser pulse. Bob will see the interference pattern, only if Alice applied the second pulse. Thus, Bob will know Alice’s decision with superluminal velocity. The argument of Ingraham is based on the fact that before the second laser pulse the two states b c and c b are practically orthogonal, while 1 2 1 2 | i | i after the second pulse they evolve into the states c c φ and c c φ 1 2 1 1 2 2 | i| i | i| i which are practically identical since φ , the state of the photon emitted by 1 | i the first atom is almost identical to φ , emitted by the second atom. This 2 | i process violates the unitarity of quantum theory and, therefore, it cannot take place. But where is the mistake? The resolution is somewhat subtle. It is true that a single atom in the state b immediately radiates photon φ. ′ | i However, if we put another atom in the ground state very close to the first one (such that the scalar product of the states of the photon emitted from thetwo locationsapproximately equals 1), theprobabilityto emit the photon reduces to 1/2 [2]. Indeed, while in the symmetric state Ψ = 1 ( b c + | +i √2 | ′1 2i c b ) the atoms emit the photon φ immediately, in the antisymmetric state 1 ′2 | i Ψ = 1 ( b c c b ) the atoms can not emit the photon. One can | −i √2 | ′1 2i − | 1 ′2i understand this phenomenon as a destructive interference between the states of the photon emitted by the two atoms in the antisymmetric state. The 3 correct evolution, instead of Eq. (2) is: 1 1 ( b c γ + c b γ ) = ( Ψ + Ψ ) γ +( Ψ Ψ ) γ √2 | ′1 2i| 1i | 1 ′2i| 2i 2(cid:16) | +i | −i | 1i | +i−| −i | 2i(cid:17) → 1 ( c c φ + Ψ ) γ +( c c φ Ψ ) γ (3) (cid:16) 1 2 1 1 2 2 (cid:17) 2 | i| i | −i | i | i| i−| −i | i Since the states 1 ( c c φ + Ψ ) and 1 ( c c φ Ψ ) are orthogonal, 1 2 1 2 √2 | i| i | −i √2 | i| i−| −i there is no memory erasing. (Since the states φ and φ are not exactly 1 2 | i | i orthogonal, the state Ψ is actually only a metastable state and it will | −i finally decay emitting a photon φ . However, since it can be emitted only ′ long after the emission time of φ, the state φ is practically orthogonal to ′ | i φ . Thus, after the final decay, the memory is stored in the photon state.) | i One may suspect that since the photon states γ and γ are obtained 1 2 | i | i by emission from the same very close atoms, similar phenomena will happen when the photon γ is emitted. This, however, is not the case: In order to be able to yield an interference pattern the wavelength of γ has to be taken smaller than the distance between the atoms and therefore the photon states γ and γ are almost orthogonal. 1 2 | i | i References [1] R.L. Ingraham, Phys. Rev. A 50, 4502 (1994) [2] R.H. Dicke, Phys. Rev. 93, 99 (1954). 4

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.