STUDIES IN POLITICAL ECONOMY edited by John Eatwell Capital and Employment: A Study of Keynes's Economics, Murray Milgate, 1982 Gifts and Commodities, C. A. Gregory, 1982 The Economic Structure of Backward Agriculture, A. Bhaduri, 1983 CAPITAL AND EMPLOYMENT A Study of Keynes's Economics MURRAY MILGATE 1982 ACADEMIC PRESS A Subsidiary of Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, Publishers London New York Paris San Diego San Francisco Sâo Paulo Sydney Tokyo Toronto ACADEMIC PRESS INC. (LONDON) LTD. 24/28 Oval Road London NWi United States Edition published by ACADEMIC PRESS INC. 111 Fifth Avenue New York, New York 10003 Copyright © 1982 by ACADEMIC PRESS INC. (LONDON) LTD. All Rights Reserved No part of this book may be reproduced in any form by photostat, microfilm, or any other means, without permission from the publishers Bntish Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Milgate, M. Capital and employment.—(Studies in political economy; 1) 1. Keynes, John Maynard 2. Keynesian economics I. Title II. Series 330.I5'6 HB99.7 ISBN O-I2-49625O-5 LCCCN 82-73227 Photoset in Great Britain by Rowland Phototypesetting Ltd, Bury St Edmunds, Suffolk and printed by St Edmundsbury Press, Bury St Edmunds, Suffolk Series Editor's Preface The revival of the analytical principles of classical political economy that has gathered pace since the mid-1960s has been based on the firm foundation of a logically coherent theory of value and distribution. It was the failure to provide this foundation which for many years confined the classical approach to being, at best, a repository of useful ideas on growth and technological progress (Smith's discussion of the division of labour and Marx's dissection of the labour process being good examples), or at worst, identified with simple-minded devotion to the labour theory of value as the 'qualitative' expression of capitalist exploitation—the position to which Hilferding retreated in the face of Böhm-Bawerk's critique of Marx, so depriving the surplus approach of any quantitative significance as a theory of value and distribution. The publication of Piero Sraffa's Production of Commodities by Means of Commodities changed all that. Sraffa not only generalised the mathema tical solutions to the surplus approach which had been advanced by Dmitriev and Bortkeiwicz, but also presented the analytical structure of the surplus approach with stark clarity. Moreover, Sraffa provided a critique of the neoclassical theory of the rate of profit and so of the entire neoclassical explanation of value, distribution and output—hence clearing the ground for the redevelopment of classical theory. With the analytical core now secure, attention can be turned to the development of other facets of classical and Marxian theory and to the empirical insights which this theory provides. In stark contrast to the neoclassical approach, which reduces all economic activity to a single principle—the competitive resolution of individual attempts to maxi mise utility subject to the constraints of technology and endowment— classical theory is constructed from a number of analytically separable components. The core of the theory, the surplus approach to value and distribution, takes as data the size and composition of output, the technology in use (the conditions of reproduction) and the real wage (or, in some cases, the rate of profit). These data do not, however, lie outside the realm of economics (as, for example, the neoclassical economists' utility functions do). We need to provide theoretical explanations of VI SERIES EDITOR'S PREFACE their determination. Hence Smith, Ricardo and Marx advanced theories of the real wage and of the level of output (Say's law in the case of Ricardo), and Smith and Marx presented detailed analyses of technological change. Assembled around the core, these theories are the building blocks of a general theory of the operations of the capitalist economy. There is in all this a clear danger of constructing a disjointed ad hoc collage of theories and empirical generalisations. This is avoided by enveloping the entire edifice in a general characterisation of the economic system: the clear specification, that is, of the capitalist mode of production. This serves both to cement the elements of the theory together and to eliminate propositions that do not fit. This series of books is devoted to studies which develop and extend the classical framework. Broadly, there are two jobs to be done. First, the classical theory itself must be developed and generalised. All the elements surrounding the core analysis of value and distribu tion—theories of output and employment, of accumulation, of technol ogy, of the wage, of competition and so on—require reassessment and 'modernisation' in the light both of Sraffa's results and of the many changing facets of the modern capitalist system. This will involve both theoretical development and empirical analysis. For one of the import ant characteristics of classical theorising is the manner in which theory is grounded in the socio-economic data of the system under considera tion. The institutional environment is an essential part of the theory. Second, the rejection of the now discredited neoclassical theory throws open a wide range of problems in international trade, develop ment economics, fiscal and monetary policy and so forth, into which the classical approach can provide new insights. In part these will lead to the refreshing task of debunking the policy prescriptions of orthodox theory which revolve primarily around the fundamental theorem of welfare economics and the supposed 'efficiency' of competitive mar kets. But there is also a positive job to be done. The reconstruction of economic theory will inevitably precipitate a reinterpretation of econo mic policy and problems. In this book Murray Milgate pursues the task of reassessing Keynes's theory of effective demand in the light of developments in the theory of value and distribution. The argument sweeps away the considerable accretion of confusion that has built up around the theory of output and employment since the publication of Keynes's General Theory, confu sion which has stemmed primarily from vain attempts to integrate SERIES EDITOR'S PREFACE Vil Keynes's ideas into the corpus of neoclassical theory by means of a variety of arbitrary assumptions—'sticky' wages, the effects of uncer tainty and expectations, short run rigidities and the like. Milgate not only presents a more coherent interpretation of the debates surrounding Keynes's ideas than has hitherto been available, but also points to the important theoretical compatability between the classical analysis of value and distribution and Keynes's theory of output. John Eatwell Trinity College, Cambridge September, 1982 Preface This work is offered as a contribution to a new and promising line of inquiry into Keynesian Economics opened up by the recent contribu tions of Pierangelo Garegnani. It has its roots in the economic theory of the old Classical Economists from Adam Smith down to Marx and, more recently, Piero Sraffa. Its essential ingredient is the rejection of the orthodox marginalist vision of the economic system operating according to the principles of demand and supply theory. This work seeks to show that not only is this the upshot of recent controversies in the theory of capital, but also that it is the course suggested by Keynes's contribution to the theory of employment. Its primary aim is to re-examine the nature of Keynes's contribution to economic theory and, following from this, to review critically dominant contemporary interpretations of Keynes's work. The work also seeks to isolate the linkages which exist between Keynes's theory of output and employ ment on the one hand, and the surplus approach to value and distribu tion of the old Classical Economists on the other. While the primary focus of the work is, so to speak, theoretical, its central conclusions embody important messages for the conduct of economic policy. In particular, while they suggest that the adoption of Keynesian policies is desirable, they also imply that this does not entail a return to those simplistic 'fine tuning' policies that became the norm after the Second World War. If the interpretation of Keynes's contribution that is given in this work is accepted, it implies the need for a much more interven tionist stance than has hitherto been thought to be theoretically justi fied. I should like to thank Dr John Eatwell for his aid and advice over the period which led up to the completion of this book. I should like also to thank Professors Pierangelo Garegnani, Luigi Pasinetti and Joan Robinson for their comments on earlier drafts of parts of this work. Though my reading of Keynes may not concur, on every point, with theirs, it will be obvious to the reader how profound has been their influence upon my thinking. It goes without saying that all errors and misinterpretations are my own responsibility. MURRAY MILGATE Cambridge, June iç82 I. INTRODUCTION It appears to me that one great cause of our difference of opinion ... is that you have always in your mind the immediate and temporary effects of particular changes—whereas I ... fix my whole attention on the perma nent state of things which will result from them. Perhaps you estimate these temporary effects too highly, whilst I am too much disposed to undervalue them. To manage the subject quite right they should be carefully distinguished and mentioned, and the due effects ascribed to each. (Ricardo to Malthus, 1817, in Ricardo, 1951—1973, vol. VII, p. 120). Controversy over the significance of Keynes's General Theory as a theoretical work has continued virtually undiminished since its publi cation in 1936. However, although a wide variety of themes have been aired, two basic issues have been central to the questions that in terpreters of Keynes's work have sought to resolve. On the one hand, there has been the attempt to reveal the precise nature of the construc tive theoretical contribution of the General Theory and, on the other, there has been the consequent attempt to provide an understanding of the significance of Keynes's ideas as a critique of received opinion. Of course, these two issues are not unrelated. Any interpretation of the General Theory must seek to resolve them both. But a separate treatment of these two topics provides a particularly clear and precise way of approaching the problem of the interpretation of the General Theory. For this reason the present examination of Keynes's contribution, and the associated critical analysis of subsequent interpretations of the General Theory, will be developed by addressing each of these issues in turn. 1 2 CAPITAL AND EMPLOYMENT A. THE CONTEMPORARY POSITION OF 'KEYNESIAN' ECONOMICS If one considers the dominant contemporary interpretations of the General Theory, two important sub-divisions may be isolated. There is one school that regards the constructive contribution of that book to consist exclusively of an examination of the short-period behaviour of the economic system. That is, the General Theory is seen to provide a detailed analysis of what Ricardo referred to in the passage quoted at the opening of this chapter as the temporary effects of particular changes. Accordingly, the significance of the General Theory as a critique of received opinion is, at most, that it draws our attention to the fact that the underlying forces working towards the establishment of long-period equilibrium, while always present, are only weakly felt. The basic idea is that the economic system may become 'stuck', so to speak, in a short-period position where certain frictions or rigidities prevent the systematic forces outlined by orthodox marginalist theory from produc ing those permanent effects that they ultimately have a tendency to produce. This view may be associated, in particular, with the interpretations advanced by Hicks in his famous 'Mr Keynes and the classics' paper of 1937, and by Modigliani in his equally celebrated paper 'Liquidity preference and the theory of interest and money' of 1944. Interestingly, it was also the position adopted by Pigou in his self-styled recapitulation on the question of the significance of the General Theory in 1949, where it was argued that Keynes's purpose was to deal with "fluctuations over short periods" as distinct from questions about the "ultimate equilib rium" of the system (Pigou, 1950, pp. 3-4). Subscribing to the same school of thought, Schumpeter in his History of Economic Analysis was led to the conclusion that it would have been better had Keynes not objected to the tendency towards full employment "just as we do not object to the law of gravitation on the ground that the earth does not fall into the sun"; rather Keynes really meant "that. . . though it states a tendency correctly, [its operation] is impeded by certain facts" (1954, p. 624). Though it will be necessary later to define these terms more precisely (for the notion of equilibrium itself has changed in recent years), the general tenor of these interpretations is captured in the idea that Keynes's contribution was to 'disequilibrium' rather than to 'equilibrium' analysis. I. INTRODUCTION 3 So complete has been the triumph of this theme in the practice of Keynes's interpretation, that its presence is apparent everywhere in much more recent re-interpretations—despite the fact that one signifi cant alteration (to the notion of equilibrium), which will be mentioned in a moment, has been introduced. Thus, for example, in the well- known contributions of Leijonhufvud the essential ingredient of the old view is still to be found. "Of course", Leijonhufvud writes, "Keynes used the term 'unemployment equilibrium'. [But] ... it is not an 'equilibrium' in the strict sense at all. It is preferable to use some more neutral term which does not carry the connotation that no equilibrating forces at all are at work. The real question is why . . . the forces tending to bring the system back to full employment are so weak" (1969, p. 22, n. 1). Similarly, in his study of the development of Keynes's monetary thought, Patinkin (1976) concluded that Keynes's theory is not "strict ly speaking" one of "unemployment equilibrium" (p. 114 et seq.). And James Tobin, in a recent exposé of the shortcomings of modern monetarist doctrines, although at one point recognising that Keynes "denies the existence of self-correcting market mechanisms . . . [even] in a competitive economy" (1980, pp. 1-2), refrains from drawing the radical conclusions that would follow from this assessment and falls back instead on the idea that Keynes showed (only) that "disequilib rium can be protracted and stubborn" (p. 19). Indeed, a list of the names of those writers in whose work this familiar theme is present would be enough to dominate, if not fill, the membership of an economics Hall of Fame. However, the popularity of this view does not render it correct. The interpretation of Keynes's contribution that is presented in these pages breaks away entirely from this line of argument. Its starting point is to take seriously Keynes's claim, universally and disingenuously rejected as being not quite accurate by orthodox interpretations, that the dominant and systematic forces at work in market economies do not tend to produce the full employment of labour. Instead of arguing that Keynes shared with orthodox economics the same abstract character isation of the mechanisms through which market economies operate and differed by claiming that these mechanisms were not always as beneficent in the actual world as they were in theory, it will be my central contention that Keynes in fact rejected the orthodox character isation of the operation of the market mechanism. In short, in the General Theory Keynes provides us with a theory of employment