ebook img

Beyond Reason: Essays on the Philosophy of Paul Feyerabend PDF

543 Pages·1991·15.35 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Beyond Reason: Essays on the Philosophy of Paul Feyerabend

BEYOND REASON BOSTON STUDIES IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Editor ROBERT S. COHEN, Boston University Editorial Advisory Board ADOLF GRONBAUM, University of Pittsburgh SYLVAN S. SCHWEBER, Brandeis University JOHN J. STACHEL, Boston University MARX W. WARTOFSKY, Baruch College of the City University ofN ew York VOLUME 132 BEYOND REASON Essays on the Philosophy of Paul Feyerabend Edited by GONZALO MUNEVA R The Evergreen State College, Washington, U.SA. SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B.V. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Beyond reason : essays an the philosophy of Pau; Feyerabend I edited by Gonzalo Munevar. p. cm. -- (Boston studies in the philosophy of science ; v. 132) "Most of the essays in this festschrift were originally published in German in Hans Peter Duerr's ed., Versuchungen Aufsătze zur Phi losophie Paul Feyerabends, Shurkamp Verlag, Frankfurt am Main, 1980"--P. ISBN 978-94-010-5406-5 ISBN 978-94-011-3188-9 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-011-3188-9 1. Feyerabend, Paul K., 1924- 1. Feyerabend, Paul K., 1924- II. Munevar, Gonzalo. III. Versuchungen Aufsătze zur Philosophie Paul Feyerabends. IV. Ser ies. B3240.F484B49 1991 193--dc20 91-17470 ISBN 978-94-010-5406-5 printed on acid-free paper AlI Rights Reserved © 1991 by Springer-Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 1991 Softcover reprint ofthe hardcover Ist edition 1991 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner. "What I really am, a dishwasher", Table of Contents GONZALO MONEV AR / Introduction ix ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS xxi 1. PAULM. CHURCHLAND / A Deeper Unity: Some Feyerabendian Themes in Neurocomputational Form 1 2. MARX W. W ARTOFSKY / How to Be a Good Realist 25 3. C.A. HOOKER / Between Formalism and Anarchism: A Reasonable Middle Way 41 4. ALASTAIR HANNAY / Free of Prejudice and Wholly Critical 109 5. IAN HACKING / Speculation, Calculation and the Creation of Phenomena 131 6. JOHN KEKES / Reason and Practice 159 7. GONZALO MONEVA R / Science in Feyerabend's Free Society 179 8. MARGHERIT A VON BRENTA NO / Letter to an Anti- Liberal Liberal 199 9. WERNER DIEDERICH / Obituary on the "Anarchist" Paul Feyerabend 213 10. NORETTA KOERTGE / Ideology, Science and a Free Society 225 11. ALAN MUSGRA VB / The Myth of Astronomical Instrumen- talism 243 12. GUNNAR ANDERSSON / Feyerabend on Falsifications, Galileo, and Lady Reason 281 Vll viii TABLE OF CONTENTS 13. FREDERICK SUPPE / The Observational Origins of Feyerabend's Anarchistic Epistemology 297 14. ANTHONY N. PEROVICH, Jr. / Incommensurability, its Varieties and its Ontological Consequences 313 15. JOHN WORRALL / Feyerabend and the Facts 329 16. JEROME R. RA YETZ / Ideological Commitments in the Philosophy of Science 355 17. JOSEPH AGASSI / As You Like It 379 18. VINE DELORIA / Perceptions and Maturity: Reflections on Feyerabend's Point of View 389 19. ARNE NAESS / Paul Feyerabend - a Green Hero? 403 20. HERBERT HORZ / Ecology as a Challenge to Philosophy 417 21. HERBERT SCHNADELBACH / Against Feyerabend 433 22. DWIGHT VA N DE VA TE, JR. / A New Slant on the Tower Experiment 449 23. GROVER MAXWELL / Feyerabend's Materialism 453 24. JOSEPH MARGOLIS / Scientific Methods and Feyerabend's Advocacy of Anarchism 465 25. PAUL K. FEYERABEND / Concluding Unphilosophical Conversation 487 INDEX 529 GONZALO MUNEV AR Introduction Some philosophers think that Paul Feyerabend is a clown, a great many others think that he is one of the most exciting philosophers of science of this century. For me the truth does not lie somewhere in between, for I am decidedly of the second opinion, an opinion that is becoming general around the world as this century comes to an end and history begins to cast its appraising eye upon the intellectual harvest of our era. A good example of this opinion may be found in the admiration for Feyerabend's philosophy of science expressed by Grover Maxwell in his contribution to this volume. Maxwell, recalling his own intellectual transformation, says also that it was Feyerabend who "confirmed my then incipient suspicions that most of the foundations of currently fashionable philosophy and even a great deal of the methodology to which many scientists pay enthusiastic lip service are based on simple mistakes - assumptions whose absurdity becomes obvious once attention is directed at them". And lest the reader thinks, as many still do, that however sharp Feyerabend's attacks upon the philosophical establishment may have been, he does not offer a positive philosophy (a complain made by C.A. Hooker and some of the other contributors), Paul Churchland argues otherwise. Churchland points out several claims extracted from Feyerabend' s philosophy of science and views on materialism which violated many of the crucial tenets of the dominant philosophy in the 60's: that perceptual knowledge is never ideologically neutral, that the commonsense framework of our mental lives could be replaced by a materialist framework, that competing views occasionally are incommensurable, that scientific progress occasionally requires the proliferation of alternative IX G. Munevar (ed.), Beyond Reason, ix-xx. © 1991 Kluwer Academic Publishers. x INTRODUCfION theories, as well as of alternative methodologies. Indeed, Churchland says, most analytic philosophers "still find these claims to be individually repugnant and collectively confusing". Nevertheless recent developments in experimental neuroscience incorporate and make very plausible all of those claims by Peyerabend. What may have looked like a negative philosophy from a certain vantage point, now serves as part of the conceptual foundation of a new and exciting understanding of the mind (Churchland is particularly interested in the connectionist approach to the nature of the brain - an approach that has risen, incidentally, as a serious challenger to traditional Artificial Intelligence, a field closely allied with analytic philosophy). The reader may wish to contrast Churchland's contribution with Maxwell's more traditional appraisal of Peyerabend's materialism. Controversial figures like Peyerabend often elicit strong responses and their work provokes no end of misunderstandings, just as it also provides opportunities for new developments. In the essays collected in these pages the reader will find ample evidence for these remarks. As examples of very strong responses I can point to, among others, the essays by Joseph Agassi and Vine Deloria. The first goes beyond the customary bounds of academic essays into what may be fairly called a sustained and very strong personal attack against Peyerabend (Agassi argues that Peyerabend's philosophy could give comfort to a Nazi ideology, and he believes, given his acquaintance with Peyerabend, that such result is no accident). The second, by contrast, argues that Peyerabend is one of the few thinkers who make a serious case for treating all the peoples of the planet with respect. This is so, at least in part, because Peyerabend, as Deloria says, sees that the contributions of non-Western cultures should not be limited merely to adding to an "already constructed edifice of Western knowledge". The content of human knowledge should instead be "a discontinuous arrangement of smaller bodies of knowledge derived from the many traditions represented in planetary history". When I was an undergraduate social concerns were not topics fit for discussion in the philosophy of science. Some decry this transformation of the field, others feel intellectually liberated by it. But they can all recognize that Peyerabend had a good part in bringing it about. Of course, that certain topics were not brought up does not imply that philosophy of science never made (implicit?) ideological commitments of a moral, social, or political nature. Jerome Ravetz argues that philosophy of science did make such commitments and tries to expose them in his INlRODUCTION xi account of the history of the Vienna Circle, Popper, Kuhn, Lakatos, and finally Feyerabend. The first, decisive step in the transformation of the field came when Feyerabend (and Thomas Kuhn) showed, by a series of analyses of crucial episodes in the history of the physical sciences, that the "facts" used by scientists to pass judgement upon scientific theories are them selves based on theoretical assumptions, and are thus also theoretical. And here I include "facts" apparently as straightforward as the vertical motion of a stone as it is dropped from a tower (a fact which was long considered as a refutation of the rotation of the earth). From Feyerabend' s analysis of the Tower Argument it became clear that such fact assumed, among other things, an operationist concept of motion (motion as observable displacement), that is, a properly empiricist concept, whereas Galileo introduced unobservable, theoretical components into the motions of bodies. I place emphasis on this assumption rather than on the assump tion that space was absolute, although the relation is close, because it serves to remind us that in that particular episode the Aristotelians, the losers, were on the side of methodological propriety. For this has been one of Feyerabend's main themes: that on occasion scientific method must be violated if progress is to result (progress as determined by today' s science). This limitation on method, on any method conceived according to the canons of traditional empiricism, was an unavoidable consequence of the breakdown of the distinction between theory and "fact" (as given by experience). For at the very heart of empiricism was the belief that experience had epistemological priority over theory. But if "facts" are theoretical too, instead of a clash between theory and fact (to be resolved in favor of fact) we ultimately have a clash between theory and theory. Thus it is possible that on occasion the theory under trial should overturn the verdict of the facts. Indeed many of the great developments in the history of science could not have come about otherwise. Many philosophers of science have come to accept a position along these lines to the degree that Feyerabend's work must seem to them full of truisms (although, it seems to me, rather in the manner that Shakespeare's is full of cliches). But others will resist. John Worrall, in this volume, resurrects Poincare's distinction between scientific and crude facts, and argues that this is all it takes to rescue empiricism from Feyerabend. Once we accept this distinction there remains a core of sensible things that Feyerabend has said, but those can be better accom-

Description:
Some philosophers think that Paul Feyerabend is a clown, a great many others think that he is one of the most exciting philosophers of science of this century. For me the truth does not lie somewhere in between, for I am decidedly of the second opinion, an opinion that is becoming general around the
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.