ebook img

Between Philosophy and Poetry PDF

230 Pages·2002·0.757 MB·230\230
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Between Philosophy and Poetry

BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND POETRY TEXTURES – PHILOSOPHY/LITERATURE/CULTURE SERIES Series editor: Hugh J. Silverman, Stony Brook University, Stony Brook, New York, USA An interdisciplinary series, Textures addresses questions of cultural meaning, difference, and experience. Extreme Beauty: Aesthetics, Politics, Death Edited by James E. Swearingen and Joanne Cutting-Gray Thresholds of Western Culture: Identity, Postcoloniality, Transnationalism Edited by John Burt Foster Jr. and Wayne J. Froman Panorama: Philosophies of the Visible Edited by Wilhelm S. Wurzer Between Philosophy and Poetry: Writing, Rhythm, History Edited by Massimo Verdicchio and Robert Burch B E T W E E N P H I L O S O P H Y A N D P O E T RY WRITING, RHYTHM, HISTORY EDITED BY MASSIMO VERDICCHIO AND ROBERT BURCH Continuum The Tower Building, 11 York Road, London, SE1 7NX 370 Lexington Avenue, New York, NY 10017–6503 First published 2002 © Massimo Verdicchio, Robert Burch and the contributors 2002 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, or transmitted in any form, or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. ISBN 0–8264–6005–4 (hardback) 0–8264–6006–2 (paperback) Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Between philosophy and poetry: writing, rhythm, and history / edited by Massimo Verdicchio and Robert Burch. p. cm — (Textures) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0–8264–6005–4 — ISBN 0–8264–6006–2 (pbk.) 1. Philosophy. 2. Poetry. I. Verdicchio, Massimo, 1945–. II. Burch, Robert, 1949–. III. Textures (New York, N.Y.) B66 .B48 2002 101—dc21 2002074053 Typeset by RefineCatch Limited, Bungay, Suffolk Printed and bound in Great Britain by Biddles Ltd, Guildford and King’s Lynn CONTENTS General Introduction: Thinking Between Philosophy and Poetry 1 Robert Burch Part One: Ethics of Writing Introduction 11 1 Gesture and Word: The Practice of Philosophy and the Practice of Poetry 15 Carlo Sini 2 The Rise and Fall of Reality: Socrates, Virtual Reality, and the Birth of Philosophy from the “Spirit of Writing” 27 Alessandro Carrera 3 Analogical Thinking as a Friend of Interpretive Truth: Reflections Based on Carlo Sini’s Images of Truth 41 Forrest Williams Part Two: Truth, Texts, and the Narrative Self Introduction 59 4 When Truth Becomes Woman: Male Traces and Female Signs 63 Eve Tavor Bannet 5 Orality and Writing: Plato’s Phaedrus and the Pharmakon Revisited 73 P. Christopher Smith 6 Ethics of the Narrative Self 91 Richard Kearney Part Three: Poetry, Philosophy, and the Spirit of History Introduction 101 7 Woburn on My Mind and in My (Mind’s) Eye: Beckett’s Poi¯esis 105 Stephen Barker vi CONTENTS 8 The Naming of the Hymn: Heidegger and Hölderlin 117 Karen Feldman 9 On Transvaluing History: Rilke and Nietzsche 125 Richard Detsch Part Four: The “Force of Rhythm” in Life, Philosophy, and Poetry Introduction 139 10 Reflections on Speed 143 David Halliburton 11 The Meaning of Rhythm 161 Amittai Aviram 12 Mousike¯ Techn¯e: The Philosophical Practice of Music in Plato, Nietzsche, and Heidegger 171 Babette E. Babich Abbreviations 181 Notes 185 Bibliography 207 Index 215 Acknowledgments 219 Contributors 221 Editors 223 GENERAL INTRODUCTION THINKING BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND POETRY Robert Burch Ever since Plato banished poetry from the just regime – ironically, in a dia- logue that has itself an essential narrative structure, an eiko¯n at its “logical” center, and a myth at its conclusion – philosophy has looked askance at the poetic. Metaphors, figures of speech, dramatic flourishes may be thought to favor or hinder the exposition and promulgation of philosophical truths, but as a rule they are judged accidental to the truth attained. In the extreme version of this story, the accidental is cast as decidedly villainous. Not merely is “figurative language” so much “frippery ornament” to the essential tasks of philosophy, as for example Jeremy Bentham warns, but in its ambiguity and pretence to real reference, it is virtually “unclean,” befuddling and upstaging the “majestic simplicity of good sound sense.”1 Thus portrayed, the true danger of figurative language does not lie in its being literally false but in its being a sham, a mere “semblance of thinking,” a Scheingedanke in Frege’s words, that comes on the scene unabashedly as if it possessed a genuine truth-value.2 Nowadays, however, this story is often told with a quite different plot, moral, and characterization. In place of the primacy of nominal reference, we are now advised à la Saussure “that signs, taken singly, do not signify anything, that each one of them does not so much express a meaning as mark a divergence of meaning between itself and other signs.” Accordingly, “the ability of lan- guage to signify a thought or a thing directly is only a secondary power derived from the inner life of language” itself.3 It follows then that metaphors and the like cannot be straightway condemned as obvious deviations from an original literal purity, and thereby as departures from “serious speech” and “truth,” since on this account literal references themselves come into play only through a prior interaction of signs. This tale, too, has its extreme version. Linguistic meaning is not only said to originate from the interactions of signs, but this interaction is also held to be both “omni-” and “infinite,” constituting a “differ- ential network” in which “nothing, neither among the elements nor within the system, is anywhere ever simply present or absent. There is only everywhere 2 BETWEEN PHILOSOPHY AND POETRY differences and traces of traces.”4 In this version of the story, the traditional role of philosophy – to make the absent, occluded “true in itself” totally present by means of the “literal” word – is played out as merely one more substitution within an open-ended interweaving of text. Traditional philosophy is thus deprivileged, not on skeptical grounds that its word falls short of what lies outside it, but because this story admits of no “outside” to the open play of significations, no positive entities, and no center to “arrest and ground the play of substitutions.” However familiar this juxtaposition of extremes may now be, if it is taken at face value and used to characterize what is at issue for thinking between phil- osophy and poetry, it proves altogether misleading. For it takes for granted that what is at issue in such thinking is a relation in which two discrete terms, philosophy and poetry, are to be brought together, compared, and ordered. Yet this is already to proceed in the traditional manner of philosophy. For it is to assume in principle that the “disciplinary,” “textual” identities of philosophy and poetry are determined in and through a relational opposition in which one or other of the terms must inevitably be privileged as the positive term from which the relation is first posited. The privileged term will then serve to define the ground of the relation as such. Of course, traditionally, philosophy has claimed this privilege for itself in the name of “Truth.” Yet even were one to reverse this traditional order of privilege, so as to valorize poetry over philosophy in the name of a superfluity of meaning, the same traditional assumptions and implications about the issue itself would remain in place. Consequently, in the first instance, we would be left with a “philosophical” reduction of meaning to truth in which the poetic dimensions of thinking were deliberately occluded and excised. In the second, we would be left with a “poetic” reduction of truth to meaning, which brings with it all of the trad- itional relativist complications, along with the problematics of deriving refer- ence from sense. In either case, a genuine space for thinking between philosophy and poetry would effectively vanish. It might well be argued, however, that this way of setting up the issue in the first place misrepresents at least one of the alternatives. To subvert philosophy’s traditional role as truth-teller in the name of infinite semiosis and the superfluity of meaning is not simply to put poetry by default in the traditional place of privilege. It is instead to render the interplay of poetic and philosophical dis- courses ultimately undecidable, in such a way as to make untenable the assump- tion that their relational juxtaposition is absolute and original. Thinking between philosophy and poetry would occupy the space of this ultimate “undecidability.” The essays collected in this volume are intended as characteristic examples of such thinking. As such, they serve by example to define the interplay of phil- osophy and poetry as what (in Heideggerian terms) might be called die Sache des Denkens, the matter of thinking. They represent a wide variety of perspectives and concerns both within and upon the topic. Their collective purpose, how- ever, is not to summarize the various possible “positions” that might be taken on the philosophy/poetry relation, or to indicate which, if any, of these positions is according to current fashion academically reputable. Even less is their purpose to advance (either directly through a sustained argument or indirectly through GENERAL INTRODUCTION 3 the juxtaposition of the essays themselves) any one particular position as being the “last word.” As it is construed here, thinking between philosophy and poetry does not so much represent a position as a “dis-position” to sustain the philosophy/poetry interplay. By means of a variety of concrete examples, we have sought in this volume to hold open the space for such thinking as the topic of our shared interest. The attempt, however, calls for a few words of introduc- tion, if only to help clarify – albeit superficially and even tendentiously – the initial terms around which this volume has been organized. By the term “poetry” we understand here neither exclusively nor even prin- cipally what in the current lexical definition typically falls under the rubric of “poesy,” that is, metrical and/or imaginative discourse designed above all to evoke an aesthetic response, as opposed, for example, to discourse having as its purpose apophantic truth-telling. Without pausing to discuss this disavowal in detail, suffice it to remind ourselves that, since Nietzsche and Heidegger, no one can simply take for granted the divisions and determinations of the apophantic and aesthetic upon which this usual definition of the poetic turns, nor the ready equation of poetry with meter and verse that it posits. Instead, to begin with we understand the term “poetic” here in the broadest etymological sense to encompass the whole domain of poie¯sis as that of the creative production of meaning. Following etymology, we likewise construe the term “philosophy” in a similarly broad way as philosophia, the love of wisdom, expressed in the quest for truth. In the broadest terms, then, as a tentative, working characteriza- tion we mean by thinking between philosophy and poetry, a discourse bounded by the interplay of meaning and truth. Admittedly, there is a sense in which this initial characterization might seem to offer little or no advantage. If it served in effect merely to recast the interplay of philosophy and poetry as a relation between truth and meaning, then it would only serve to reintroduce under different names the very closures and oppositional relations from which we seek expressly to abstain. How we might avoid this lapse thus needs at least some explanation. The case of poetry ought to be a familiar one. According to tradition, “the race of poets is divine,” and as such does at least occasionally hit upon truth, if only by the unmethodical means of grace and inspiration.5 In this regard, even the prosaic Aristotle concedes that poetry is “more philosophical and serious than history,” insofar as it tells a “general truth [ta katholou].”6 Traditionally, then, the issue has not been whether poetic meaning is related to truth but how it is related and how its claim upon truth is warranted. The case of philosophy is less familiar, precisely because it is one that the philosophers themselves have tended to suppress. According to tradition, Pythagoras coins the term philosophos to denote one who “seeks for truth [the¯ratai ... te¯s ale¯theias].”7 In offering this characterization, however, he uses a metaphor, that of the festival, ta Olumpia, with philosophers being cast as theatai, the “spectators,” whose defining excellence is that they simply look at the Games in order to get the sense of it all. In the metaphor, the philosopher’s love of truth is at the same time a love of “the finest sights” (to¯n kallisto¯n theo¯rian), from which they glean a comprehensive meaning. Thus, according to this hagiograph, philosophy has situated itself from the beginning

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.