ebook img

Beneficence and Health Care PDF

278 Pages·1982·14.001 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Beneficence and Health Care

BENEFICENCE AND HEALTH CARE PHILOSOPHY AND MEDICINE Editors: H. TRISTRAM ENGELHARDT, JR. Kennedy Institute of Ethics, Georgetown University, Washington, D.C., U.S.A. STUART F. SPIeKER University of Connecticut Health Center, Farmington, Connecticut, U.S.A. VOLUME 11 BENEFICENCE AND HEALTH CA]~E Edited by EARL E. SHELP Institute of Religion and Bay/or Col/ege ofM edicine, Houston, Texas D. REIDEL PUBLISHING COMPANY DORDRECHT: HOLLAND / BOSTON: U.S.A. LONDON: ENGLAND library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Main entry under title: Beneficence and health care. (Philosophy and medicine; v. 11) Bibliography: p. Includes index. 1. Benevolence-Addresses, essays, lectures. 2. Altruism Addresses, essays, lectures. 3. Medical care-Moral and ethical aspects-Addresses, essays, lectures. I. Shelp, Earl E., 1947- II. Series. [DNLM: 1. Ethics, Medical. 2. Religion and medicine. 3. Delivery of health care. W3 PH609 v, 11 1982 / W 50 B463] B11474.B46 174'.2 82-540 ISBN-13: 978-94-009-7771-6 e-ISBN-13: 978-94-009-7769-3 001: 10.1007/978-94-009-7769-3 Published by D. Reidel Publishing Company, P.O. Box 17,3300 AA Dordrecht, Holland. Sold and distributed in the U.S.A. and Canada by Kluwer Boston Inc., 190 Old Derby Street, Hingham, MA 02043, U.S.A. In all other countries, sold and distributed by Kluwer Academic Publishers Group, P.O. Box 322, 3300 AH Dordrecht, Holland. D. Reidel Publishing Company is a member of the Kluwer Group. All Rights Reserved Copyright © 1982 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland and copyright holders as specified on appropriate pages within No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner T ABLE OF CONTENTS EARL E. SHELP / Introduction vii SECTION II HISTORICAL AND CONCEPTUAL BACKGROUND DARREL W. AMUNDSEN and GARY B. FERNGREN / Philan- thropy in Medicine: Some Historical Perspectives 1 ALLEN E. BUCHANAN / Philosophical Foundations of Beneficence 33 WILLIAM K. FRANKENA / Beneficence in an Ethics of Virtue 63 JOHN P. REEDER, JR. / Beneficence, Supererogation, and Role Duty 83 SECTION II I BENEFICENCE IN RELIGIOUS ETHICS RONALD M. GREEN / Jewish Ethics and Beneficence 109 WILLIAM E. MA Y / Roman Catholic Ethics and Beneficence 127 HARMON L. SMITH / Protestant Ethics and Beneficence 153 SECTION III I BENEFICENCE IN HEALTH CARE NAT A LIE A BRA M S / Scope of Beneficence in Health Care 183 EARL E. SHELP / To Benefit and Respect Persons: A Challenge for Beneficence in Health Care 199 JAMES F. CHILDRESS / Beneficence and Health Policy: Reduction of Risk-Taking 223 RONALD M. GREEN / Altruism in Health Care 239 EARL E. SHELP / Epilogue 255 NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS 257 INDEX 259 EARL E. SHELP INTRODUCTION The meaning and application of the principle of beneficence to issues in health care is rarely clear or certain. Although the principle is frequently employed to justify a variety of actions and inactions, very little has been done from a conceptual point of view to test its relevance to these behaviors or to explore its relationship to other moral principles that also might be called upon to guide or justify conduct. Perhaps more than any other, the principle of benef icence seems particularly appropriate to contexts of health care in which two or more parties interact from positions of relative strength and weakness, advantage and need, to pursue some perceived goal. It is among those moral principles that Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress selected in their textbook on bioethics as applicable to biomedicine in general and relevant to a range of specific issues ([1], pp. 135-167). More narrowly, The National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behav ioral Research identified beneficence as among those moral principles that have particular relevance to the conduct of research involving humans (2). Thus, the principle of beneficence is seen as pertinent to the routine delivery of health care, the discovery of new therapies, and the rationale of public policies related to health care. Given the sort of central place the principle of beneficence commonly has in guiding and justifying activity in health care, it is important to the moral conduct of that enterprise to understand what the principle means, what it rightly warrants and what it does not. The essays in this volume respond to these concerns. A previous volume in the series, Philosophy and Medicine (No.8), addressed the relevance and implications of the principle of justice for health care [3]. The essays in that collection discussed what might be owed to persons in health care as a matter of their due or right. As a compan ion and complement to that earlier work, these essays interpret the principle of beneficence from several philosophical and theological perspectives in order to suggest its meaning, relevance, and application to a variety of moral concerns in contemporary health care. Much in this volume is ground-breaking. And, the contributors report that the ground was not easily broken! Several found that much of the existing theoretical and applied literature on beneficence was inadequate vii Earl E. Shelp (ed.), Beneficence and Health Care, vii-xvi. Copyright © 1982 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland.. viii EARL E. SHELP or inappropriate for the specific selected concerns addressed here. Yet, in spite of the difficulty of the assignment, all have been faithful to their charge. The creative bounty of their labors is here presented to stimulate, enrich, and advance contemporary moral reflection about the principle of beneficence and its strategic importance to health care. The essays are presented within three categories of investigation. The first section contains one historical and three philosophical studies that provide an introduction to the history of beneficence in medicine and an orientation to the foundation, nature, and function of the principle of beneficence in theories of ethics. The second section contains three essays. These examine the place of beneficence in West ern religious ethics and comment on the relationship of these understandings to moral questions in health care. The third section contains four essays that investigate the meaning of beneficence for health care and the relevance of beneficence to the distribution of health care resources. The section of background studies begins with an historical study by Darrel Amundsen and Gary Ferngren. They provide a description of a commen tary on that elusive quality of the medical event that alternately has been called 'caring', 'compassion', 'humanitarianism', 'altruism', 'beneficence', and 'philanthropy'. They focus on the use of 'philanthropy' and the concept of beneficence in medical history in order to assess the meaning and implication of the concept for present health care concerns, especially the patient-physi cian relationship. Their review begins in the Greek period of medicine where philanthropy carried within it a notion of reciprocity or obligation on the part of the recipient to honor the giver. During the Roman period the scope of philanthropy (humanitas) was extended in philosophical and popular ethics to be more inclusive, giving voice to the notion of human brotherhood. But, according to the authors, it was not until Scribonius !.argus (first century C. E.) that philanthropy or love of mankind was considered an essential trait of a physician. The relationship of the Christian idea of agape to philanthropy also is discussed. The church's interest in the cure of bodies is traced to an ethic of agape which was expressed at times in secular terms like philanthro pia. As a result, hospitals were founded by the Christian church and medical charity became a prominent part of the Christian movement. This was partic ularly true for monasticism during the Middle Ages. With the advent of the licensing of physicians (12th century), medical philanthropy was given a dif ferent emphasis in both Christian and secular literature. The literary discussion moves to a consideration of the treatment of the poor and the setting of fees. Amundsen and Ferngren conclude that, during the periods reviewed, philan thropy was considered by some an essential feature of the true physician. For INTRODUCTION ix others, competence enjoyed prominence with philanthropy or compassion seen as merely desirable. The proper mix of these qualities among physicians is still subject to debate. However, the debate gains perspective with a con sideration of the historical precedents provided by this essay. The background studies continue with a discussion by Allen Buchanan of the role, function, and ground of beneficence in several moral theories. He traces the basic lineaments of each theory and gives special attention to the role of beneficence in Kant's moral theory, John Rawls's ideal contract theory of justice, utilitarianism, Robert Nozick's rights-based libertarianism, and rational egoism. His analysis draws upon three fundamental distinctions: beneficence and benevolence, beneficence in special relationships and gener alized beneficence, and the respective rational foundation of special and generalized forms of beneficence. Buchanan observes that answers to questions of who are the proper recipients of beneficence in health care and the place of the principle of beneficence in a moral consideration of health care issues depend on a general philosophical theory of beneficence. Thus, he critically assesses the potential of each of the surveyed theories to provide an adequate statement and ground for beneficence, finding areas of difficulty and profit in all. He concludes his evaluation of beneficence in the selected, general moral theories with suggestions of the implications of each for moral questions in health care in terms of social policy and individual relationships. William Frankena considers the implications of beneficence for health care from the perspective of an ethics of virtue. He contrasts an ethics of virtue with an ethics of duty. The former is concerned primarily with dispositions, motives, traits, or ways of being as morally good, independent of the actions which issue from them. The latter is concerned primarily with the rightness of actions or duty independent of certain dispOsitions, motives, or traits. Frankena notes that beneficence mayor may not have a place within an ethics of virtue, noting that beneficence as now understood was not an important virtue in the West before Christianity, with the possible exception of the Stoics. He thinks that an adequate ethics of virtue must include justice as a cardinal virtue as well as beneficence/benevolence. He does not consider beneficence as a virtue. Rather, he combines benevolence and responsibility as the disposition that can be properly characterized as virtuous. The central component of this virtue is a motivation to do good and not evil to others. Yet, he remarks that dispositions can be good without being morally good and that virtues need not be necessarily moral ones. His representation of beneficence in an ethics of virtue as beneficence/responsibility suggests that all moral agents are to cultivate the virtue and then do in each situation what x EARL E. SHELP the virtue moves one to do. Frankena doubts that health care could be pro vided adequately in a society that relied solely on personal virtue. He discusses the implications of such an approach to various forms of individual and social relationships pertinent to health and health care. The essay concludes with a consideration of the relevance of an ethics of virtue to professional ethics. John Reeder's review of the nature of the duty of beneficence concludes the first section. He suggests that there are three levels or forms of duties of beneficence. The first form, mutual aid, is held to be a general duty for all members of the moral community apart from institutional provisions to render assistance. Reeder distinguishes welfare and well-being, suggesting that a moral agent has a duty to promote the former at the expense of the agent's own well-being in whole or in part. He argues, recognizing that a justification of his view is problematic, that a moral agent is obligated even to sacrifice one's welfare up to an indeterminate point. This point is indeterminate because of variations in empirical predictions of the future, levels of risk people will tolerate, and value judgments regarding the ranking of various goods. Yet, he holds that such a principle of obligation would be adopted as a form of self-interest. Beyond this level of duty, Reeder's theory terms actions on behalf of others as desirable or supererogatory but not required. He suggests that supererogation can take several forms beyond the require ments of mutual aid but that, again, the difference between mutual aid and supererogation is sometimes difficult to determine. Medical treatment is not considered by Reeder as subject to mutual aid or supererogatory beneficence in situations where a specialized class of personnel function within a social institution to perform this service. In the absence of unusual circumstances, the duty of mutual aid is replaced by the system of medical care. Although his analysis of role duties for medical personnel accommodates supereroga tory beneficence, ''the beneficence which is proper to the therapeutic role is a duty of justice." Transitioning from philosophical investigations, the three essays in the second section examine the role of beneficence or its equivalent in Judaism, Roman Catholicism, and selected forms of Protestantism. Ronald Green initiates this area of inquiry with a review of "Jewish Ethics and Beneficence." He finds the tradition to be rich with reflection on matters of beneficience. Opinions vary within the Jewish community regarding acts of beneficence or self-sacrificing love, depending on the weight given to the worth of each individual in a situation of conflict. Green sorts out several strands of Jewish teaching about this complex and diverse area of inquiry. He notes that the Rabbis encouraged generosity but held one's duty to be limited by one's INTRODUCTION xi responsibilities to oneself or one's community. Thus, the Rabbis recognized a duty to save another's life but not necessarily at the cost of one's own life. In health care contexts, the Rabbis held physicians to have certain role-related duties that required the assumption of certain risks, beyond the usual requirements, in order to serve one's patients. Green draws upon the historic views of Judaism toward self-sacrifice or beneficence to conclude his essay with a discussion of their implications for such concerns as visiting the sick, financial support of institutions of health care, donation of blood, medical experimentation, and organ donation. William E. May finds the tradition of Roman Catholicism to be rich, like Judaism, in reflection on acts of the virtue of charity which is the equivalent to philosophical beneficence. His survey of Roman Catholic moral thought includes a report of the relevant moral teachings issued by thl! magisterium and an account of the debate among Roman Catholic writers about these teachings, particularly as they relate to issues in health care. The magisterium teaches that some goods like human life, justice, truth, love, and peace are good in and of themselves. Further, evil ought not be done to produce good. From these basic claims, specific norms of conduct are derived. Thus, accord ing to May, certain acts in health care are incapable of being described as beneficent because they would violate certain principles held to be universally binding. He identifies euthanasia, abortion, contraception, and mutilation as examples of violating acts. In addition to these universal principles, May shows how the principles of 'double effect' and 'totality' have been used to interpret and apply the teachings of the magisterium to contexts of health care. The discussion then shifts to a summary of the contemporary debate within the church regarding the relationship of the principle of beneficence to the principle of utility or its Roman Catholic counterpart, proportionalism. Advocates of proportionalism hold, according to May, that there are no moral proscriptions that are absolutely unexceptional. Thus, they admit, in opposi tion to the view of the magisterium, that certain acts in health care can be beneficent if done for a proportionate reason. He thinks that the adequacy of this view turns on an interpretation of the principle of double effect and the distinction between a directly intended and an indirectly intended effect of some action. The major features of this debate are detailed. May concludes that the more proper view of beneficence in health care reflects agreement with the teaching of the magisterium rather than with the thOUght of those who favor proportionalism. Harmon Smith examines the theologies of Martin Luther, John Calvin, and John Wesley as representative of major traditions in Protestant Christianity.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.