ebook img

Attitudes Toward Death in Archaic Greece PDF

25 Pages·1989·3.24 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Attitudes Toward Death in Archaic Greece

IAN MORRIS Attitudes Toward Death in Archaic Greece W AST HERAE SIGNIFICASNHTI FTin a ttitudes towardd eath inA rchaic Greece? In this paper, I argue both yes and no, according to how "attitudes toward death" isd efined. My thesis is a reply to two important articles by Christiane Sourvinou Inwood. Dr. Sourvinou-Inwood claims that the rise of the polis affected mentali tiesw ithin the intellectual elite, and that death began to be fearedm ore after 700 B.C.S he further suggests that the changes identified by Philippe Aries in eleventh to twelfth-century-A.D.F rance provide a useful analogy forA rchaic Greece.' Her case has far-reaching consequences: if theG reeks had to any extent anticipated Western developments by twom illennia, much thinkinga bout the history of death would be challenged, and the theoretical basis for the archaeology of burials would crumble. The argument also raises serious questions about the possibility of "intellectualist" interpretations of archaeological evidence.2 The question, then, is of interest even beyond the field of Greek religious history. I am grateful to a number of readers in Cambridge and Oxford, and to seminar audiences in Cambridge and Chicago, for valuable comments on earlier drafts of this paper. Iw ould particularly like to thankA nthony Snodgrass, Paul Cartledge, and Tony Long for their help, without wishing to implicate them in the results. 1. C. Sourvinou-Inwood, "A Trauma in Flux: Death in the Eighth Century and After," in R. Hagg, ed., The Greek Renaissance of theE ighth Century B.C. (Stockholm, 1983) 33-49; Sourvinou Inwood, "To Die and Enter the House of Hades: Homer, Before and After," in J. Whaley, ed., Mirrors of Mortality (London, 1981) 15-39. P. Aries (The Hour of Our Death [New York, 19811) himself believes that there was no change in antiquity; he speaks of a single attitude, which "is the unchronicled death throughout the long ages of most ancient history, and perhaps of prehistory" (p. 5). 2. I. Morris, Burial and Ancient Society: The Rise of the Greek City-State (Cambridge, 1987) 32-36; cf. I. Hodder, Reading the Past (Cambridge, 1986) 5. I was unable to discuss Sourvinou Inwood's theories there, owing to lack of space. (0 1989 BY THE REGENTS OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA MORRIASt:t itudes Toward Death inA rchaic Greece 297 Dr. Sourvinou-Inwood suggests that therew as a large-scalec hange in individ ual psychologies around 700 B.C. I dispute this view, arguing that there was fundamental continuity inp ersonal attitudes towardd eath from the earliest times to the Classical period and beyond. There were some eschatological changes, such as the arrival of Eastern ideas about the soul around 500, but I believe that these had very limited impact.W hat did change, though, was the communal use made of the dead, in rituals evoking and creating the structure of society. For simplicity's sake, I refer to the ritual uses of death to "create" the polis community as "ideologies of death," and to individuals' concepts about the fear of death and the afterlife as "individual attitudes to death." The two are not completely separable, and to some extent they overlap;3 but for the analysis here, this rather crude distinction is a useful tool. I begin by considering the methodological problems involved in this ques tion, focusing on the role of generalization. I then outline Dr. Sourvinou Inwood's case and its links with Aries's model in more detail, arguing that her causalm odel is inadequate. Finally, Iw ill offer alternative interpretationso f the literary and archaeological evidence, emphasizing social rather than psychologi cal factors. I am certainly not claiming that personal belief-religious or otherwise-has no place in the analysis of death and burial; rather, I suggest that it is much harder to carry out a study at this level than is often assumed. Struc tural and intellectualist interpretations of rituals are complementary ways of viewing the same data, not competing alternatives; but in this particular case, there is insufficient evidence for an individualist approach, and Dr. Sourvinou Inwood's theory lacks an empirical basis.4 ANCIENT MENTALITIES How do we know when there has been a significant shift in attitudes toward death? There are two general problems to consider. Evidence. Most people's ideas about death change frequently.5 Archaic Greek poetry probably represents only elite attitudes, but even so we will expect to findm any viewpoints within it.6T o talk about the history of death is to try to 3. See M. Bloch, "Death, Women and Power," in M. Bloch and J. Parry, eds., Death and the Regeneration of Life (Cambridge, 1982) 223-30. 4. I explore this theme more fully in By Their Dead Shall You Know Them: Burial and Social Structure inC lassical Antiquity (Cambridge, inp ress) chap. 1.O n the structural/intellectualistd istinc tion, see E. E. Evans-Pritchard, Theories of Primitive Religion (Oxford, 1965); M. Bloch, From Blessing to Violence (Cambridge, 1986) 3-9. A psychohistory of death may be possible, but note that David Stannard, one of the leading historians of death, is also a stern critic of psychohistory; see his The PuritanW ay of Death (Oxford, 1977) and ShrinkingH istory: Freud and theF ailure of Psychohis tory (Oxford, 1980). 5. See R. Hinton, Dying (Harmondsworth, 1967) 21-49. 6. Compare the arguments of R. Favre, La mort dans la literature et la pensee francaise au siecle des lumieres (Lyon, 1978). R. G. Osborne ("Death Revisited, Death Revised: The Death of 298 CLASSICAALN TIQUITY Volume 8/No. 2/October 1989 capture a "spirito f the age," which is necessarily a very high-level generalization, in a distant and complex relationship to any single datum. Such abstraction affects thew ays we may use the sources. The risk of error in picking out just a few witnesses is obvious. People do not think all alike; we can only understand a "mentality" by ironing out human diversity, taking a huge sample of the thought of an age and standing so far back that its internal differ ences disappear from view.7 Some historians respond statistically. Studying links between "total" Christianity and attitudes toward death, Vovelle drew on over two thousand wills; while Chaunu, arguing for demography as a prime mover behind attitudes toward death, used some eight thousandw ills and a huge mass of population statistics.8 Quantification has its own drawbacks,9b ut it throws theH ellenist's problems into sharp relief. Our evidence is fragmentary, has been pre-selected by transmis sion processes we can rarely observe, and is unevenly distributed in time and space; itw as written by people of whom we know little or nothing, for purposes now generally unrecoverable, and in several very different literary genres. We cannot even claim to be able to describe the attitude toward death of a single Greek poet at any time in his (or in a few cases her) career. When we make sweeping generalizations about "collective representations" on the basis of this patchwork of snippets, we should remember Alan Macfarlane's warning that "every poem and every line has to be carefully weighed in order to discover the stylistic and traditional constraints on the expression of thought and emotion.""' This is not a counsel of despair, but a plea for an appropriate methodology. Our sources cannot support Aries's type of wide-ranging eclecticism, and still less Vovelle's rigorous serial analyses. But simply ignoring the problems and letting the sources speak for themselves, as it seems to me that Sourvinou Inwood has tried to do, is unacceptable. If we wish to study ancient mentalities, we are forced to build a simplifyingm odel from prior probabilities, establishing which way the burden of proof lies, and then to examine it in the light of the evidence, modifying, adjusting, or discarding the original hypothesis as neces the Artist inA rchaic and Classical Greece," Art History 11 [1988] 1-16) illustrates the variety of responses available to the ancient Greeks using artistic evidence. I am not persuaded by his empathetic methods, but he does raise very interesting possibilities. 7. See J. Le Goff, "Mentalities: A History of Ambiguities," in J. Le Goff and P. Nora, eds., Constructing the Past (Cambridge, 1985) 166-80; P. and C. Stearns, "Emotionology: Clarifying the History of Emotions and Emotional Standards," AHR 90 (1985) 813-36. 8. M. Vovelle, Piete baroque et dechristianisation en Provence au XVI1Ie siecle abr. ed. (Paris, 1978); P. Chaunu, La mort a Paris, 16e, 17e, 18e sicles (Paris, 1978) and more briefly inA nnales (ESC) 31 (1976) 29-50. 9. The literature is large; for an introduction, see R. Fogel and G. Elton, Which Road to the Past? (New Haven, 1983). 10.A. Macfarlane, "Death and the Demographic Transition: A Note on the English Evidence on Death, 1500-1700," in S. C. Humphreys andH . King, eds., Mortality and Immortality (New York and London, 1981) 252. MORARtItSit:u dTeso warDde athi nA rchaGic reece 299 sary." The texts are so difficult that them ost we can hope for is compatibility with a theory. Analysis of the logic and structure of the models used and the sophistication of the questions asked is every bit as important as discussion of the sources that support them. Concepts. Discussions of historical change are only meaningful within some explicit framework. Golden's recent study, "Did theA ncients Care When Their Children Died?," is a case in point; the issue is reduced to a black-and-white question. His simple answer-yes-does not tell us very much about ancient society.12 Similarly, asking "Was there a change in attitudes toward death in Archaic Greece?" is pointless. The pool of ideas about death current in 500 B.C. must have been different from those views that existed in Homer's time, simply because different people were alive. Even when consciously trying to reproduce rules and ideas, people inevitably transform their structures of thought."3T he question is not whether Greek attitudes were the same in 500 as they had been ten generations earlier-they simply cannot have been-but whether we see the changes as historically significant; and the facts can only be called important or unimportant relative to a specific theory. Sourvinou-Inwood linked her studies to those by Aries, and it is from this that her argument derives its interest. We can see changes in individuals' attitudes in our sources, but all Archaic and Classical writers can be encompassed within the category that Aries calls the Tame Death. This is not to say that Aries's system is too broad to have analytical value; rather, itm eans that in historical terms the continuities and similarities in attitudes found in eighth- to sixth-century literaturev astly outweigh the elements of change. FEAR OF DEATH: MEDIEVAL FRANCE AND ARCHAIC GREECE Only the first two stages of Aries's history of death concern us here. He calls these the Tame Death and the Death of the Self. He describes the first as "an attitude toward death that remained almost unchanged for thousands of years, an attitude that expressed a naive and spontaneous acceptance of destiny and nature."'4 It is familiar, "the recognition of an evil inseparable from man."15 Only the mystic welcomes death,'6 but it is not loathed or shunned. Above all, death was a shared transition: "Death was always public."'7 The Tame Death produced a characteristic idea of the Good Death, a fate met with composure. 11. Generally, see M. I. Finley, Ancient History: Evidence andM odels (London, 1985). 12. M. Golden, "Did the Ancients Care When Their Children Died?" G&R, n.s., 35 (1988) 152-63. 13. See A. Giddens, The Constitution of Society (Oxford, 1984). 14. Aries (supra n. 1) 29. 15. Ibid. 605. 16. Ibid. 13-14. 17. Ibid. 19. 300 CLASSICAALN TIQUITY Volume 8/No. 2/October 1989 The dying person was forewarned, and had time tom ake farewells, quitting life with dignity.W hether death was in bed or in battle, the same pattern of accept ance, goodbyes, and mourning was called for.'8 Aries sees a second model, theD eath of the Self, appearing among intellec tuals around A.D. 1100. New weight was put on individuality, and on death as a lonely fate: "Death ceased to be a weighing, a final reckoning, judgement or repose, and became carrion and corruption; it ceased to be the end of life, the last breath, and became physical death, suffering and decomposition."'" Aries explains the psychological change through greater chances for the educated to achieve upward social mobility, coupled with frequent failure to do so. This led to a widespread sense of personal failure, which, given the facts of medieval demography, was blamed on death. Death began to be a hateful individual doom, cutting off a rewarding life.'2 The Tame Death was still important inE urope in the eighteenth century and even later, but, Aries adds, "the fact thatw e keep meeting instances of the same general attitude from Homer to Tolstoi does not mean we should assign it a structural permanence."2' The Death of the Self displaced the Tame Death "among the rich, the well educated, and the powerful,"22w hile theT ame Death lingered on among the peasantry. Aries has been attacked for his impressionism, but his distinctions between the Tame Death and later forms and between elite and commoner attitudes are widely accepted.23 Sourvinou-Inwood uses his great achievement as an analogy for her model of Greek attitudes:24 In Homer there is one dominant model of attitudes towards death, firmly rooted in the epic, and then signs of a tentative beginning of a partial movement away from it. The dominant model is the "familiar" or "tradi tional" type of attitude toward death, a version of the "Tamed Death" attitude analysed by Aries.... The new stirrings, by contrast, some of which are also reflected in eighth-century archaeological evidence, are the first beginnings of a series of developments which will gain momen tum in the succeeding, archaic period (c. 700-c. 480) duringw hich we can 18. Ibid. 603. 19. Ibid. 138. 20. Ibid. 137-39. 21. Ibid. 28. 22. Ibid. 138. 23. Aries (ibid., xiii) describes his methods as "intuitive and subjective." See also M. Vovelle, "Les attitudes devant la mort: Problemes de methode, approches et lectures differentes," Annales (ESC) 31 (1976) 120-32; D. Ilmer, Zeitschrift fur Historische Forschung 6 (1979) 213-15; J.W haley, "Introduction," and J. McManners, "Death and the French Historians," inW haley, ed. (supra, n. 1) 1-14, 106-30; A. J. Gurevic, "Au moyen age: Conscience individuelle et image de l'au-dela," Annales (ESC) 37 (1982) 255-75. Lawrence Stone (The Past and the Present Revisited [London. 19871 310-27) has suggested that moves away from the Tame Death only began in the sixteenth century. 24. Sourvinou-Inwood, "To Die" (supra n. 1) 16-17. MORRIASt:t itudes Toward Death inA rchaic Greece 301 detect a (partial) shift away from familiar acceptance, towards a more individual, and anxious approach towardo ne's own death-broadly com parable to the change which occurred in the late [sic]M iddle Ages in Europe. The changing demographic, socio-economic, political and intel lectual realities of eighth-century Greece, in interactionw ith each other, affected the existing system of funerary behaviour, attitudes towards death, and afterlife beliefs; they initiated a process of change, feedback, and interactionw ith the interlocking parts of the funerary system (multi plier effect), and continued to fuel it during the following period. Comparing Aries' translation with what she saw inG reece, Sourvinou-Inwood added:25 The similarities, especially that in the basic mentality, the "elementary syntax" of the model, suggest that certain (general) types of attitude towardd eath depend on a certain nexus of demographic, socio-economic, political and "intellectual" conditions, and so characterize certain general types of society. I will argue that the complexity of Homeric attitudes is best explained not as the beginnings of changes, but as part of a general pattern of attitudes that remained little changed from 800 to 500 B.C. First, though, I will consider Sourvinou Inwood's causalm odel, which asserts that "the [eighth-century]p opulation explo sion and the resulting urbanization . . . expanded drastically Greek physical and mental horizons, and dislocated or destroyed many of the structures on which the 'familiar'd eath attitudes had depended."26 DEMOGRAPHY, THE INDIVIDUAL, AND DEATH Did population growth transform attitudes toward death? Most historians agree that it could,27 and there was population growth in eighth-century Greece-according to Snodgrass, at a rate of up to 4 percent per annum at Athens.28 This would surely have had a profound impact, but it strains demo graphic plausibility and has a weak evidential base. I am not persuaded that the known burials represent a constant proportion of the ancient populations.29B ut even if we do use the graves as a yardstick, major problems remain. The age 25. Ibid. 39. 26. Sourvinou-Inwood, "Trauma" (supra n. 1) 34. 27. The demographic argument ism ade by Chaunu (supra n. 8), although F. Lebrun docu mented similar changes in attitudes inA njou without population growth in Les hommes devant la mort a Anjou au XVIle et XVIIIe siecles (Paris, 1971). Vovelle (supra n. 8) tried to balance the material and the mental. 28. A. M. Snodgrass, Archaeology and the Rise of the Greek State (Cambridge, 1977) 10-18; Archaic Greece (London, 1980) 18-25; "Two Demographic Notes," in Hagg, ed. (supra n. 1) 167 71. 29. Morris (supra n. 2) 57-155. 302 CLASSICAALN TIQUITY Volume 8/No. 2/October 1989 structure of the cemeteries fluctuates: in Sub-Mycenaean (ca. 1125-1050 B.C.) and Late Geometric II (735-700), the adult-child ratio isw hat we would expect in an agrarian society; but in Protogeometric to Late Geometric I (1050-735), the young are underrepresented, probably being buried in an archaeologically less visible way.30 This sharply reduces the proposed population growth. The Late Geometric increasew as also temporary: as Camp points out, if graves show population growth in the eighth century, theym ust also show a massive decline in the seventh, which Sourvinou-Inwood's model does not accommodate.31 Settlement evidence does indicate eighth-century growth,32b ut this did not necessarily have am ajor influence on attitudes towardd eath. Most historians see the "demographic transition," a sudden decline in birth rates and infantm ortal ity, as the decisive factor in changing attitudes.33T here is no evidence for such a transition in antiquity. The fifth-centuryK erameikos cemetery atA thens and the fourth-century cemetery at Olynthus have typical pre-transition age structures, with child:adult ratios of 9:10 and 8:10, respectively;34a nd Aristotle remarked that most deaths occurred in the first week after birth, again a typical pre transition pattern.35 Sourvinou-Inwood suggests that population growth led to urbanization, which influenced people's attitudes toward death. But "urbanization" is an inap propriate concept forA rchaic Greece. Few would put the population of Athens above five to ten thousand in 700 B.C., or forty thousand in 450 B.C., and most poleis were very much smaller.36T his level of growth and absolute population 30. Ibid. 57-62. 31. J.M cK. Camp, "A Drought in the Late Eighth Century B.C.,"H esperia 48 (1979) 397-411. Sourvinou-Inwood ("Trauma" [supra n. 1] 34 n. 5) rejects his interpretation. Iw ould like to thank Professor Camp for corresponding with me about his theory. I would now modify my critique in Morris (supra n. 2) 155-67, which oversimplifies the problem, but I am still not persuaded by his arguments. However, ifw e see an eighth-century increase in graves as an increase in population, his logic cannot be faulted. 32. Morris (supra n. 2) 156-59. 33. Of the many accounts of the demographic transition, I have found the following the most useful: E. A. Wrigley, Population and History (London, 1969);C . M. Cipolla, The Economic History ofW orld Population, 7th ed. (Harmondsworth, 1978); and the comparative evidence of J.C . Caldwell, P. H. Reddy, and P. Caldwell, The Causes of Demographic Change (Madison,W isc., 1988). 34. J. L. Angel's findings at Olynthus and elsewhere are conveniently summarized inM . D. Grmek, Diseases in theA ncient Greek World (Baltimore, 1989) 99-103. No equivalent study of the Kerameikos is available. The actual numbers involved are 445 children and 510 adults, with 54 uncertain cases. The main reports are in AM 81 (1966) 4-135; K. Kiibler, Kerameikos VII.1 (Berlin, 1976); U. Knigge, Kerameikos IX (Berlin, 1976). I discuss some of thism aterial in "Monumental Burial: The Family and the State in Classical Athens," in D. Charles and J. Thomas, eds.. Monu ments to theD ead (forthcoming, Cambridge). 35. Ar. HA 7.588a. See M. H.. Hansen, Demography and Democracy (Copenhagen, 1986) 7 13; P. Garnsey, ed., "Food, Health and Culture in Classical Antiquity," Cambridge Faculty of ClassicsW orking Papers, no. 1 (1989). 36. Morris (supra n. 2) 99-101, with references. M. H. Hansen's revision of the number of fifth centuryA thenian citizens upwards to 60,000 ("Three Studies inA thenian Demography," Kongelike Dansk Videnskabernes Selskab, Historisk-filosofiske Meddelelser 56 [1988] 14-28) does not affect this MORRIASt:t itudes Toward Death inA rchaic Greece 303 size cannot meaningfully be compared with even the medieval situation, and could in no way have created an "urban anomie" in T6nnies's or Wirth's sense, undermining the Tame Death.37 Neither the demographic and socioeconomic parts of Sourvinou-Inwood's "nexus" of conditions nor what she calls the "intellectual realities" provide con vincing motors for change. The idea of a "rise of the individual" loosening the bonds of kinship and changing attitudes toward death around 700 depends very heavily on the contrast in genres between Homer and later poets, and compares poorly with the rich medieval evidence with which Sourvinou-Inwood draws another analogy.38 The chain of cause and effect is left unclear in her argument, and, more important, even in the fourth century the obligations of the ayXLOTEia inA thenian funeralsw ere very like those of the near kin inH omer.39T here is no evidence that a rise of the individual disembedded death from its communal context.40 Sourvinou-Inwood's causal model is not persuasive: the demographic and intellectual background inA rchaic Greece cannot be said to be sufficiently like that in high medieval France for us to expect a priori that there might have been comparable changes in attitudes toward death. Iw ill therefore proceed with the hypothesis that individual attitudes remained essentially constant. In the next section, I review the textual evidence. This is consistent with my argument for changes in ideologies of death but continuity in individual attitudes. THE POETICS OF DYING The first and fullest source is the Iliad, the poem of death: 318 heroes, 243 of them named, get killed.41 But the very abundance of heroic corpses is a problem. figure. E. Ruschenbusch ("Die Zahl der griechischen Staaten und Arealgrosse und Burgerzahl der 'Normalpolis,' "Z PE 59 [1985] 253-63) puts the "Normalzahl" of citizens at just 133 to 800. 37. See I. Morris, "The Early Polis as City and State," in J. Rich and A. Wallace-Hadrill, eds., City and Country in theA ncient World (London, forthcoming). On medieval urbanism, see P. M. Hohenberg and L. H. Lees, TheM aking of Urban Europe, 1000-1950 (Cambridge,M ass., 1985) 22 105. The classic (although now rathero ld-fashioned) studies of the "urbanm entality" are F. Tonnies, Community and Association (London, 1955); and L. Wirth, "Urbanism as aW ay of Life," American Journal of Sociology 44 (1938) 1-24. 38. Sourvinou-Inwood, "Trauma" (supra n. 1) 48 n. 89. On medieval individualism, see G. Duby and P. Braunstein, "The Emergence of the Individual," inG . Duby, ed., A History of Private Life II, Revelations of theM edieval World (Cambridge,M ass., 1988) 507-630. 39. Compare the accounts of Homeric funerals by R. Garland, "Geras Thanonton," BICS 29 (1982) 69-80, and by M. Edwards, "The Conventions of a Homeric Funeral," in J. H. Betts, J. T. Hooker, and J. R. Green, eds., Studies inH onour of T. B. L. Webster (Bristol, 1986) 84-92, with those of Classical Athens byW . K. Lacey, The Family in Classical Greece (London, 1968) 147-50, and the remarks throughout S. C. Humphreys' The Family, Women and Death (London, 1983). Generally, see R. Garland, The Greek Way of Death (London, 1985). 40. The distinctive notion of individual judgment of the dead known in the late sixth century probably began with Pherecydes of Syros: see M. L. West, Early Greek Philosophy and theO rient (Oxford, 1971) 255. I dicuss it later in this paper. 41. Counted by S. E. Bassett, The Poetry of Homer (London, 1938) 256 n. 37. 304 CLASSICAALN TIQUITY Volume 8/No. 2/October 1989 The warrior's death was special in Greek literature, and we have to distinguish between the death of the hero and the deaths of ordinary folk. Looking at the Song of Roland, Aries saw a contradiction: death in bed in peaceful old age and violent death in battle were both Good Deaths. He suggested a functional explanation-"in a society founded on chivalric and military ideals, the stigma attached to sudden death was not extended to the noble victims of war."42 We find a similar "double good death" inH omer, but its structure ism ore complex. I will try to bring this out with a few examples. In Iliad Book 22, Hector is waiting outside the walls of Troy. Priam calls down to him to come back inside, for Achilles will surely kill him. In this moment of crisis, Hector should think not of his own death, but of his father's:43 For a young man all things are seemly, if he falls in battle, lying dead, pierced by the sharp bronze; yes, all things are beautiful for the dead man, whatever happens; but when the dogs defile the grey hair, grey beard, and genitals of an old man who has been killed, this is the most miserable thing forw retched mortals. The contrast is strong. Violent death makes Hector beautiful, but it degrades and defiles Priam. Death fixes the hero in his youthful bloom, and fixes his glory (xXeos). His &aQoxliaw ill be remembered for generations to come, when they sing of the fames of men. The hero killed in battle lives on through epic and his well-marked tomb. Hades is a dismal place far worse than any life,44 but death is inevitable, and it is this rather than earthly honors that drives the hero to em brace his doom.45H ere is the essential tension of the heroic condition-the very awfulness of Hades drives him to death in battle as the only way to survive.4 Through the Good Death in battle, the hero beats fate and becomes almost immortal by doing just what the immortals never do-dying. Homer calls the 42. Aries (supra n. 1) 12. His approach to the poem is criticized in R. F. Cook, The Sense of "The Song of Roland" (Ithaca. N.Y., 1987) 141. 43. 11. 22.71-76: VO, 6E TE aTUVT'E tCEOLXEV, dQrli'xctiaEVa. 6e6iy?1EVW O6i; XOXtkx XElCO O(- 6vTaV6TO xXk6t 0av6OVTl JTEQ,6 OTt - 4)atvt] (&X' OTE 6ti JTnot6v TV xdctt JtOOt6v TE y?VEtov (tl6( T' aXioxiV(ool XlVEC XT(LI 01VO0OyE OOVTOCg. toU TO 6h OiXTILOOV JTk?ETctL6 ELXkOOi pOQ OtlOV. 44. Od. 11.487-91. 45. See esp. II. 12.310-28. 46. J. M. Redfield, Nature and Culture in the Iliad (Chicago, 1975) 30-35; J. Griffin, Homer On Life and Death (Oxford, 1980) 95-102; J.-P. Vernant, "Death with Two Faces," in S. C. Humphreys and H. King, eds., Mortality and Immortality (New York, 1981) 285-91; "La belle mort et le cadavre outrage," in G. Gnoli and J.-P. Vernant, eds., La mort, les morts, dans les societies anciennes (Cambridge, 1982) 45-76; "nHvta xakx: D'Homere a Simonide," in J. Harmatta, ed., Proceedings of the Vllth Congress of the International Federation of the Societies of Classical Studies I (Budapest, 1984) 167-73. MORARtItSit:u dTeso warDde athi nA rchaGic reece 305 doomed or dead hero "godlike," at once heightening the audience's awareness of the hero's victory in death, the frailty of humanity, and the gulf that finally separates us from the gods. Let us return to Hector's fightw ith Achilles. The Trojan is speared through the throat, and his soul speeds away, bewailing its loss of life. Looking to the Achaeans, Achilles tells them to sing the triumph:47 "We have won great glory; we have killed godlike Hector, to whom the Trojans in the city pray like a god." And then he did disgraceful things to godlike Hector. Godlike Hector ism utilated and dragged round thew alls behind Achilles' char iot. Thus he wins his xXkog: "If the hero were really god-like, if he were exempt, as the gods are, from age and death, then he would not be a hero at all."48 This violent and often humiliating Good Death is no poetic whim. The Tame Death attitudes of the eighth century are used to create an ideology of the permanence and power of the nobility. Vernant argues that heroic tombs and poems provided early Greeks with a collective past throughw hich they defined themselves,49 and Bloch develops the links between the hero's beauty in death and his permanence as cremated bones:5' The ideal is . . . for the body to be immediately cremated so that disfigu ration and decay do not occur. The image of the uncorrupted youth continues and maintains the undiminished life of the ideal society. The perfect body is in itself the source of the timelessness of the second side of the funeral, in that it represents an unchangingly vigorous martial order of society composed forever of incorruptible heroes. But what of Priam? His death will not be a good one. He will vanish utterly and his line will end. For an old man, a violent death is no Good Death. In this case, it comes in the sack of a city, not on a battlefield; it creates no timeless past; it is simply degrading. Women and old men should die peacefully in bed, resigned to fate, well mourned. Children should not die at all. Only immortal xXeog gives the hero cause to die young. Griffin echoes 47. II. 22.393-95: "rdl.Etc-a aneya xvbog- ej:e4voEav "EXTooCx 6Fov. ,XT QCoEC xaTa aoTv 6eTOC 5 EUXEToO)VTO." i1e a, xci "ExToQa 6rov &etLXa jI6ltTo Eiya. On &etxea, see Griffin (supra n. 46) 85 n. 9. 48. Griffin (supra n. 46) 92-93. 49. Vernant (supra n. 46). 50. Bloch (supra n. 3) 228. Vernant also links this process with the sacrifice of animals-see particularly "Sacrificial and Alimentary Codes inH esiod's Myth of Prometheus," inR . L. Gordon, ed., Myth, Religion and Society (Cambridge, 1981) 77; andW . Burkert, Homo Necans (Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1983) 48-58.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.