ebook img

Arrow of time PDF

230 Pages·2001·1.89 MB·English
by  Zeh.
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Arrow of time

Preface to the Third and Preliminary Fourth Edition { Prelim.4th edtn.(Feb 01): www.time-direction.de The third (1999) edition of the Direction of Time ofiered far more revisions andadditionsthanthesecondonein1992.Duringthesevenyearsinbetween, several flelds of research related to the arrow of time had shown remarkable progress. For example, decoherence proved to be the most ubiquitous man- ifestation of the quantum arrow, while articles on various interpretations of quantum theory (many of them with inbuilt time-asymmetric dynamical aspects)cananddonowregularlyappearinreputedphysicsjournals.There- fore, most parts of Chap.4 were completely rewritten and some new sections added, while the second part of Chap.3 was afiected by these changes in or- dertoprepareforthediscussionofmeasurementsanddynamicalmapswithin the framework of classical ensemble theory. However,allpartsofthebookhavebeenrevised,andsomeofthemcom- pletely rewritten, whilst essentially maintaining the book’s overall structure. Some of its new aspects may be listed here: The Introduction now attempts to distinguish rigorously between those time asymmetries which still preserve dynamical determinism, and the various ‘irreversiblities’ (arrows of time proper) which are the subject of this book. In Chap.2, the concept of forks of causality is contrasted to that of forks of indeterminism (to be used in Chaps.3 and 4), while the treatment of the radiation reaction of a moving charge (Sect.2.3) had to be updated. Sects.3.2{3.4 have been given a new structure, while a discussion of semi- groups and their physical meaning has been added to Sect.3.4. InChap.4,onlySects.4.1and4.5(theformerSect.4.3onexponentialdecay) arenotentirelynew.Inparticular,thereisnowanextendedseparateSect.4.3 ondecoherence.Sects.4.4(onquantumdynamicalmaps)and4.6(onthetime arrow in various interpretations of quantum theory) is now added. In Chap.5, the thermodynamics of acceleration is now presented separately (Sect.5.2),whileSect.5.3ontheexpansionoftheuniversecontainsadiscus- sionoftheconsistencyofcosmictwo-timeboundaryconditions.Thedynam- ical interpretation of general relativity with its concept of intrinsic time is discussed in Sect.5.4. Chap.6 now covers all aspects of quantum cosmology and thus includes, as Sect.6.1, the material of the former Sect.5.2.2 on phase transitions of the vacuum with their consequences on entropy capacity. In Sect.6.2 on quan- tum gravity, emphasis is on timelessness, which is enforced by quantization of a reparametrization invariant theory. There is a new Sect.6.2.2 on the II PrefacetotheThirdandPreliminaryFourthEdition{Prelim.4thedtn.(Feb01):www.time-direction.de emergence of classical time along the lines of the Tomonaga-Schwinger equa- tion, while Sect.6.2.3 describes some speculations on the impact of quantum cosmology on the concept of black holes and their thermodynamical proper- ties. A numerical toy model has been appended after the Epilog in order to illustrate some typical arguments of stastistical mechanics. I also hope that most disadvantages which had resulted from the fact that I previously had (very unfortunately) translated many parts of the flrst edition from the German lecture notes that preceded it (Zeh 1984), have now been overcome. Two new books on the arrow of time (Price 1996 and Schulman 1997) have recently appeared. They are both well written, and they discuss many important aspects of ‘irreversible’ physics in a consistent and illuminating manner | often nicely complementing each other as well as this book. However, I difier from their views in two respects: I regard gravity (not least its quantized form) as basic for the arrow of time, as I try toexplaininChaps.5and6,andIdonotthinkthattheproblemofquantum measurements can be solved by means of an appropriate flnal condition in a satisfactory way (see Footnote 4 of Chap.4). I wish to thank Julian Barbour, Erich Joos, Claus Kiefer, Joachim Kupsch, York Ramachers, Huw Price, Fritz Rohrlich, Paul Sheldon and Max Tegmark for their comments on early versions of various parts of the manu- script. Heidelberg, April 1999 H.-D. Zeh The fourth edition contains revisions throughout the whole book. There are many new formulations and arguments, several new comments and ref- erences, and three minor error corrections (on page 22, 112 and 146 of the third edition). It is now planned to be published in Spring 2001. Therefore, this preliminary internet version will not be further updated. For this edition I am grateful to David Atkinson (for a very helpful dis- cussionofradiationdamping|Sect.2.3),toLarrySchulman(forcomments on the problem of simultaneous arrows of time | Sect.3.1.2), and to Paul Sheldon (for a discussion of the compatibility of closed time-like curves with quantum theory | Chap.1). The most e–cient help, this time, came from John Free, who carefully edited the whole book (not only for matters of English language). Heidelberg, February 2001 H.-D. Zeh Contents Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1 1. The Physical Concept of Time . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9 2. The Time Arrow of Radiation . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15 2.1 Retarded and Advanced Forms of the Boundary Value Problem . . . . . . . . . . 18 2.2 Thermodynamical and Cosmological Properties of Absorbers . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22 2.3 Radiation Damping . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 26 2.4 The Absorber Theory of Radiation . . . . . . . . . 32 3. The Thermodynamical Arrow of Time . . . . . . . . . . 37 3.1 The Derivation of Classical Master Equations . . . . . 40 3.1.1 „-Space Dynamics and Boltzmann’s H-Theorem . . 41 3.1.2 ¡-Space Dynamics and Gibbs’s Entropy . . . . . 45 3.2 Zwanzig’s General Formalism of Master Equations . . . 55 3.3 Thermodynamics and Information . . . . . . . . . . 66 3.3.1 Thermodynamics Based on Information . . . . . 66 3.3.2 Information Based on Thermodynamics . . . . . 71 3.4 Semigroups and the Emergence of Order . . . . . . . 75 4. The Quantum Mechanical Arrow of Time . . . . . . . . . 83 4.1 The Formal Analogy . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 84 4.1.1 Application of Quantization Rules . . . . . . . 84 4.1.2 Master Equations and Quantum Indeterminism . . 87 4.2 Ensembles versus Entanglement . . . . . . . . . . 92 4.3 Decoherence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 99 4.3.1 Trajectories . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 100 4.3.2 Molecular Conflgurations as Robust States . . . . 103 4.3.3 Charge Superselection . . . . . . . . . . . . 105 4.3.4 Classical Fields and Gravity . . . . . . . . . 107 4.3.5 Quantum Jumps . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 109 IV Contents 4.4 Quantum Dynamical Maps . . . . . . . . . . . . 111 4.5 Exponential Decay and ‘Causality’ in Scattering . . . . 116 4.6 The Time Arrow of Various Interpretations of Quantum Theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 121 5. The Time Arrow of Spacetime Geometry . . . . . . . . . 133 5.1 Thermodynamics of Black Holes . . . . . . . . . . 137 5.2 Thermodynamics of Acceleration . . . . . . . . . . 146 5.3 Expansion of the Universe . . . . . . . . . . . . . 151 5.4 Geometrodynamics and Intrinsic Time . . . . . . . . 159 6. The Time Arrow in Quantum Cosmology . . . . . . . . . 169 6.1 Phase Transition of the Vacuum . . . . . . . . . . 171 6.2 Quantum Gravity and the Quantization of Time . . . . 174 6.2.1 Quantization of the Friedmann Universe . . . . . 177 6.2.2 The Emergence of Classical Time . . . . . . . 185 6.2.3 Black Holes in Quantum Cosmology . . . . . . 193 Epilog . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 197 Appendix: ASimpleNumericalToyModel . . . . . . . . . . 201 References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 207 SubjectIndex . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 227 Introduction Prelim.4th edtn.(Nov 00): www.time-direction.de Theasymmetryofnatureundera‘reversaloftime’(thatis,areversalofmo- tion and change) appears only too obvious, as it deeply afiects our own form of existence. If physics is to justify the hypothesis that its laws control ev- erythingthathappensinnature,itshouldbeabletoexplain(orconsistently describe) this fundamental asymmetry which deflnes what may be called a direction in time or even | as will have to be discussed | a direction of time.Surprisingly,theverylawsofnatureareinpronouncedcontrasttothis fundamentalasymmetry:theyareessentiallysymmetricundertimereversal. It is this discrepancy that deflnes the enigma of the direction of time, while there is no lack of asymmetric formalisms or pictures that go beyond the empirical dynamical laws. Ithasindeedprovenappropriatetodividetheformaldynamicaldescrip- tion of nature into laws and initial conditions. Wigner (1972), in his Nobel Prizelecture,calleditNewton’sgreatestdiscovery,sinceitdemonstratesthat the laws by themselves are far from determining nature. The formulation of these two pieces of the dynamical description requires that appropriate kine- matical concepts (formal states or conflgurations z, say), which allow the unique mapping (or ‘representation’) of all possible states of physical sys- tems, have already been deflned on empirical grounds. For example, consider the mechanics of N mass points. Each state z is then equivalent to N points in three-dimensional space, which may be rep- resented in turn by their 3N coordinates with respect to a certain frame of reference. States of physical flelds are instead described by certain func- tions on three-dimensional space. If the laws of nature, in particular in their relativistic form, contain kinematical elements (that is, constraints for kine- matical concepts that would otherwise be too general), such as divB = 0 in electrodynamics, one should distinguish them from the dynamical laws proper. This is only in formal contrast to relativistic spacetime symmetry (see Sect.5.4). Thelawsofnature,thusreflnedtotheirpurelydynamicalsense,describe the time dependence of physical states, z(t), in a general form | usually by meansofdifierentialequations.Theyarecalleddeterministiciftheyuniquely determine the state at time t from that (and possibly its time derivative) at anyearlierorlatertime,thatis,fromanappropriateinitialorflnalcondition. This symmetric causal structure of dynamical determinism is stronger than thetraditionalconceptofcausality,whichrequiresthateveryeventinnature 2 Introduction Prelim.4thedtn.(Nov00):www.time-direction.de must possess a speciflc cause (in its past), while not necessarily an efiect (in its future). The Principle of Su–cient Reason can be understood in this asymmetriccausalsensethatwoulddependonanabsolutedirectionoftime. However, only since Newton do we interpret uniform motion as ‘event- less’, while acceleration requires a force as the modern form of causa movens (sometimes assumed to act in a retarded, but hardly ever in an advanced manner). From the ancient point of view, terrestrial bodies were regarded as eventless or ‘natural’ when at rest, celestial ones when moving in circular or- bits (including epicycles), or when at rest on the celestial (‘crystal’) spheres. These motions thus did not require any dynamical causes according to this picture,similartouniformmotiontoday.Noneofthetraditionalcauses(nei- ther physical nor other ones) ever questioned the fundamental asymmetry in (or of) time, as there were no con(cid:176)icting symmetric dynamical laws yet. Newton’sconceptofaforceasdeterminingacceleration(thesecondtime derivativeofthe‘state’)formsthebasisoftheformalHamiltonianconceptof states in phase space (with corresponding dynamical equations of flrst order intime).Firstordertimederivativesofstatesinconflgurationspace,required todeflnemomenta,canbefreelychosenaspartoftheinitialconditions.Inits Hamiltonianform,thispartofthekinematicsmayappearasdynamics,since the deflnition of canonical momentum depends in general on a dynamical concept (the Lagrangean). Physicists after Newton could easily recognize friction as a possible source of the apparent asymmetry of conventional causality. While difier- entmotionsstartingfromthesameunstablepositionofrestrequiredifierent initialperturbations,friction(ifunderstoodasafundamentalforce)couldde- terministically bring difierent motions to the same rest. States at which the symmetryofdeterminismmaythuscometoanend(perhapsasymptotically) are called attractors in some theories. The term ‘causality’ is unfortunately used with quite difierent mean- ings. In physics it is often synonymous with determinism, or it refers to the relativistic speed limit for the propagation of causal in(cid:176)uences (hence of in- formation). In philosophy it may refer to the existence of laws of nature in general. In (phenomenological) mathematical physics, dynamical deter- minism is often understood to apply in the ‘forward’ direction of time only (thus allowing attractors | see Sect.3.4). Time reversal-symmetric deter- minism was discovered only with the laws of mechanics, when friction could eitherbeneglected,orwasrecognizedasbeingbasedonthermodynamics.An asymmetric concept of ‘intuitive causality’ that is compatible with (though difierent from) symmetric determinism will be deflned and discussed in the introduction to Chap.2. Thetimereversalsymmetryofdeterminismasaconceptdoesnotrequire symmetricdynamicallaws.Forexample,theLorentzforceev£B,actingona charged particle, and resulting from a given external magnetic fleld, changes sign under time reversal (deflned by a replacement of t with ¡t, hence as Introduction 3 a reversal of motion1), as it is proportional to the velocity v. Nonetheless, determinism applies in both directions of time. This time reversal asymmetry of the equation of motion would be can- celled by a simultaneous space re(cid:176)ection, which would reverse the magnetic fleld. Similar ‘compensated asymmetries’ may be found in many other situa- tions, with more or less physical symmetry operations (see Sachs 1987). As an example, the formal asymmetry of the Schr˜odinger equation under time reversal is cancelled by complex conjugation of the wave function on con- flguration space. This can be described by an anti-unitary operation T that leaves the conflguration basis unchanged, Tcjqi = c⁄jqi, for complex num- bers c. For technical reasons, T may be chosen to contain other self-inverse operations,suchasmultiplicationwiththeDiracmatrixfl.Asafurthertriv- ial application, consider the time reversal of states in classical phase space, fq;pg!fq;¡pg.Thistransformationrestoressymmetryunderaformaltime reversal p(t);q(t) ! p(¡t);q(¡t). In quantum theory it corresponds to the transformationTjpi=j¡pithatresultsfromthecomplexRconjugationofthe wave function eipq which deflnes the state jpi=(2…)¡1=2 dqeipqjqi. Fortrajectoriesz(t),oneusuallyincludesthetransformationt!¡tinto the action of T rather than applying it only to the state z: Tz(t):=z (¡t), T where z := Tz is the ‘time-reversed state’. In the Schr˜odinger picture of T quantumtheorythisisautomaticallytakencareofbytheanti-unitarityofT when commuted with the time translation eiHt by means of a time reversal invariant Hamiltonian H. In this sense, ‘T invariance’ means time reversal invariance. When discussing time reversal, one usually assumes invariance under translations in time, in order not to specify an arbitrary origin for the time reversal transformation t!¡t. The time reversal asymmetry characterizing weak forces responsible for K-meson decay is balanced by an asymmetry under CP transformation, where C and P are charge conjugation and spatial re(cid:176)ection, respectively. The latter do not re(cid:176)ect a time reversal elsewhere (such as the reversal of a magneticfleldthatiscausedbyexternalcurrents).Onlyifthecompensating symmetry transformation represents an observable, such as CP, and is not theconsequenceofatimereversalelsewhere,doesonespeakofaviolationof time reversal invariance. Thepossibilityofcompensatingforadynamicaltimereversalasymmetry by another asymmetry (observable or not) re(cid:176)ects the prevailing symmetry of determinism. This is in fundamental contrast to genuine ‘irreversibilities’, which form the subject of this book. No time reversal asymmetry of deter- ministic laws would be able to explain such irreversibilities. 1 Any distinction between reversal of time and reversal of motion (or change, in gen- eral) is meaningful only with respect to some concept of absolute or external time (see Chap.1).Anasymmetryofthefundamentaldynamicallawswoulddeflne(orpresume)an absolutedirectionoftime|justasNewton’sequationsdeflneabsolutetimeuptolinear transformations(includingareversalofitssign,whichisthusnotabsolutelydeflnedinthe absenceofasymmetricfundamentalforces). 4 Introduction Prelim.4thedtn.(Nov00):www.time-direction.de Allknownfundamentallawsofnaturearesymmetricundertimereversal aftercompensationbyanappropriatesymmetrytransformation,T^,say,since theselawsaredeterministic.Forexample,T^ =CPT inparticlephysics,while T^fE(r);B(r)g = fE(r);¡B(r)g in classical electrodynamics. This means that for any trajectory z(t) that is a solution of the dynamical laws there is a time-reversed solution z (¡t), where z is the ‘time-reversed state’ of z, T^ T^ obtained by applying the compensating symmetry transformation. ‘Initial’conditions(contrastedtothedynamicallaws)areunderstoodas conditionswhichflxtheintegrationconstants,thatis,whichselectparticular solutions of the equations of motion. They could just as well be regarded as flnal conditions, even though this would not re(cid:176)ect the usual operational (hence asymmetric) application of the theory. These initial conditions are to select the solutions which are ‘actually’ found in nature. In modern versions ofquantumfleldtheory,eventheboundarybetweenlawsofnatureandinitial conditions blurs. Certain parameters which are usually regarded as part of the laws (such as those characterizing the mentioned CP violation) may havearisenbyspontaneoussymmetry-breaking(anindeterministicirreversible process of disputed nature in quantum theory | see Sects.4.6 and 6.1). An individual (contingent) trajectory z(t) is generically not symmetric under time reversal, that is, not identical with z (¡t). If z(t) is su–ciently T^ complex,thetime-reversedprocessisnotevenlikelytooccuranywhereelsein naturewithinreasonableapproximation.However,mostphenomenaobserved in nature violate time reversal symmetry in a less trivial way if considered as whole classes of phenomena. The members of some class may be found abundant, while the time-reversed class is not present at all. Such symmetry violations will be referred to as ‘fact-like’ | in contrast to the mentioned CP symmetry violations, which are called ‘law-like’. In contrast to what is often claimed in textbooks, this asymmetric appearance of nature cannot be explained by statistical arguments. If the laws are invariant under time reversalwhencompensatedbyanothersymmetrytransformation,theremust be precisely as many solutions in the time-reversed class as in the original one (see Chap.3). Generalclassesofphenomenawhichcharacterizeadirectionintimehave since Eddington been called arrows of time. The most important ones are: 1. Radiation: In most situations, flelds interacting with local sources are appropriately described by retarded (outgoing or defocusing) solutions. For example, a spherical wave is observed after a point-like source event, propa- gatingawayfromit.Thisleadstoadampingofthesourcemotion(seeItem5). For example, one may easily observe ‘spontaneous’ emission (in the absence of incoming radiation), while absorption without any outgoing radiation is hardly ever found. Even an ideal absorber leads to retarded consequences in the corresponding fleld (shadows) | see Chap.2. 2.Thermodynamics: TheSecondLawdS=dt‚0isoftenregardedasalawof nature.Inmicroscopicdescriptionithasinsteadtobeinterpretedasfact-like Introduction 5 (seeChap.3).Thisarrowoftimeiscertainlythemostimportantone.Because ofitsapplicabilitytohumanmemoryandotherphysiologicalprocessesitmay be responsible for the impression that time itself has a direction (related to the apparent (cid:176)ow of time | see Chap.1). 3. Evolution: Dynamical ‘self-organization’ of matter, as observed in biolog- ical and social evolution, for example, may appear to contradict the Second Law. However, it is in agreement with it if the entropy of the environment is properly taken into account (Sect.3.4). 4. Quantum Mechanical Measurement: The probability interpretation of quantum mechanics is usually understood as a fundamental indeterminism of the future. Its interpretation and compatibility with the deterministic Schr˜odinger equation constitutes a long-standing open problem of modern physics. Quantum ‘events’ are often dynamically described by a collapse of the wave function, in particular during the process of measurement. In the absence of a collapse, quantum mechanical interaction leads to growing en- tanglement (quantum nonlocality) | see Chap.4. 5. Exponential Decay: Unstable states (in particular quantum mechanical ‘particle resonances’) usually fade away exponentially with increasing time (see Sect.4.5), while exponential growth is only observed in self-organizing situations (cf. Item 3 above). 6. Gravityseemsto‘force’allmattertocontractwithincreasingtimeaccord- ingitsattractivity.However,thisisanotherprejudiceaboutthecausalaction of forces. Gravity leads to the acceleration of contraction (or deceleration of expansion) in both directions of time, since acceleration is a second time derivative.Theobservedcontractionofcomplexgravitatingsystems(suchas stars) against their internal pressure is in fact controlled by thermodynami- calandradiationphenomena.Suchgravitatingobjectsarecharacterizedbya negativeheatcapacity,andclassicallyevenbytheabilitytocontractwithout limit in accordance with the Second Law (see Chap. 5). In general relativity thisleadstotheoccurrenceofasymmetricfuture horizonsthroughwhichob- jects can only disappear. The discussion of quantum flelds in the presence of such black holes during recent decades has led to the further conclusion that horizons must possess fundamental thermodynamical properties (tempera- ture and entropy). This is remarkable, since horizons characterize spacetime, hence time itself. On the other hand, expansion against gravity is realized by the universe as a whole. Since it represents a unique process, this cosmic expansion does not deflne a class of phenomena. For this and other reasons it is often conjectured to be the ‘master arrow’ from which all other arrows may be derived (see Sects.5.3 and 6.2.1). In spite of their fact-like nature, these arrows of time, in particular the thermodynamicalone,havebeenregardedbysomeofthemosteminentphysi- cists as even more fundamental than the dynamical laws. For example, Ed- dington (1928) wrote: 6 Introduction Prelim.4thedtn.(Nov00):www.time-direction.de \The law that entropy always increases holds, I think, the supreme position among the laws of nature. If someone points out to you that your pet theory of the universe is in disagreement with Maxwell’s equations { then so much theworseforMaxwell’sequations....butifyourtheoryisfoundtobeagainst the second law of thermodynamics, I can give you no hope; there is nothing for it but to collapse in deepest humiliation." And Einstein (1949) remarked: \It" (thermodynamics) \is the only physical theory of universal content con- cerningwhichIamconvincedthat,withintheframeworkoftheapplicability of its basic concepts, it will never be overthrown." Regardless of whether these remarks will always remain valid, their meaning should be understood correctly. They were hardly meant to express doubts inthederivabilityofthis‘fundamental’thermodynamicalarrowoftimefrom presumeddynamicallawsinthemannerofBoltzmann(seeChap.3).Rather, theyseemtoexpresstheirauthors’convictionintheinvarianceofthederived results under modiflcations and generalizations of these laws. However, the derivation will be shown to require important assumptions about the initial stateoftheuniverse.IftheSecondLawisfact-likeinthissense,itsviolation or reversal must at least be compatible with the dynamical laws. The arrows of time listed above describe an asymmetry in the history of the physical world under a formal reversal of time. This history can be considered as a whole, like a complete movie fllm sitting on the desk, or an ordered stack of static picture frames (‘states’), without any selection of a present (one speciflc ‘actual’ frame) or an external distinction between beginning and end. This is sometimes called the ‘block universe view’ (cf. Price 1996), and contrasted to that of an evolving universe (based on the concept of a ‘(cid:176)ow of time’, picture by picture, as seen by an external movie viewer as a deflner of ‘absolute’ time for the movie). Itappearsdoubtfulthatthesedifierentview pointsshouldhavedifierent power of explaining an asymmetry in the content of the movie, even though they are regarded as basically difierent by many philosophers, and also by some physicists (Prigogine 1980, von Weizs˜acker 1982) | see also Chap.1. The second point of view is related to the popular position that the past be ‘flxed’, while the future is ‘open’ and does ‘not yet exist’. The asymmetry of history is then regarded as the ‘outcome’ (or the consequence) of this time- directed ‘process of coming-into-being’. (The abundance of quotation marks indicates how our language is loaded with prejudice about the (cid:176)ow of time.) The fact that there are documents, such as fossils, only about the past, and thatwecannotrememberthefuture,2 appearsasevidenceforthis‘structure of time’ (as it is called), which is also referred to as the ‘historical nature’ (Geschichtlichkeit) of the world. 2 \It’sabadmemorythatonlyworksbackwards"saystheWhiteQueentoAlice.

Description:
For this third edition H. D. Zeh has thoroughly revised his book to include important new results. At the same time it retains the features that make it a classic text on irreversibility, and one which clearly distinguishes the latter from time asymmetry. New findings are presented particularly in t
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.