ebook img

Aristotle's De Motu Animalium PDF

230 Pages·1986·18.4 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Aristotle's De Motu Animalium

Aristotle s DE MOTU ANIMALIUM Text with Translation, Commentary, and Interpretive Essays by MARTHA CRAVEN NUSSBAUM PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS PRINCETON ho ~HfV'\ Published by Princeton University Press, 41 William Street, To the memory of my father, George Craven, 1901-1972 Princeton, New Jersey 08540 In the United Kingdom: Princeton University Press, Chichester, West Sussex Copyright © 1978 by Princeton University Press All Rights Reserved Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data will be found on the last printed page of this book First Princeton Paperback printing, with corrections, 1985 IXC 77-72132 ISBN 0-691-07724-8 ISBN 0-691-02035-3 (pb.) Publication of this book has been aided by a grant from The Andrew W. Mellon Foundation Princeton University Press books are printed on acid-free paper and meet the guidelines for permanence and durability of the Committee on Production Guidelines for Book Longevity of the Council on Library Resources Printed in the United States of America 9 8 7 6 5 4 *2551082554* Filozoficka fakulta Univerzity Karlovy v Praze h'^ll00i CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS IX ABBREVIATIONS USED FOR WORKS OF ARISTOTLE XI ABBREVIATIONS USED FOR JOURNALS AND REFERENCE WORKS xii INTRODUCTION XV NOTE TO THE PAPERBACK EDITION XXV I AUTHENTICITY, TEXT TRANSMISSION, AND MANUSCRIPTS 1 Chapter 1. The Authorship and Dating of the De Motu Animalium 3 Chapter 2. The Manuscripts 13 II TEXT AND TRANSLATION 19 Note on the Translation 20 Text 25 Translation 24 III INTERPRETIVE ESSAYS 57 Essay 1: Aristotle on Teleological Explanation 59 The Democritean Challenge 61 The Level of Explanation: Form and Matter 67 Teleology: The Direction of Explanation 74 Self-Maintaining Systems 76 Functions 81 Teleology and Intentionality 85 Teleology and Necessity 88 Teleology and the Universe 93 Appendix: The Function of Man 100 Essay 2: The De Motu Animalium and Aristotle's Scien­ tific Method 107 The MA and Physics VIII 114 Animal Motion and Heavenly Motion 121 Chapters 1 and 2: introductory remarks on animals 121 Chapters 3 and 4: the arguments for an external unmoved mover 125 Essay 3: The Sumphuton Pneuma and the De Motu Anhnaliuvfs Account of Soul and Body 143 The pneuma and hylomorphism 146 The pneuma and Aristotle's theory of matter 158 VII CONTENTS Essay 4: Practical Syllogisms and Practical Science 165 Necessity and the Practical-Theoretical Parallel 175 The Practical Syllogism in the De Motu 184 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS The Syllogism in EN VII and DA III 201 Rules and Practical Consistency 210 Essay 5: The Role of Phantasia in Aristotle's Explana- tions of Action 221 This book could not have been written without the Society Phantasia in the accounts of action 232 of Fellows at Harvard, which supported me generously dur­ The use and range of phantasia 241 ing its preparation and made it possible for me to spend a Phantasia and aisthisis 255 year in England, during which much of the work was Phantasia and orexis 261 completed. Phantasia and thinking 265 Aristotle wrote of philosophical studies that "it is not easy IV COMMENTARY 271 to be continuously active in solitude; but with others and Chapter 1 273 towards others it is easier" (EN 1170a5-7). This book owes Chapter 2 286 an enormous debt to those whose philosophical acumen and Chapter 3 292 Chapter 4 311 whose friendship inspired and encouraged me through many Chapter 5 325 drafts. My first thanks are due to G. E. L. Owen, who sug­ Chapter 6 331 gested this as a thesis topic and supported me through every Chapter 7 341 stage in my work. His dedication, his boundless energy, Chapter 8 353 and his incisive intellect are a model for me, as they are for Chapter 9 369 everyone working in this field. To Terence Irwin, my Chapter 10 374 second thesis reader, I am grateful for a detachment and a Chapter 11 379 lucidity that repeatedly engendered productive dissatisfac­ tion with current progress. My understanding of various BIBLIOGRAPHY 387 problems connected with practical reasoning and the prac­ INDEX 401 tical syllogism owes much to conversations and corres­ INDEX OF PROPER NAMES 406 pondence with David Wiggins; the whole book owes more INDEX LOCORUM 412 still to his insight, encouragement, and friendship. Conver­ sations with Nelson Goodman and Thomas Nagel were in­ valuable for my revisions of what is now Essay 5. In Albert Henrichs, the text and many portions of the commentary found a critic both diligent and acute. Gerasimos Santas and Marianne McDonald read the entire manuscript with great care and made a number of valuable suggestions. Dur­ ing the final stages of revision I was stimulated by conver­ sations with Hilary Putnam and John Rawls, by forceful criticisms from Zeph Stewart, and by questions from Bruce Altshuler and the students in my Philosophy 105. I par­ ticularly wish to thank Norman Malcolm for giving me per- Vlll IX ACKNOWLEDGMENTS mission to discuss a forthcoming article of his in Essay 4. There are many others whose contributions have been ABBREVIATIONS USED FOR WORKS OF valuable to me, and I hope they will forgive this list, a ARISTOTLE totally inadequate gesture of appreciation: J. L. Ackrill, D. M. Balme, J. Cooper, D. J. Furley, R. Kassel, C. Kirwan, A. C. Lloyd, Paul Moraux, Malcolm Schofield, Peter M. Smith, Richard Sorabji, Bernard Williams. Bckker nos. Cat. Categories 1-15 Translations from the Greek (including the Homer Dl De Interpretatione 16-24 translation in Essay 1) are my own, unless otherwise APr Prior Analytics 24-70 acknowledged. APo Posterior Analytics 71-100 Martha Craven Nussbaum Top. Topics 100-164 SE De Sophisticis Elenchis 164-184 Ph. Physics 184-267 DC De Caelo 268-313 GC De Generatione et Corruptione 314-338 Meteor. Meteorologica 338-390 DA De Anhna 402-435 PN Parva Naturalia 436-486 Sens. De Sensu 436-449 Mem. De Memoria 449-453 Somn. De Somno 453-458 Insomn. De Insomniis 458-462 Div. Somn. De Divinatione per Somnum 462-464 Long. De Longitudine Vitae 464-467 Juv. De Juventute 467-470 Resp. De Respiratione 470-480 HA Historia Animalium 486-638 PA De Partibus Animalium 639-697 MA De Motu Animalium 698-704 IA De Incessu Animalium 704-714 GA De Generatione Animalium 715-789 Probl. Problemata 859-967 Metaph. Metaphysics 980-1093 EN Nicomachean Ethics 1094-1181 MM Magna Moralia 1181-1213 EE Endeviian Ethics 1214-1249 Pol. Politics 1252-1342 Rhet. Rhetoric 1354-1420 Po. Poetics 1447-1462 x XI ABBREVIATIONS USED FOR JOURNALS AND ABBREVIATIONS REFERENCE WORKS RPh Revue de philologie, de litterature, et d'histoire anciennes AbhBerl, AbhMainz Abhandlungen of Berlin and Mainz Aca­ ZDMG Zeitschrift der deutschen morgenldndis- demies chen Gesellschaft AGP Archiv fiir die Geschichte der Philoso­ ZOG Zeitschrift fiir die osterreichischen Gym- phic nasien AJP American journal of Philology AntCl L'Antiquke classique APQ American Philosophical Quarterly BfP British Journal of Psychology BJPS British Journal of the Philosophy of Science CAG Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca CIMed Classica et Mediaevalia CQ Classical Quarterly CR Classical Review HSCP Harvard Studies in Classical Philology JHB Journal of the History of Biology JHS Journal of Hellenic Studies JOBG Jahrbuch der osterreichischen byzantinis- chen Gesellschaft JPhilol Journal of Philology JPhilos Journal of Philosophy MusHelv Museum Helveticum PAS Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society PASS Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Vol. PBA Proceedings of the British Academy PCPS Proceedings of the Cambridge Philolog­ ical Society PPA Philosophy and Public Affairs PQ Philosophical Quarterly PR Philosophical Review PS Philosophy of Science RE Pauly-Wissowa, Real-Encyclopadie der klassischen Altertumswissenschaft REG Revue des Etudes grecques RM Review of Metaphysics Xll xin \-=*- INTRODUCTION "The unexplained should by all means be inexplicable, the unexplainable by all means unnatural, supernatural, miraculous—thus goes the demand in the souls of all the religious and the metaphysicians . . .; while the scientific person sees in this demand the 'evil principle'." Friedrich Nietzsche, Human, All-Too-Human, 136 I The aim of this book is to ask through a study of one of his most complicated treatises on explanation, how far, and in what sense, the demands of the "scientific person" are Aristotle's. All men by nature reach out for understanding (Metaph. 980al). What form does this episteme take, and how far, in the various areas of human life and study, can our need for it be satisfied? What will the most satisfactory answers to our "why" questions be like? How are our various answers related? How far should we press the demand for understanding? These are, of course, the central preoccupations of Aris­ totle's philosophical work; no comprehensive account could be attempted here. But the De Motu Animalium, with its cryptic and intricate attempt to formulate answers to some of these questions, provides us with an occasion to make some preliminary moves toward such an account, while at the same offering a comprehensive exegesis of a little-known source of evidence. Aristotle's treatment of these central problems is never dogmatic. One of the great virtues that distinguishes him from his philosophical predecessors is his reluctance to press for a single answer when the evidence points to several, or to apply incautiously in one area a solu­ tion that had been found promising in another. The best way to build towards an account of his theories seems, then, xv ARISTOTLE'S DE MOTU ANIMALIUM INTRODUCTION to be to begin with particular problems, or with the data of (Diog. Laert. §17). Mathemata, the texts of distinguished a particular text, "through which we may seek the general books and of common experience, here take the place of account as well, and with which we think it ought to be Plato's mystical vision of the Forms as our best (and only) in harmony" (cf. MA 698a13-14). As Aristotle's treatises source of philosophical light. Aristotle insists that we must are related to our experience of and talk about the world, confront great obscurities not with a prayer for sudden so it is the aim of this commentary to stand to one of his insight, but by "trying to say the phainomenori"—by setting works: as a sorting-out and an interpretation that both out clearly what we and others say; the student who has "saves" the "appearances" and illuminates them. a genuine thirst for philosophy will consider it a sign of Aristotle was the first philosopher to cherish books and self-respect to attempt neither more nor less than this.4 I reading. He believed that all genuine philosophy is com­ shall try here to describe an Aristotelian text as it appears to mentary—on the texts of the "wise" and on the data of our me, and to show how it might be a source of learning. My ordinary speech.1 Throughout his career, he defended com­ ideal would be to treat Aristotle with the critical rigor, the mentary against the claims of those who insisted that the independence, and the devotion5 with which he treated philosopher ought to seek a mystical revelation that would those who helped him to understand the world. set him apart from the common man, and teach a self- contained doctrine that would make no attempt to return to the "appearances," to the world in which we live our II daily lives.2 It seems particularly fitting, then, that one who We see animals moving around—walking, swimming, flying, thinks Aristotle one of the very wisest of "the many and the wise"3 should embrace the philosophical task that he creeping. And we ourselves are also moving animals. Why? What role does motion from place to place play in animal invented—and as one which can contribute not only to lives? And what would be an adequate explanation of a par­ our understanding of Aristotle but, ultimately, to our grasp ticular animal movement? Is there some general account we of the questions that this wise man thought most important. can give of these phenomena that will hold good for humans If it was with a sneer that Plato invited students occupied with higher matters to pay a visit to "the reader's house" and animals alike? With these questions, and with the hope {Vita Marciana 5), we might answer the sneer with the that such a general answer will be found, Aristotle begins "reader's" reported epigram: "As sight receives light the De Motu Animalium. from the surrounding air, so does the soul from its studies" If the work assumes anything from the beginning, it is that it always makes sense to ask the question "Why?" about 1 On the Aristotelian notion of the "appearances" (phainomena), a particular case of animal motion. This is not a trivial claim. cf. Essays 2 and 5. I am indebted throughout to Owen's important "Tithenai," which first made the vital point that the phainomena in­ 4 DC 291b25-28; this passage is discussed further in Essay 2, and clude what we say, as well as what we see and hear. especially in n. 47, which defends the reading here adopted. * Cf. DC 293*27-30, 306*5 ff.; GC 316*5-14, 325*13 ff.; and notes to "Aristotle (if it was, indeed, he) wrote that Plato was a man chapter 1, 698*4 ff. Dialectic may, of course, require us to abandon "whom it is not right for base men even to praise" (Olympiadorus or alter some of our initial beliefs (Top. 101*33, EN 1145b2-6); but if In PL Gorg. 41.3, emphasis mine)—thus succinctly indicating that the argument is not merely eristic (cf. 160*33 ff.), it will show that the independent critic can be more truly reverent than the disciple. our most basic beliefs and sayings require the change. Many attacks on Aristotle's reputation as a historian of philosophy 'Top. 100*21, 104*8-10. neglect this point. xvi XVII INTRODUCTION ARISTOTLE'S DE MOTU ANIMALIUM I am not saying that I do not know the explanation; I To see this, let us imagine that two Greek biologists are am saying that I know that there is no explanation. conversing—somewhere in Asia Minor, by the side of a Animals, especially tortoises, are arbitrary creatures. large fresh-water pond. There are some cases (though not terribly many) B.: Why did that tortoise cross the mud? (cf. MA 698b16) where they move this way or that, jump in the air or A.: To get to the other side. cross the mud, for no reason at all. It is a mistake to B.: (triumphantly) Wrong. suppose that all cases can be forced into your pattern; A.: Well, what was the reason then? some are simply intractable, and any good theory of B.: No reason at all. animal motion must acknowledge this. To say that all A.: What do you mean? Didn't he go to get something? motions can be—even potentially—understood and Wasn't there something he wanted, something he explained is just a fashionable dogmatism. couldn't get without crossing the mud? B.: No. You can see that there's nothing over there but B.'s position is not at all absurd or indefensible6—though more mud. there is, of course, danger in retreating to such a position too A.: Well maybe he is running away from something. If soon in any particular problem case. We will want to be very his feet weren't slipping so much (cf. MA 698b17), sure that he has not simply overlooked some relevant piece he would be going rather fast. The origin of motion of evidence, or failed to develop the best kind of explana­ can be an object either of pursuit or of avoidance tory theory. It is not through researchers like B. that sci­ (cf. 701b33-34). ence has progressed. Still, we seem to have no way of re­ B.: No, there is no reason. On your instructions I have futing him in general. Even if he does accept as adequate been sitting beside this pond studying these tortoises many explanations we now use, for example those that allow every day for three years now. So you had better us to make consistently successful predictions, it is hard to write in your Historia Animalium that they have been imagine that there will never be a piece of recalcitrant evi­ known to move for no reason. dence he can use against us. And even if he does not see any, A.: I see. You mean that there isn't any ordinary ideolog­ he may insist on holding it open as a conceptual possibility ical account in terms of the tortoise's goals and de­ that there might be. He will tell us that it is simply a preju­ sires. As part of your research you've planted some dice, connected with our modern optimism for science, that mechanical device in his heart that simply triggers the every motion can be explained and that nothing is random motor activity. or arbitrary. B.: You are trying to substitute one sort of explanation for It is from the conviction that B. is wrong about the ex­ another. I am saying something entirely different: planation of particular animal motions—or, at the very least, there just is no explanation. from the decision that the only sensible thing for the sci­ A.: (turning to go) Well, send a messenger to me when entist to do is to force him to cede as much ground as you find it, and then we can get together and finish "A form of it has been defended by von Wright in EU and a those chapters. subtler and more moderate related position is defended by Malcolm B.: You are deliberately misunderstanding me. You are in "Intention and Behavior". Both of these, and Aristotle's view, are looking for excuses to abuse my professional standing. discussed at length in Essay 4. xvm XIX ARISTOTLE'S DE MOTU ANIMALIUM INTRODUCTION possible, that Aristotle begins the MA. I am inclined to think meal for the light it could shed on the discussion of similar that he would find B.'s position not just pragmatically un­ questions in the ethical and cosmological works. But it is sound, but more than that: a failure to comprehend the from a study of its entire plan and argument, rather than meaning of our notions of action and motion. B., one might from considering it bit by bit, that one can emerge with argue, is not even speaking our language when he talks of the most useful insights into the many problems with which an inexplicable motion, or a random action.7 Tuche, chance, it deals. Because it is so full of allusions to other Aristotelian is not a separate explanatory principle; all motions described works, it cannot be interpreted without extensive analysis as coming about "by chance" have, under some description, of parallel discussions and an attempt to see the problem in an adequate explanation. If Aristotle's vaunted optimism for question as it emerges from Aristotle's work as a whole. The science means anything (and it does not mean everything framework of line-by-line commentary proves, in conse­ it has been taken to mean—cf. Essays 2 and 4) it does mean quence, too confining. One has to take a stand on some that it is always appropriate to ask, "Why this motion?," major issues in Aristotle's philosophy of science, ethics, and and to search persistently for the most adequate response. philosophy of mind before one can claim to have interpreted Aristotle realizes, of course, that there are a number of the MA. The aim of the interpretive essays is to provide ways this question might be answered. A main aim of the this kind of wide-ranging discussion of central problems, treatise will be to analyze and defend a certain kind of while leaving for notes textual, historical, and less central answer—the teleological—and to indicate its relationship to exegetical points. Sometimes the division may appear arbi­ other answers. In the process, Aristotle presents an analysis trary: a point of some philosophical importance may find of motivation that has important implications for our under­ itself in the notes because it simply did not help the argu­ standing of his theory of soul and his account of human ment of any of the essays, or a rather technical piece of deliberation. And the treatise addresses itself to cosmological exegesis may be found in an essay because it is crucial to its questions as well: the conditions for motion in the universe, argument. I have tried to make cross-references as extensive the necessity of postulating an unmoved mover. We dis­ as possible, in order to minimize this problem for the reader. cover in some cases that its unusual combination of questions But I hope that this format will make my views on major has suggested to Aristotle more adequate solutions for prob­ issues as accessible as possible to the reader with no knowl­ lems he had approached separately in other works. edge of Greek (none of the essays uses untranslated Greek), and to those interested less in the MA itself than in Aristotle's position on certain central problems in philosophy. Ill The first essay provides a general introductory account The MA is cryptic and brief, occasionally obscure.8 Be­ of Aristotle's views on functional and teleological explana­ cause of its heterogeneity, it has often been studied piece- tion and, in an appendix, an analysis of the famous "man's ' Cf. Essay 4. and Burley have recently been edited, and are occasionally useful. * The only full-length commentaries ever written on the MA (to (On all these, see the full discussions in my doctoral thesis, Part I, my knowledge) are the twelfth-century commentary by Michael chapter 2.) Among modern exegeses, most valuable are Farquharson's of Ephesos and the thirteenth-century treatise De Principiis Motus notes to his Oxford Translation. Notes are also provided by Torraca Trogressivi of Albertus Magnus. Short paraphrases were written by and Louis, and summaries of the argument can be found in Jaeger, a number of mediaeval philosophers, among which those of Buridan "Pneuma," and During, Aristoteles, 345. XX XXl

Description:
The aim of this book is to ask through a study of one of his most complicated treatises on explanation, how far, and in what sense, the demands of the 'scientific person' are Aristotle's.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.