’ ARISTOTLE IN AQUINAS S THEOLOGY ’ Aristotle in Aquinas s Theology Editedby GILLES EMERY, OP, and MATTHEW LEVERING 1 3 GreatClarendonStreet,Oxford,OX26DP, UnitedKingdom OxfordUniversityPressisadepartmentoftheUniversityofOxford. ItfurtherstheUniversity’sobjectiveofexcellenceinresearch,scholarship, andeducationbypublishingworldwide.Oxfordisaregisteredtrademarkof OxfordUniversityPressintheUKandincertainothercountries #OxfordUniversityPress2015 Themoralrightsoftheauthorshavebeenasserted FirstEditionpublishedin2015 Impression:1 Allrightsreserved.Nopartofthispublicationmaybereproduced,storedin aretrievalsystem,ortransmitted,inanyformorbyanymeans,withoutthe priorpermissioninwritingofOxfordUniversityPress,orasexpresslypermitted bylaw,bylicenceorundertermsagreedwiththeappropriatereprographics rightsorganization.Enquiriesconcerningreproductionoutsidethescopeofthe aboveshouldbesenttotheRightsDepartment,OxfordUniversityPress,atthe addressabove Youmustnotcirculatethisworkinanyotherform andyoumustimposethissameconditiononanyacquirer PublishedintheUnitedStatesofAmericabyOxfordUniversityPress 198MadisonAvenue,NewYork,NY10016,UnitedStatesofAmerica BritishLibraryCataloguinginPublicationData Dataavailable LibraryofCongressControlNumber:2015940445 ISBN 978–0–19–874963–9 Printedandboundby CPIGroup(UK)Ltd,Croydon,CR04YY LinkstothirdpartywebsitesareprovidedbyOxfordingoodfaithand forinformationonly.Oxforddisclaimsanyresponsibilityforthematerials containedinanythirdpartywebsitereferencedinthiswork. ’ Editors Preface ThisworkinvestigatestheroleofAristotelianconcepts,principles,andthemes in Thomas Aquinas’s theology. The ten chapters are intended to provide an introductiontothesignificanceofAquinas’stheologicalreceptionofAristotle in certain major loci: the Trinity, the angels, soul and body, the Mosaic law, grace, charity, justice, contemplation and action, Christ, and the sacraments. Some of these chapters focus on the Summa theologiae, while others range more widely in Aquinas’s corpus. Aristotelian concepts, of course, appear throughout Aquinas’s theology. Jean-Pierre Torrell has pointed out that “the presence and influence of Aristotle in Thomas’s writings no longer have to be shown....Thomas retained so many important elements of Aristotle’s thought that they cannot be numbered.”1 On the one hand, for quite some time, it has above all been the influence of Aristotle on Aquinas’s philosophy that has been the center of attention. Thomas O’Meara states, “Often the approach to Thomas Aquinas during the neo-Thomist revival from 1850 to 1960wastodescribeaphilosophy.Duringthattimefarmorebookstreatedhis philosophy than his theology....A search through a library catalogue or a perusal of a bibliography of articles on Aquinas written prior to Vatican II yieldsmorematerialonthemetaphysicsofanunmovedmoverortheabstract descriptionofphilosophicalvirtuesthanonsalvationbyJesusortheroleofa sacrament.”2 On the other hand, perhaps in reaction to philosophical neo- Thomism, or perhaps because this Aristotelian influence appears no longer necessarytodemonstrate,theroleofAristotleinAquinas’stheologypresently receiveslesstheologicalattentionthandoesAquinas’suseofotherauthorities, especially in domains outside of theologicalethics—somuch so that in some theological circles the influence of Aristotle upon Aquinas’s theology is no longerwellunderstood. WhenAquinasdescribeshisuseof“authorities”intheSummatheologiae,he states that sacra doctrina accepts “the authority of philosophers in those ques- tionsinwhichtheywereabletoknowthetruthbynaturalreason.”3Hecarefully adds, however, that sacra doctrina “makes use of these authorities as extrinsic and probable arguments,” by contrast to the proper and incontrovertible 1 Jean-Pierre Torrell, OP, Aquinas’s Summa: Background, Structure, and Reception, trans. Benedict M. Guevin (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 2005), pp.76–7. 2 Thomas F. O’Meara, OP, Thomas Aquinas Theologian (Notre Dame, IN: University of NotreDamePress,1997),pp.xi–xii. 3 STI,q.1,a.8,ad2.Englishtranslationfrom:ThomasAquinas,SummaTheologiae,trans. FathersoftheEnglishDominicanProvince,vol.1(Westminster,MD:ChristianClassics,1981). vi Editors’Preface “authority of the canonical Scriptures” and the proper but only probable authority of the Fathers.4 His vision and practice of theology firmly avoid rationalism.Inthislight,TorrellaptlypresentsAquinasasa“spiritualmaster” and a “mystic”: “The figure who at times seems to be known only for his philosophy is also first and foremost a theologian, a commentator on Sacred Scripture, an attentive student of the Fathers of the Church, and a man concerned about the spiritual and pastoral repercussions of his teaching.”5 Aquinasisindeed“firstandforemostatheologian.”AsRobertBarronwrites: “WhenoneinterpretsThomasasarationalistphilosopherortheologian,one missestheburningheartofeverythinghewrote.Aquinaswasasaintdeeplyin lovewithJesusChrist,andtheimageofChristpervadestheentireedificethat is his philosophical, theological, and scriptural work. Above all, Thomas Aquinas was a consummate spiritual master, holding up the icon of the Wordmadefleshandinvitingothersintoitstransformativepower.”6 NotleastbecauseofthesuccessofTorrell’smasterfulwork,scholarstoday tend to focus on the biblical, patristic, and liturgical sources of Aquinas’s theology,aswellasonAquinas’sdebtstoPlatonicinsightssuchasparticipa- tion.7Butforthis very reason, Aquinas’stheologicaluse of Aristotle requires 4 STI,q.1,a.8,ad2.SeeM.-D.Chenu’sclassicdiscussionofAquinas’suseof“auctoritates”in Marie-DominiqueChenu,OP,TowardUnderstandingSaintThomas,trans.AlbertM.Landry andDominicHughes(Chicago:HenryRegnery,1964),ch.4. 5 Jean-PierreTorrell,OP,SaintThomasAquinas,vol.2,SpiritualMaster,trans.RobertRoyal (Washington,DC:TheCatholicUniversityofAmericaPress,2003),p.vii.SeealsoJean-Pierre Torrell, OP, Christ and Spirituality in St. Thomas Aquinas, trans. Bernhard Blankenhorn (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 2011); Paul D. Murray, OP, AquinasatPrayer:TheBible,MysticismandPoetry(London:Bloomsbury,2013). 6 RobertBarron,ThomasAquinas:SpiritualMaster(NewYork:Crossroad,1996),p.13. 7 Among many excellent studies, see Thomas F. Ryan, Thomas Aquinas as Reader of the Psalms(NotreDame,IN:UniversityofNotreDamePress,2000);AntoineGuggenheim,Jésus Christ,grandprêtredel’ancienneetdelanouvelleAlliance:Étudethéologiqueetherméneutique du commentaire de saint Thomas d’Aquin sur l’Épître aux Hébreux (Paris: Parole et Silence, 2004);ThomasG.Weinandy,O.F.M.Cap.,DanielA.Keating,andJohnP.Yocum,eds.,Aquinas on Scripture: An Introduction to his Biblical Commentaries (London: T. & T. Clark, 2005); Matthew Levering and Michael Dauphinais, eds., Reading Romans with St. Thomas Aquinas (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press, 2012); Paweł Klimczak, OP, ChristusMagister:LeChristMaîtredanslescommentairesévangéliquesdesaintThomasd’Aquin (Fribourg: Academic Press, 2014); Fran O’Rourke, Pseudo-Dionysius and the Metaphysics of Aquinas (Leiden: Brill, 1992); Rudi A. te Velde, Participation and Substantiality in Thomas Aquinas (Leiden: Brill, 1995); Gregory T. Doolan, Aquinas on the Divine Ideas as Exemplar Causes(Washington,DC:TheCatholicUniversityofAmericaPress,2008);MichaelDauphinais, Barry David, and Matthew Levering, eds., Aquinas the Augustinian (Washington, DC: The CatholicUniversityofAmericaPress,2007).Recentworksinmoraltheologyandphilosophy havecontinuedtoexploreAquinas’sdebttoAristotle:seeforinstanceMaryM.Keys,Aquinas, Aristotle,andthePromiseoftheCommonGood(Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress,2006); Nicholas E. Lombardo, OP, The Logic ofDesire: Aquinas on Emotion(Washington, DC: The CatholicUniversityofAmericaPress,2011);DanielMcInerny,TheDifficultGood:AThomistic Approach to Moral Conflict and Human Happiness (New York: Fordham University Press, 2006); Fabrizio Amerini, Aquinas on the Beginning and End of Human Life, trans. Mark Henninger(Cambridge,MA:HarvardUniversityPress,2013). Editors’Preface vii renewedattention,lestthestudyofAquinas’stheologybecomeone-sided.Our work,therefore,highlightsthesignificanceofAristotleinAquinas’stheology. Readers will encounter here the great Aristotelian themes, such as act and potency, God as pure act, substance and accidents, power and generation, changeandmotion,fourfoldcausality,formandmatter,hylomorphicanthro- pology, the structure of intellection, the relationship between knowledge and will, happiness and friendship, habits and virtues, contemplation and action, politics and justice, the best form of government, private property, and the commongood. Somegeneralbackgroundtoourtopicwillbehelpful,sinceAquinas’suseof Aristotle should not be viewed in isolation from the whole of Christian theology. This is especially so in an introductory work such as the present volume,whosetheologicalaudiencecanbeassumedtopossesswidelydiffer- ingdegreesoffamiliaritywithAristotle’sreceptioninChristiantheologyover the centuries. It is no secret, of course, that strong critiques of Aristotle have been commonplace in the history of theology. For example, Gregory of Nazianzus, though benefiting from Aristotle’s philosophy in some ways, nonethelesscondemnedAristotle’s“meanconceptionofProvidence,hisarti- ficialsystem,hismortalviewofthesoul,andthehuman-centerednatureofhis teaching.”8 Likewise, Augustine complained that his reading of Aristotle’s Categories led him to think of God as simply another substance.9 And in the thirteenthcenturyalone,theCatholicChurch’shierarchywarnedagainstthe theologicaluseofAristotlein1215,1228,1231,1245,1263,1270,and1277.10 During the Renaissance and Reformation period, Aristotle often came under particularly strong attack. Thus, in his Letter to Martin Dorp (1514), Desiderius Erasmus criticized “modern theology” as “so contaminated with Aristotle, with trifling ideas thought up by men, even with secular laws, that I hardly see how it can preserve the true savor of Christ, who is pure and uncontaminated.”11Erasmuswentontoaskrhetorically:“Whatconnectionis there,Iaskyou,betweenChristandAristotle?orbetweensophisticalquibbles andthemysteriesofeternalwisdom?Wherewilltheselabyrinthsofquestions 8 GregoryofNazianzus,Oration27,inGregoryofNazianzus,OnGodandChrist:TheFive TheologicalOrationsandTwoLetterstoCledonius,trans.FrederickWilliamsandLionelWick- ham(Crestwood,NY:St.Vladimir’sSeminaryPress,2002),p.33.GregoryequallycriticizesPlato forhisdoctrineofideasandhishypothesisthatsoulsarecyclicallyreincarnated. 9 Augustine,ConfessionsIV,XVI;trans.HenryChadwick(Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress, 1991),pp.69–70. 10 UlrichG.Leinsle,IntroductiontoScholasticTheology,trans.MichaelJ.Miller(Washington, DC:TheCatholicUniversityofAmericaPress,2010),pp.138–41and144–7.SeealsoRobert Pasnau, “The Latin Aristotle,” in The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle, edited by Christopher Shields(Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,2012),pp.665–89. 11 DesideriusErasmus,“Erasmus’LettertoMartinDorp(1514),”inThePraiseofFolly,trans. ClarenceH.Miller(NewHaven,CT:YaleUniversityPress,1979),pp.139–74,at155. viii Editors’Preface get us?”12 A few years later, Martin Luther rejected (as he put it) “the Thomistic—thatis,theAristotelianchurch.”13Inthecourseofarguingagainst transubstantiation, Luther observed that “Aristotle speaks of subject and accidents so very differently from St. Thomas that it seems to me this great man[St.Thomas]istobepitiednotonlyforattemptingtodrawhisopinions inmattersoffaithfromAristotle,butalsoforattemptingtobasethemupona man whom he did not understand, thus building an unfortunate superstruc- tureuponanunfortunatefoundation.”14 More recently, but along quite similar lines, Karl Barth affirmed that “the ChristianChurchcertainlydoesnotnumberAristotleamongitsancestors.”15 TheRussianOrthodoxtheologianSergiusBulgakov,forhispart,warnedthat “within the limits of Aristotle’s categories, there can be no man in general; human nature exists only in particular individuals (that is precisely why the heresyoftritheismgrewoutofthesoilofAristotelianism).”16And,voicinga representative postmodern viewpoint, the contemporary philosopher Gianni Vattimohasrejected“theattributesfoundinAristotle’spureactorinParme- nides’sBeing,whichstandradicallyopposedtotheideaofBeingasacreation ofafreeandlovingGod.”17 Asonewouldexpect,however,defendersoftheroleofAristotleintheology have not been lacking. Indeed, the depth and breadth of theological indebt- edness to Aristotle over the centuries can easily go unappreciated today, even by scholars who recognize Aristotle’s significance for Aquinas. Richard Rubensteinpointsoutthatformanycenturies,Aristotlewasutterlycentralin a wide variety of fields of study for Jewish, Christian, and Islamic scholars. Duringthemedievalperiod,“onecouldnotbeginadiscussionofmetaphysics, naturalscience,logic,theology,ethics,aesthetics,orpoliticswithoutreferring 12 Erasmus,“Erasmus’LettertoMartinDorp,”p.155. 13 Martin Luther, “The Babylonian Captivity of the Church,” in Martin Luther’s Basic Theological Writings, ed. Timothy F. Lull (Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press, 1989), pp.267–313,at285.SeeDenisR.Janz,LutheronThomasAquinas:TheAngelicDoctorinthe Thought of the Reformer (Stuttgart: F. Steiner Verlag, 1989); Otto H. Pesch, Martin Luther, Thomas von Aquin und die reformatorische Kritik an der Scholastik: Zur Geschichte und WirkungsgeschichteeinesMißverständnissesmitweltgeschichtlichenFolgen(Hamburg:Joachim Jungius-GesellschaftderWissenschaften,1994). 14 Luther,“TheBabylonianCaptivity,”p.285. 15 Karl Barth, Church Dogmatics, vol. 1, The Doctrine of the Word of God, part 1, trans. GeoffreyW.Bromiley,2nded.(Edinburgh:T.&T.Clark,1975),p.11.SeealsoThomasJoseph White,OP,“Introduction:ThomasAquinasandKarlBarth,AnUnofficialCatholic–Protestant Dialogue,” in Thomas Aquinas and Karl Barth: An Unofficial Catholic–Protestant Dialogue, edited by Bruce L. McCormack and Thomas Joseph White (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2013),pp.1–39. 16 Sergius Bulgakov, The Lamb of God, trans. Boris Jakim (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans, 2008),p.67. 17 GianniVattimo,AfterChristianity,trans.LucaD’Isanto(NewYork:ColumbiaUniversity Press,2002),p.120. Editors’Preface ix to Aristotle’s views and dealing respectfully with them.”18 Depending on the Latintranslationsthatweregraduallymadeavailabletothem,19allhigh-and late-medieval Christian theologians in the West were in dialogue with Aris- totle and with Muslim interpreters of Aristotle such as Ibn Sina (Avicenna) andIbnRushd(Averroes).20 In the Christian East, among the many Eastern Fathers who could be named, Basil the Great’s Against Eunomius exhibits the fruitful influence of Aristotle’s Categories and other works—as does John of Damascus’s well- knownPhilosophical Chapters,whichdrawsheavilyupontheeclecticAristo- telianism of Nemesius of Emesa.21Indeed, Marcus Plested has demonstrated Aquinas’s“continuityandaffinitywithalongtraditionofByzantinescholas- ticism going back to the Christological debates of the fifth century and recapitulated in John of Damascus.”22 The Byzantine scholasticism that Plested traces through the nineteenth century, a scholasticism that (at least with respect to the place given to Aristotelian philosophy) included Gregory Palamas, finds a parallel not only in the long tradition of Catholic scholasti- cismbutalsointhecenturiesofLutheranandReformedscholasticism,ledby figuressuchasFrancisTurretin. 18 Richard E. Rubenstein, Aristotle’s Children: How Christians, Muslims, and Jews Redis- coveredAncientWisdomandIlluminatedtheDarkAges(NewYork:Harcourt,2003),p.283. 19 Theseries“AristotelesLatinus”(medievaltranslationsoftheworksofAristotle),partofthe “CorpusPhilosophorumMediiAevi,”isofthegreatesthelpinthisregard.Theproject,stillin progress,startedin1930,withthefirstvolumebeingpublishedin1951.Itiscurrentlysupervised and supported bythe International Union ofAcademies. For instance, thanks to“Aristoteles Latinus,”MartaBorgowasabletodemonstratethatAquinas’scommentaryonthefirstbookof the Sentences makes use of no less than four different translations of Aristotle’s Metaphysics: MartaBorgo,“LaMétaphysiqued’AristotedansleCommentairedeThomasd’AquinauIerlivre des Sentences de Pierre Lombard: Quelques exemples significatifs,” RSPhTh 91 (2007): pp.651–92. 20 See,forexample,MarilynMcCordAdams,SomeLaterMedievalTheoriesoftheEucharist: ThomasAquinas,GilesofRome,DunsScotus,andWilliamOckham(Oxford:OxfordUniversity Press, 2010); Russell L. Friedman, Medieval Trinitarian Thought from Aquinas to Ockham (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010). While critical of Aristotle in certain respects—largely the very respects identified by Gregory of Nazianzus—the great medieval MuslimtheologianandlegalscholarAl-GhazalilikewisedrewuponAristotle,asdidmedieval JewishtheologiansandlegalscholarssuchasMaimonides,Gersonides,andSaadiahGaon. 21 SeeAndrewRadde-Gallwitz,BasilofCaesarea,GregoryofNyssa,andtheTransformationof DivineSimplicity(Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,2009);AndrewLouth,StJohnDamascene: TraditionandOriginalityinByzantineTheology(Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,2002). 22 MarcusPlested,OrthodoxReadingsofAquinas(Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,2012), p.223.Foracontrastingperspective,seeDavidBradshaw,AristotleEastandWest:Metaphysics and the Division of Christendom (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004). Bradshaw holds that the bigger problem is Augustine: “Clearly the gulf separating Augustine from the eastern tradition is immense. It encompasses such basic issues as the nature of being, the simplicity of God, the intelligibility of God, and the final goal of human existence. What is perhapsmostremarkableisthattheAugustinianpresuppositionswehavesketchedcouldcome todominatethethoughtoftheWest,whilehavingvirtuallynoinfluenceintheEast,andyetfor almostathousandyearsneithersiderecognizedwhathadhappened”(p.229).
Description: