ebook img

Aristotelian Matter Unified PDF

30 Pages·2003·0.21 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Aristotelian Matter Unified

Aristotelian Matter Unified∗ John MacFarlane† Draft: Please do not cite or circulate without permission. 1. Introduction What is the matter of a (sublunary) substance? Aristotle seems to give two answers. The first is that a substance’s matter is the substrate (˝poke—menon) of its generation: the hunk of gold that is molded into a statue or the men- strual fluid that is worked up into a living human embryo.1 For I say that matter is just this—the primary substrate of each thing, from which it comes to be, and which persists in the result, not accidentally. (Phys. A9.192a31–2) Matter, in the most proper sense of the term, is to be identified with the substrate which is receptive of generation and destruc- tion. (GC A5.320a2–3) Nownaturalgenerationsarethegenerationsofthosethingswhich come to be by nature; and that out of which they come to be is ∗IamgratefultoaudiencesattheUniversityofMichiganandtheUniversityofCalifor- niaatDavis,andtoEricBrown,MylesBurnyeat,AlanCode,DavidEbrey,AndreaFalcon, MaryLouiseGill,HannahGinsborg,andJoeKarbowskiforcommentsonancestorsofthis paper. †DepartmentofPhilosophy,UniversityofCaliforniaatBerkeley,314MosesHall#2390, Berkeley, CA 94720–2390. E-mail: [email protected]. 1Aristotle countenances matter in two kinds of entities that do not admit of genera- tion or destruction: superlunary substances (like the stars) have “locational matter” ((cid:213)lh topik(cid:160), Met. H1.1042b5–6), and mathematical objects have “intelligible matter” ((cid:213)lh noht(cid:160), Met. Z10.1036a9–12). The conceptual problems I address in this paper arise only forthematterofsublunarysubstances,soIignoretheseotherkindsofmatterthroughout. 1 what we call matter...(Met. Z7.1032a16–17)2 But Aristotle also characterizes the matter of a substance in another way: as the subject (˝poke—menon) of which its form is predicated: the gold shaped into the statue or the body that possesses the capacities constituting the human soul. We say that substance is one kind of what is, and that in several senses: in the sense of matter or that which in itself is not a this, and in the sense of form or essence, which is that precisely in virtue of which a thing is called a this, and thirdly in the sense of that which is compounded of both. ...the body is the subject or matter, not what is attributed to it. Hence the soul must be a substance in the sense of the form of a natural body having life potentially within it. (De An. B1.412a6–21) About two of these we have spoken; about the essence and about the subject, of which we have said that it underlies (˝p(cid:236)keitai) in two senses, either being a “this”—which is the way in which an animal underlies its attributes—or as the matter underlies the complete reality. (Met. Z13.1038b3–7) ...when...the predicate is a form or a “this,” the ultimate sub- ject is matter and material substance. (Met. Θ7.1049a27–36) It’s the same Greek word—˝poke—menon—but not, by our lights, the same idea: hence the tendency of translators to prefer “subject” in some contexts, “substrate” in others. It appears, then, that Aristotelian matter is supposed to play two dis- tinct roles: substrate of substantial change and subject of which form is predicated. But it is notoriously hard to see how any one thing can possibly play both these roles. The problem isn’t obvious if we confine our attention tothe“toy”casewithwhichAristotleoftenillustratesmatter: thegoldbeing molded into a statue. In that case, we can easily identify a single thing— a particular quantity of gold—that is both the preexisting substrate of the statue’s generation and the subject of which the statue’s form or shape is predicated. But on Aristotle’s view, statues are only analogous to real sub- stances (Met. H2.1043a4–5, H3.1043b21–3), and the reshaping of gold is, 2Translations throughout this paper are light revisions of the Revised Oxford Transla- tion (Barnes ed. 1984). 2 strictly speaking, a nonsubstantial change (GC A4.319b14–15). As soon as we turn to the primary cases of substantial change—that is, the generation and destruction of organisms—it becomes difficult to identify anything that can serve as both the preexisting substrate and the matter of which the form is predicated. I am quite certain, for instance, that my body contains no menstrual fluid: yet that is what Aristotle often identifies as the preexisting substrate or matter for the generation of a human being (Met. H6.1044a34– 5, Λ6.1071b29–31, GA A19.727b31–3, A20.729a9–11, B4.740b24–5).3 There does not appear to be anything that can play both the roles Aristotle as- signs to matter. Indeed, there are deep theoretical reasons for thinking that nothing in Aristotle’s system can play both roles. The conclusion many commentators have drawn is that Aristotle really has two concepts of matter, each defined in terms of one of these roles. Call this position bifurcationism. In this paper, I am going to argue on both textual and philosophical grounds that bifurcationism is untenable. I will then sketch a way of thinking about Aristotelian matter that allows it to play both roles. That is, I will argue for a unitary conception of Aristotelian matter. 2. The case for bifurcationism The case for bifurcationism consists in two powerful arguments for the claim that no single thing could play both the functional roles Aristotle assigns to “matter.” The first argument appeals to Aristotle’s distinction between substantial change and mere alteration, the second to Aristotle’s claim that the matter of living creatures is essentially ensouled. 2A. Substantial change and mere alteration ItisimportantforAristotle—indeed,itispartandparcelofhisessentialism— that there be a firm and non-interest-relative distinction between the gen- eration or destruction of a substance and a mere alteration. He articulates this distinction in On Generation and Corruption A4: 3ButcomparePhys. A7.190b3–5,wheretheseed issaidtobethepreexistingsubstrate from which plants and animals come to be. (In the case of humans, the seed (sperma) is the semen, not the menstrual fluid.) 3 ...there is alteration when the substrate is perceptible and per- sists, but changes in its own properties, the properties in question being either contraries or intermediates. The body, e.g., although persisting as the same body, is now healthy and now ill; and the bronze is now spherical and at another time angular, and yet re- mains the same bronze. But when nothing perceptible persists in itsidentityasasubstrate, andthethingchangesasawhole(when e.g. the seed as a whole is converted into blood, or water into air, or air as a whole into water), such an occurrence is a generation of one substance and a destruction of the other...(319b10–17) On this account, the formation of a statue out of a lump of bronze is not re- ally a substantial change, but merely an alteration in an accidental property of the bronze (its shape). Aristotle’s examples of statues and so forth are meant to be analogies to help one understand cases of genuine substantial change (Met. H2.1043a4–5, Phys. A7.191a7–12). In a genuine substantial change, nothing—or, at least, nothing perceptible—persists. So it seems that the preexisting substrate could not possibly be the subject of which the form of the generated substance is predicated. (Strictly speaking, of course, the GC account of substantial change only forbids a perceptible persisting sub- strate. Keep that in mind for later. Note, however, that whenever Aristotle says what the matter of a substance is, it’s always something perceptible: menstrual fluid, flesh and bones, the organic body.) 2B. Essentially enformed matter In some passages, Aristotle identifies the subject of which a human being’s form (or soul) is predicated as the “organic” body (Met. Z11.1037a6).4 In other passages, he points to the body’s uniform tissues, flesh and bones (Z11.1036b4–6). Itdoesn’tmuchmatter,becauseAristotleseemstoholdthat neither of these can exist when not enformed by soul. When the body and its tissues and organs are no longer enformed by soul, they are body, organs, andtissuesonlyhomonymously(Meteor. ∆12.390a10–15,GAA19.726b21–3, 4It is often assumed that by “organic” Aristotle means “having organs,” but Stephen Everson 1997 has shown that (cid:230)rganik(cid:236)n always has the sense “instrumental” elsewhere and should probably be taken in the same sense here. Cf. De An. B4.415b18–19, where Aristotle describes the natural bodies of plants and animals as “organs” (instruments) of soul, and GA A1.716a25. 4 B1.734b24–7, PA A1.640b34–641a5, DA B1.412b18–22, Met. Z10.1035b23– 5). That is, they have only a name in common with the living body, organs, and tissues, not a definition (Cat. 1.1a1–3). So the body and its tissues, which Aristotle names as the subject of which the human being’s form is predicated, cannot possibly exist before the human being itself (or at least the nascent human being, the embryo) and therefore cannot play the role of substrate of the human being’s generation. (This problem was pointed out forcefully by Ackrill 1972/3 and is often called “Ackrill’s problem.”) 2C. Constitutive and preexisting matter In the teeth of these arguments, many commentators have concluded that there simply isn’t anything in Aristotle’s ontology that can play both the roles he assigns to matter, and that accordingly Aristotle’s word “matter” has two quite different senses, which we can disambiguate as constitutive matter and preexisting matter.5 Constitutive matter is the subject of which form is predicated: for instance, the living body or the flesh and bones. Preexisting matter is the preexisting substrate of substantial change: for instance, the menstrual fluid. The arguments just canvassed appear to show that the constitutive matter of a genuine substance must be distinct from its preexisting matter. 3. Two problems with bifurcationism Persuasiveastheseargumentsare,Idon’tthinkthatbifurcationismistenable as a reading of Aristotle. There are two serious problems with it, which I will detail in this section. Then, in section 4, I will present a unitarian view of matter and show where the arguments for bifurcationism go wrong. 3A. Aristotle doesn’t make the distinction The first problem is that Aristotle doesn’t explicitly make the distinction between constitutive and preexisting matter anywhere in the corpus. Since Aristotle is not one to leave it as an exercise to the reader to figure out that something is “said in many ways,” the bifurcationist must take him to have 5See Kosman 1987:362, 378, Charlton 1970:73–7, Jones 1974:495, 500 n. 22, Gill 1989, Lewis 1991:256–8, Dancy 1973:698. The precise terminology varies. 5 conflated the two notions of matter in his own thinking, or at least never to have clearly distinguished them. Proximate and remote matter Aristotle does make some distinctions that might be thought to line up with the distinction between constitutive and preexisting matter. One is the distinction between remote and proximate matter (Met. H4.1044a15–25, b1–3, ∆6.1016a19–24,∆24.1023a25–29, Θ7.1049a21–7; cf. H6.1045b17–20, Λ3.1070a20).6 The relation “x is the remote matter of y” is just the ances- tral of the relation “x is the proximate matter of y”; that is, the former is to the latter as “x is the ancestor of y” is to “x is the parent of y.” Thus, for example, the sweet is the remote matter of phlegm, because it is the proximate matter of fat, which is in turn the proximate matter of phlegm (H4.1044a20–22). Presumably, the elements (earth, air, fire, and water) are the remote matter of a living organism (cf. PA B1), and the elements, at least, can preexist the organism. Moreover, it is clear from Aristotle’s discus- sion of form-matter predication at Met. H6.1045b17–19 that the constitutive matter, of which form is predicated, must be proximate matter. Might we then identify the organism’s preexisting matter (the substrate for its gener- ation) with its remote matter? This would give textual legitimacy to the posited distinction between preexisting and constitutive matter. Tempting as it is, this approach won’t work. The preexisting matter for an F must be potentially an F (GC A3.317b16–18, Met. Λ2.1069b15–20). But on Aristotle’s view, it is only the proximate matter of an F, and not the remote matter, that is potentially an F. For example, it is bronze, the proximatematterofastatue,thatispotentiallythestatue. Earth,theremote matter of a statue, is only potentially bronze—not potentially a statue (Met. Θ7.1049a17–18). So the preexisting matter cannot be identified with the remote matter. In support of this point, note that there are two plausible candidates for the proximate matter of a human being: the menstrual fluid or katam(cid:160)nia, which Aristotle names as the preexisting substrate of generation, and the human body, which he names as the matter of which the human form is predicated. Both of these are potentially human beings (GA B1.734b35–6, 6The terms “proximate” and “remote” are Irwin’s (1988:241). Aristotle uses a va- riety of words for “proximate” matter: (cid:210)dion (H4.1044b3), o˚ke—a (H4.1044a18), (cid:226)sq(cid:136)th (H6.1045b18), and teleuta—a (Λ3.1070a20). 6 B4.740b19–20, DA B1), so neither can be remote matter. So the distinction between proximate and remote matter is simply orthogonal to the bifurca- tionist’s distinction between preexisting and constitutive matter. Substrate as matter and substrate as matter + privation Alternatively, we might try to find the distinction between preexisting and constitutivematterinAristotle’sobservationthatthesubstrateofsubstantial change is “one in number, but two in form” (Phys. A7.190b23–5). On the one hand, the substrate is the unshaped bronze, which does not persist when the bronze becomes shaped; on the other hand, it is the bronze which persists in the statue. Might we identify the constitutive matter with the bronze and the preexisting matter with the unshaped bronze, that is, the bronze + the privation of statue-shape? No. Theproposalseemsplausibleintheartifactualcase, butbreaksdown when we consider the generation of genuine substances. On this proposal, the menstrual fluid—the preexisting matter of a human being—would have to be the human’s constitutive matter as qualified by the privation of soul. But the constitutive matter of a human is the organic body, or perhaps the flesh and bones (that’s what gets the bifurcationist ball rolling in the first place). And Aristotle is quite explicit that these cannot exist at all qualified by the privation of soul (§2B, above). So the distinction between substrate as matter and substrate as matter + privation doesn’t seem to match up with the bifurcationist’s distinction, either. Was Aristotle confused? It appears, then, that the bifurcationist is invoking a distinction that appears nowhere in the actual Aristotelian text. Anyone who has spent much time reading Aristotle will agree that it is exceedingly unlikely that he had the distinction in mind but just did not bother to make it explicit. So the bifur- cationist is committed to saying that Aristotle failed to grasp a distinction to which he is committed by his own theory, and as a result has no resources for avoiding equivocation in his talk about matter. To get an idea of just how uncharitable this reading would be, con- sider Aristotle’s argument for the substantiality of matter in Metaphysics H1.1042a32-b3. Though the details are puzzling, the form of the argument seems to be something like this: 7 All substrate is substance. Matter is substrate in substantial changes. Matter is substance. The bifurcationist will have to say that this argument equivocates. For “sub- strate” in the second premise must mean “substrate of change.” But if we read “substrate” in the first premise that way, then we must say that Aristo- tle has never given us any argument for this premise.7 On the other hand, if we read “substrate” in the first premise as “(ultimate) substrate of predica- tion,” then the first premise is just the familiar “ultimate substrate” criterion for substance that Aristotle first proposes in the Categories and reiterates at several points in the Metaphysics (∆8.1017b13–14, Z3.1028b36–1029a2, Z13.1038b15). The obvious conclusion is that Aristotle is conflating “sub- strate of substantial change” with “substrate (subject) of predication,” rely- ing on the latter reading for the plausibility of his major premise, the former for the plausibility of his minor premise. It is not impossible that Aristotle was confused in this way. But we ought to favor a more charitable interpretation, if one can be found.8 3B. The substrate for substantial change persists On the bifurcationist account, there is no persisting matter in substantial change. The preexisting matter (for instance, the menstrual blood) is de- stroyed or “used up,” and the constitutive matter (for instance, the organic body) comes into being. Indeed, the bifurcation is motivated, in large part, by Aristotle’s claim in GC A4 that when something perceptible persists as 7SocomplainsBostock1994:252. ItispossiblethatAristotleishererelyingonhisclaim in Cat. 5.4a10–b4 that “It seems most distinctive of substance that what is numerically one and the same is able to receive contraries.” But if this is the argument, it is not one we have been prepared for by anything in Z. 8Perhapsthebifurcationistcouldofferthefollowingalternativereadingoftheargument. The first premise, “all substrate is substance,” implies both “all potential substrates are potentially substance” and “all actual substrates are actually substance.” The second premise can be read “the pre-existing matter in a substantial change is potentially sub- strate (to the form).” Then it can be validly concluded that “the pre-existing matter in a substantial change is potentially substance.” Since “is” for Aristotle can have the sense of either potential or actual being (compare the two readings of “is a jogger”), this conclusion is one possible meaning of “matter is substance.” Moreover, it comports well withAristotle’sconclusionatthebeginningofH2thatmatteristhesubstancethatexists potentially. (I am indebted here to conversations with Alan Code.) 8 substrate, the change is a mere alteration, not a genuine substantial change (§2A, above). Recalcitrant texts A serious problem with this view is that Aristotle claims explicitly that the substrate of substantial generation persists in the generated substance. Aris- totle’sdefinitionofmatterinthePhysics is“...theprimarysubstrateofeach thing, from which it comes to be, and which is present in it ((cid:226)nup(cid:136)rqontoc), not accidentally” (A9.192a31–2). And lest it be thought that the Physics definition reflects an earlier and more primitive conception of matter, there are these passages from the Metaphysics: Therefore, as we say, it is impossible that anything should be produced if there were nothing before. Obviously then some part of the result will preexist of necessity; for the matter is a part; for this is present in the thing ((cid:226)nup(cid:136)rqei)9 and it is this that becomes something. (Z7.1032b30–1033a1) ...there must be something underlying which changes into the contrary state; for the contraries do not change. Further, some- thing persists (˝pomŁnei), but the contrary does not persist; there is, then, some third thing besides the contraries, viz. the matter. (Λ1,2.1069b6–9) All of these passages clearly state that the preexisting matter persists in a substantial change. It is open to the bifurcationist to claim that the passages asserting the persistenceofmatterdonotexpressAristotle’sconsideredview. MaryLouise Gill holds, for instance, that the model of substantial change presented in the Physics and book Z of the Metaphysics is replaced by a new model in Metaphysics H6 and Θ7.10 But given that Aristotle does not explicitly draw the distinction between preexisting and constitutive matter—not even in the texts that are supposed to present his mature view—our justification for 9Here I depart slightly from Ross, who renders (cid:226)nup(cid:136)rqei “is present in the process.” Note that the same verb is used in the passage from Phys. A9 just quoted. 10Gill 1989:6–11. Gill is neutral about whether the presence of these two models of change in the Metaphysics reflects an actual change in Aristotle’s thinking or a dialectical strategy. 9 invoking the distinction can only be its usefulness in making sense of Aris- totle’s text. So throwing away texts to save the distinction is like throwing away an election in order to raise more funds for the campaign. Each text that is inconsistent with the distinction weakens the case for attributing it to Aristotle in the first place.11 Trifurcation? Gill has proposed patching up the bifurcationist account by finding in Aris- totle a third kind of matter, “generic matter,” which does persist through substantial change, but “only as a set of properties that modify the higher construct” (1989:164). Because generic matter survives only as property, not as substrate or subject, it does not threaten to make substantial change look like a mere alteration of the material substrate: “...the lower matter is not a definite subject to which the functions belong but instead a set of properties accidental to the higher object...” (167). Jennifer Whiting has offered a similar account of the persisting matter, with similar motivation (1992:84). But these maneuvers don’t really solve the fundamental problems facing bifurcationism. One still needs to explain away texts in which matter is said to persist as substrate or subject (hence not property) and as substance (hence not accident)—for instance, Metaphysics H1: Butclearlymatteralsoissubstance; forinalltheoppositechanges that occur there is something which underlies the changes, e.g. in respect of place that which is now here and again elsewhere, and in respect of increase that which is now of one size and again less or greater, and in respect of alteration that which is now healthy and again diseased; and similarly in respect of substance there is something that is now being generated and again being de- stroyed, and now underlies the process as a “this” (˝poke—menon –c t(cid:236)de ti) and again underlies it in respect of a privation of positive character (˝poke—menon –c kat(cid:128) stŁrhsin). (1042a32-b3) On Gill’s view, this text reflects the more primitive model of substantial change Aristotle aims to replace. But it is only her commitment to bifurca- tionism that makes this model look primitive. Apart from this commitment, 11Still, Gill’s approach might be justified if it were the only way of attributing a philo- sophically satisfactory position to Aristotle. I will argue below that it is not. 10

Description:
The first is that a substance's matter is the substrate (Õpoke–menon) of its generation: virtue of which a thing is called a this, and thirdly in the sense.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.